The Role of Emotion in Believable Agents. Joseph Bates. Carnegie Mellon University

Similar documents
The Nature of Characters in Interactive Worlds. Joseph Bates. Carnegie Mellon University. Abstract

Integrating Reactivity, Goals, and Emotion. in a Broad Agent. Joseph Bates A. Bryan Loyall W. Scott Reilly. May School of Computer Science

An Architecture for. Action, Emotion, and Social Behavior. School of Computer Science, Carnegie Mellon University. Pittsburgh, PA 15213, USA

Development of extemporaneous performance by synthetic actors in the rehearsal process

Walt Stanchfield 03 Notes from Walt Stanchfield s Disney Drawing Classes

The Yamaha Corporation

Comparison, Categorization, and Metaphor Comprehension

Computer Coordination With Popular Music: A New Research Agenda 1

Story Visualization Techniques for Interactive Drama

FINAL PROJECT: PERFORMANCE ARTS AND AI

A Guide to Paradigm Shifting

MIMes and MeRMAids: On the possibility of computeraided interpretation

MAKING INTERACTIVE GUIDES MORE ATTRACTIVE

Reflections on the digital television future

Environment Expression: Expressing Emotions through Cameras, Lights and Music

Journal of Field Robotics. Instructions to Authors

Empirical Evaluation of Animated Agents In a Multi-Modal E-Retail Application

Imitating the Human Form: Four Kinds of Anthropomorphic Form Carl DiSalvo 1 Francine Gemperle 2 Jodi Forlizzi 1, 3

Exploring Choreographers Conceptions of Motion Capture for Full Body Interaction

days of Saussure. For the most, it seems, Saussure has rightly sunk into

Visual Literacy and Design Principles

ENVIRONMENTAL EXPERIENCE: Beyond Aesthetic Subjectivism and Objectivism

The Effects of Web Site Aesthetics and Shopping Task on Consumer Online Purchasing Behavior

High School Photography 1 Curriculum Essentials Document

The Matched Delay Technique: Wentai Liu, Mark Clements, Ralph Cavin III. North Carolina State University. (919) (ph)

Second Grade: National Visual Arts Core Standards

Mise en scène Short Film Project Name:

Relative frequency. I Frames P Frames B Frames No. of cells

Social Interaction based Musical Environment

This full text version, available on TeesRep, is the post-print (final version prior to publication) of:

Is there a Future for AI without Representation?

Destination Imagination

Department of Computer Science, Cornell University. fkatej, hopkik, Contact Info: Abstract:

RESPONDING TO ART: History and Culture

The Fox News Eect:Media Bias and Voting S. DellaVigna and E. Kaplan (2007)

sustainability and quality

2 nd Grade Visual Arts Curriculum Essentials Document

Incommensurability and Partial Reference

Meaning Machines CS 672 Deictic Representations (3) Matthew Stone THE VILLAGE


22/9/2013. Acknowledgement. Outline of the Lecture. What is an Agent? EH2750 Computer Applications in Power Systems, Advanced Course. output.

Concept of ELFi Educational program. Android + LEGO

GLOSSARY for National Core Arts: Visual Arts STANDARDS

Children s Book Committee Review Guidelines

A STEP-BY-STEP PROCESS FOR READING AND WRITING CRITICALLY. James Bartell

Articulation * Catherine Schmidt-Jones. 1 What is Articulation? 2 Performing Articulations

Object Oriented Learning in Art Museums Patterson Williams Roundtable Reports, Vol. 7, No. 2 (1982),

Technology and the distribution of music *

Browsing News and Talk Video on a Consumer Electronics Platform Using Face Detection

Brain.fm Theory & Process

Situated actions. Plans are represetitntiom of nction. Plans are representations of action

Genre, Style, Context

Evaluating Interactive Music Systems: An HCI Approach

A New Approach to the Paradox of Fiction Pete Faulconbridge

Exhibits. Open House. NHK STRL Open House Entrance. Smart Production. Open House 2018 Exhibits

Harris Wiseman, The Myth of the Moral Brain: The Limits of Moral Enhancement (Cambridge, MA and London: The MIT Press, 2016), 340 pp.

Ideograms in Polyscopic Modeling

It is Not Always Black and White. Alfred Hitchcock was in Hollywood more or less since His name, his profile, and

Is Genetic Epistemology of Any Interest for Semiotics?

Analysis of local and global timing and pitch change in ordinary

Human beings argue: To justify what they do and think, both to themselves and to their audience. To possibly solve problems and make decisions

PERFORMANCE CATEGORY

Psychology of film: Psychology of film: Mise-en-scene Page 1. Psychology of film: Mise-en-scene Page 2

The Discussion about Truth Viewpoint and its Significance on the View of Broad-Spectrum Philosophy

More please! More! More! Save the Whales, Screw the Shrimp Summary. In Joy Williams essay Save the Whales, Screw the Shrimp, published in 2001, she

Roald Dahl s Influence On Today s Society. Elijah Espinoza. Mr. Mark Schuerer. 4th Hour

PHL 317K 1 Fall 2017 Overview of Weeks 1 5

My work comes out of being frustrated about the human condition. And about how people refuse to understand other people

Is composition a mode of performing? Questioning musical meaning

Policy on the syndication of BBC on-demand content

PREPARATION (0-30 POINTS PER SONG) (Visual Plan)

Big Idea 1: Artists manipulate materials and ideas to create an aesthetic object, act, or event. Essential Question: What is art and how is it made?

The Conflict Within. A Guide to Personal and Classroom Management By Michael Edgar Myers

Musical Meaning and String Quartets

Lian Loke and Toni Robertson (eds) ISBN:

Summer Assignment. B. Research. Suggested Order of Completion. AP Art History Sister Lisa Perkowski

Philosophy of Science: The Pragmatic Alternative April 2017 Center for Philosophy of Science University of Pittsburgh ABSTRACTS

Edge Level A Unit 1 Cluster 1 The Experiment

SUMMARY BOETHIUS AND THE PROBLEM OF UNIVERSALS

CHAPTER I INTRODUCTION

Audience/Performer Chemistry

The Teaching Method of Creative Education

Student Performance Q&A:

Reference: Chapter 6 of Thomas Caldwell s Film Analysis Handbook.

EXAMPLE: (Liechtenstein 169) or (Liechtenstein )

PMEA Model Curriculum Framework Strand: Music Technology PA Big Ideas and National Standards Artistic Processes

Coping Skills Seminars

Supporting Random Access on Real-time. Retrieval of Digital Continuous Media. Jonathan C.L. Liu, David H.C. Du and James A.

AESTHETICS. Key Terms

OCTAVE C 3 D 3 E 3 F 3 G 3 A 3 B 3 C 4 D 4 E 4 F 4 G 4 A 4 B 4 C 5 D 5 E 5 F 5 G 5 A 5 B 5. Middle-C A-440

NSF/ARPA Science and Technology Center for Computer Graphics and Scientific Visualization

WHY SWITCH TO A SYSTEM?

A2 Art Share Supporting Materials

Years 9 and 10 standard elaborations Australian Curriculum: Drama

Vuzik: Music Visualization and Creation on an Interactive Surface

FRAMES PER MULTIFRAME SLOTS PER TDD - FRAME

6Harmonics. 6Harmonics Inc. is pleased to submit the enclosed comments to Industry Canada s Gazette Notice SMSE

Logisim: A graphical system for logic circuit design and simulation

Sound visualization through a swarm of fireflies

Incandescent Diffusers Deflectors Photo boxes

Transcription:

The Role of Emotion in Believable Agents Joseph Bates April 1994 CMU-CS-94-136 School of Computer Science Carnegie Mellon University Pittsburgh, PA 15213 To appear in Communications of the ACM, Special Issue on Agents, July 1994. Abstract Articial intelligence researchers attempting to create engaging, apparently living creatures may nd important insight in the work of artists who have explored the idea of believable character. In particular, appropriately timed and clearly expressed emotion is a central requirement for believable characters. We discuss these ideas and suggest how they may apply to believable interactive characters, which we call \believable agents." This work was supported in part by Fujitsu Laboratories and Mitsubishi Electric Research Laboratories. The views and conclusions contained in this document are those of the authors and should not be interpreted as representing the ocial policies, either expressed or implied, of any other parties.

Keywords: articial intelligence, emotion, believable agents, art, animation, believable characters.

1 BELIEVABILITY 1 1 Believability There is a notion in the Arts of \believable character." It does not mean an honest or reliable character, but one that provides the illusion of life, and thus permits the audience's suspension of disbelief. The idea of believability has long been studied and explored in literature, theater, lm, radio drama, and other media. Traditional character animators are among those artists who have sought to create believable characters, and the Disney animators of the 1930's made great strides toward this goal. The rst page of the enormous classic reference work on Disney animation (Thomas and Johnston, 1981) begins with these words: \Disney animation makes audiences really believe in ::: characters, whose adventures and misfortunes make people laugh and even cry. There is a special ingredient in our type of animation that produces drawings that appear to think and make decisions and act of their own volition it is what creates the illusion of life." Many articial intelligence researchers have long wished to build robots, and their cousins called \agents," that seem to think, feel, and live. These are creatures with whom you'd want to share some of your life: as with a companion, or a social pet. For instance, in his 1985 American Association of Articial Intelligence Presidential Address (Bledsoe, 1986), Woody Bledsoe told of his continuing dream to build a computer friend. He spoke of the \excitement of seeing a machine act like a human being, at least in many ways," of building a machine that could \understand, act autonomously, think, learn, enjoy, hate" and which \liked to walk and play Ping- Pong, especially with me." Woody Bledsoe is hardly alone. Further reading on the dreams of animators and AI researchers nds both groups speaking of thinking, feeling, living creatures, of creating at least the illusion of life, of building apparently autonomous entities that people, especially the creators, would genuinely care about. Both groups also speak of achieving these dreams by nding the essence of the creatures to be simulated, and reconstructing that essence in the medium of the artist's or scientist's choice. As AI researchers tried to nd these essential qualities of humanity, they gravitated toward reasoning, problem solving, learning via concept formation, and other qualities apparently central to the capacitywecallintelligence. Perhaps this happened because these qualities are characteristic of the idealized scientist, and thus are valued by the communities of which the researchers were part. Artists, in particular the character animators, also tried to understand and express the essence of humanity in their constructions. Character animators had to be especially analytic, because they had to produce human life from nothing more than

2 EMOTION IN BELIEVABLE CHARACTERS 2 individual, hand-drawn, at-shaded line drawings, moved frame by frame, without being able to rely on a human actor to portray thecharacter. The practical requirement of producing hundreds of thousands of these drawings forced animators to use extremely simple, non-realistic imagery, and to seek and abstract precisely that which was crucial. It can be argued that while scientists may have more eectively recreated scientists, it is the artists who have come closest to understanding and perhaps capturing the essence of humanity that Bledsoe, and other AI researchers, ultimately seek. If this is true, then the results of artistic inquiry, especially the insights into character animation such as those expressed in The Illusion of Life(Thomas and Johnston, 1981) and elsewhere (Jones, 1989 Lasseter, 1987), may provide key information for building computational models of believable interactive characters. We call these constructions \believable agents." Their development is one of my group's research goals in the Oz project(bates, 1992). 2 Emotion in Believable Characters The qualities the animators judged important are not identical to those that AI researchers emphasized, though there is some overlap. One quality the animators felt was of the greatest signicance in characters was appropriately timed and clearly expressed emotion. Quoting again from Thomas and Johnston, two of Disney's Nine Old Men (Thomas and Johnston, 1981): \From the earliest days, it has been the portrayal of emotions that has given the Disney characters the illusion of life." The apparent desires of a character, and the way the character feels about what happens in the world with respect to those desires, are what make us care about that character. If the character does not react emotionally to events, if they don't care, then neither will we. The emotionless character is lifeless, as a machine. According to Thomas and Johnston, properly portraying the emotional reactions of a character requires the animator to remember several key points: 1. The emotional state of the character must be clearly dened. The animator needs to know this state at each moment, so that the viewer will be able to attribute denite emotional status to the character as well. 2. The thought process reveals the feeling. Since Disney technique claims that action shows the thought processes, viewers must see the emotions in what the character does as its thinking is inuenced by its clearly dened emotional state.

3 USING EMOTION TO CONSTRUCT BELIEVABLE AGENTS 3 Figure 1: The Woggles in Edge of Intention 3. Accentuate the emotion. Use time wisely to establish the emotion, to convey it to viewers, and to let them savor the situation. People often cannot grasp emotional state (and other situations) immediately. Thus, believable characters depend on appropriate use of a variety of mechanisms to convey emotion, such as fore-shadowing the emotion, exaggerating it, and toning down other simultaneous action to get the main point across. Of course, there is far more to be said about emotion in believable characters, but let us see where these comments might lead us in thinking about computational models for believable agents. In particular, we'll look briey at how the Oz group attempted to build on animation criteria, such as the signicance of emotion, and at some of the results of trying to construct believable agents in this way. 3 Using Emotion to Construct Believable Agents One of the eorts of the Oz project in 1992 was to build a small simulated world containing several realtime, interactive, self-animating creatures based on the principles of traditional character animation. We constructed an art work, called \Edge of Intention", that was rst shown at the AAAI-92 AI-based Arts Exhibition and then subsequently at SIGGRAPH-93, at Ars Electronica '93, and in the Boston Computer Museum. Figure 1 shows an image of three of these self-animating creatures, called \Woggles," posing for the camera. The three particular creatures are named Shrimp, Bear, and Wolf. The Disney suggestions on portrayal of emotions do not tell us much about the representations of emotion inside an agent. There may be many computational models consistent with the appearance of a denite emotional state, and with the other

3 USING EMOTION TO CONSTRUCT BELIEVABLE AGENTS 4 suggestions. In particular, there is no requirement that the emotional state be represented in any obvious way within the agent, or within the agent/world system. In building the Woggles, wechose to develop a goal-directed, behavior-based architecture for action (Loyall and Bates, 1993 Brooks, 1986 Maes, 1989), and to couple it to a distinct component for generating, representing, and expressing emotion based on the work of Ortony, Collins, and Clore (OCC) (Ortony et al., 1988 Bates et al., 1992). The action system does no planning and almost no world modeling, but it does use a minimalist conception of goals to manipulate a dynamically changing set of behaviors. These goals, and the agent's appraisals of events with respect to the goals, are key to producing a clearly dened emotional state in the creature. Our choices to make emotions explicit and to allow composition of behaviors through goals were intended to make it easy to build characters with specic personalities, while maintaining the robustness of robots that use minimal representation. Building on the OCC theory of emotion gives us creatures with denite emotional reactions to events. A simple example is a Woggle creating an analog of anger when it both experiences an important goal failure and judges that the failure was caused by another Woggle. It often occurs, however, thatmany emotions of various intensities exist simultaneously. Part of our work has been in nding ways to combine these togetoneortwo primary overall emotions of adequate clarity to satisfy maxim 1. We are not sure if our solutions are adequate (Reilly and Bates, 1992), and we are continuing to explore this problem. According to the second maxim, a creature's emotional state must change its thought processes so that the emotional state is visible in its actions. In the Woggles, each emotion was mapped in a personality specic way toabehavioral feature. For instance, the \fear" emotion mapped to the \alarmed" feature in Shrimp, but to the \aggressive" feature in Wolf. These features had both local and systemic eects on the action generating components of the architecture. We attempted to build behaviors so that any combination of features would produce action that conveyed those features. Behavioral features were intended as an abstraction mechanism, to let us build a library of modular behaviors that later could be used in any character. However, as we constructed individual Woggles from these modules, we found that we wanted emotion to aect action in very ad hoc ways that seemed to depend on breaking down the abstraction barriers frequently. There is debate within the Oz group about whether this is an essential quality ofcharacters, or whether it will be possible to nd durable abstractions in the mapping from emotion to action. An argument against abstraction comes from our experience with Shrimp. Due to a programming error, Shrimp occasionally peppers his ongoing behavior with what seems to be a nervous tick causing him repeatedly to hit his head against the ground. This attracts people's attention immediately, but to our surprise they build psycho-

4 CONCLUSION 5 logical theories, always incorrect, about Shrimp's mental state and seem to nd him much more interesting and alive forhaving this behavior. Their reaction appears consistent with what Chuck Jones, famous for his success animating Bugs Bunny and other Warner Brothers characters, says was his key insight into animation. As an eight year old he had a cat named Johnson who liked to eat grapefruit and then wear the eaten rind on his head. Jones says he discovered that it is the oddity, the quirk, that gives personality toacharacter, and it is personality thatgives life. If so, our architectures must support quirks, and this may mean they need to allow regularities, such as are expressed in abstraction barriers, to be broken. Finally, let us consider the third maxim. We took care to design an architecture that provided Woggles with strong internal emotional states. However, we did not use the animation techniques of exaggeration, anticipation, or staging nearly to the extent necessary to make those emotions quickly recognizable. An example of insucient exaggeration was the moping behavior. A moping Woggle directly expresses sadness by decreasing its muscle tone, decreasing the length of its jumps, and slowing the timing of its actions. The creator of the behavior reported that he \started with what I thought would be a reasonable looking behavior, but it wasn't clear enough so I tripled and then doubled again [the relevant parameters] and still only got a mope that people recognize when it is pointed out to them." Anticipation denotes broadcasting in advance that a certain action is about to occur, to let people prepare to see it. This is necessary because realistic timing causes events to happen quickly, and people will miss them unless they are experienced watchers. An analogy is that people watching an unfamiliar sport often seem unable to see what is happening until they learn to predict likely near future events. A classic example of anticipation in animation occurs when a character rears back in preparation for a rapid forward motion. Strictly speaking, this is unrealistic, but it is essential for people to grasp the meaning in motion. Staging is used in theater and animation to refer to controlling the action of several characters in time and space to make sure the main point of a situation is conveyed. At each moment in \Edge of Intention," several Woggles are often moving, jumping, and gesturing socially. This makes it very dicult for people interacting with the creatures to stay aware of what is happening. While this simultaneous action may be realistic, unless the goal is specically to produce confusion in the user, it is not helpful in producing the subjective feeling of realism. 4 Conclusion We've talked about the idea of believable agents, by which we mean an interactive analog of the believable characters discussed in the Arts. We've tried to argue that these artists hold some of the same central goals as AI researchers, and that their

4 CONCLUSION 6 insights could be important as we try to build engaging, apparently living creatures. Such creatures, besides sparking the interest of AI researchers and artists, may serve as a component of new user interfaces for the broad human population. Chuck Jones, describing animation at Warner Brothers (Jones, 1989), said: \Believability. That is what we were striving for... belief in the life of the characters. That, after all, is the dictionary denition and meaning of the word `animation': to invoke life." Emotion is one of the primary means to achieve this believability, this illusion of life, because it helps us know that characters really care about what happens in the world, that they truly have desires. In contrast, the ghting characters of current video games show almost no reaction to the tremendous violence that engulfs them. Such showing of reaction is a key to making characters believable and engaging, which is perhaps why these characters engender no concern they are merely abstract symbols of action. As we've mentioned and implied several times, the \illusion of life" refers to the conveyance of a strong subjective sense of realism. One might wish to distinguish this from a notion of genuine life, which would refer to entities that \really are" alive, as opposed to merely seeming so. Just what to make ofsuch a distinction is, of course, the subject of deep debate. Turing's test, Dennett's \intensional stance" (Dennett, 1987), and many other ideas of substance try to get at this issue. We would note here that whatever one makes of the fundamental philosophical concern, there remains a practical concern of constructing agents of increasing degrees of believability in the short term. Indeed, sucient success in this regard may alter or eliminate the philosophical debate, as has happened before where practice meets theory. In any case, it is our view that believability will not arise from copying reality. Artists use reality in the service of realism, for example by carefully studying nature, but they do not elevate it above their fundamental goal. Mimicking reality is a method, to be used when but only when appropriate, to convey a strong subjective sense of realism. It is art which must lead the charge here. Believability places a variety of demands on an interactive character. These include the appearance of reactivity, goals, emotions, and situated social competence, among others. The emphasis in \alternative AI" on reactivity could be seen as choosing one of the believability requirements and elevating it to a position of importance, while downgrading other qualities, such as those related to our idealized view of intelligence. We oer the thought that researchers could make this same methodological move with other requirements, such as emotion or personality, that artists tell us are needed to present the convincing, persistent, illusion of life.

5 ACKNOWLEDGMENTS 7 5 Acknowledgments We gratefully acknowledge research support for the Oz project provided by Fujitsu Laboratories and Mitsubishi Electric Research Laboratories. References Bates, J. (1992). Virtual reality, art, and entertainment. PRESENCE: Teleoperators and Virtual Environments, 1(1):133{138. Bates, J., Loyall, A. B., and Reilly, W. S. (1992). An architecture for action, emotion, and social behavior. In Proceedings of the Fourth European Workshop on Modeling Autonomous Agents in a Multi-Agent World, S.Martino al Cimino, Italy. Bledsoe, W. (1986). I had a dream: AAAI presidential address. AI Magazine, 7(1):57{ 61. Brooks, R. (1986). A robust layered control system for a mobile robot. IEEE Journal of Robotics and Automation, RA-2:14{23. Dennett, D. (1987). The Intentional Stance. The MIT Press, Cambridge, MA. Jones, C. (1989). Chuck Amuck: the Life and Times of an Animated Cartoonist. Farrar, Straus & Giroux, New York. Lasseter, J. (1987). Principles of traditional animation applied to 3D computer animation. In Proceedings of SIGGRAPH '87, pages 35{44. Association for Computing Machinery. Loyall, A. B. and Bates, J. (1993). Real-time control of animated broad agents. In Proceedings of the Fifteenth Annual Conference of the Cognitive Science Society, Boulder, CO. Maes, P. (1989). How to do the right thing. Connection Science, 1(3):291{323. Ortony, A., Clore, G., and Collins, A. (1988). The Cognitive Structure of Emotions. Cambridge University Press. Reilly, W. S. and Bates, J. (1992). Building emotional agents. Technical Report CMU- CS-92-143, School of Computer Science, Carnegie Mellon University, Pittsburgh, PA. Thomas, F. and Johnston, O. (1981). Disney Animation: The Illusion of Life. Abbeville Press, New York.