Cultural Specification and Temporalization An exposition of two basic problems regarding the development of ontologies in computer science

Similar documents
observation and conceptual interpretation

The Nature of Time. Humberto R. Maturana. November 27, 1995.

TROUBLING QUALITATIVE INQUIRY: ACCOUNTS AS DATA, AND AS PRODUCTS

Poznań, July Magdalena Zabielska

POST-KANTIAN AUTONOMIST AESTHETICS AS APPLIED ETHICS ETHICAL SUBSTRATUM OF PURIST LITERARY CRITICISM IN 20 TH CENTURY

Disputing about taste: Practices and perceptions of cultural hierarchy in the Netherlands van den Haak, M.A.

Truth and Method in Unification Thought: A Preparatory Analysis

The Observer Story: Heinz von Foerster s Heritage. Siegfried J. Schmidt 1. Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2011

ITU-T Y.4552/Y.2078 (02/2016) Application support models of the Internet of things

Interdepartmental Learning Outcomes

What do our appreciation of tonal music and tea roses, our acquisition of the concepts

PROJECT DESCRIPTION HERMA: AUTOMATED MODELLING OF HERMENEUTIC PROCESSES

Rhetorical question in political speeches

Heideggerian Ontology: A Philosophic Base for Arts and Humanties Education

(Ulrich Schloesser/ Humboldt-Universität zu Berlin)

Global culture, media culture and semiotics

Mensuration of a kiss The drawings of Jorinde Voigt

Philosophical foundations for a zigzag theory structure

SYSTEM-PURPOSE METHOD: THEORETICAL AND PRACTICAL ASPECTS Ramil Dursunov PhD in Law University of Fribourg, Faculty of Law ABSTRACT INTRODUCTION

Hans-Georg Gadamer, Truth and Method, 2d ed. transl. by Joel Weinsheimer and Donald G. Marshall (London : Sheed & Ward, 1989), pp [1960].

Back to Basics: Appreciating Appreciative Inquiry as Not Normal Science

The Body in its Hermeneutical Context

Advanced Statistical Steganalysis

High School Photography 1 Curriculum Essentials Document

Intersubjectivity and Language

ITU-T Y Functional framework and capabilities of the Internet of things

Kuhn Formalized. Christian Damböck Institute Vienna Circle University of Vienna

What counts as a convincing scientific argument? Are the standards for such evaluation

INTERNATIONAL CONFERENCE ON ENGINEERING DESIGN ICED 05 MELBOURNE, AUGUST 15-18, 2005 GENERAL DESIGN THEORY AND GENETIC EPISTEMOLOGY

PHD THESIS SUMMARY: Phenomenology and economics PETR ŠPECIÁN

Loughborough University Institutional Repository. This item was submitted to Loughborough University's Institutional Repository by the/an author.

foucault s archaeology science and transformation David Webb

Kuhn s Notion of Scientific Progress. Christian Damböck Institute Vienna Circle University of Vienna

Foundations in Data Semantics. Chapter 4

Do we use standards? The presence of ISO/TC-46 standards in the scientific literature ( )

Analysing and Mapping Cited Works: Citation Behaviour of Filipino Faculty and Researchers

Date Inferred Table 1. LCCN Dates

Ontological and historical responsibility. The condition of possibility

Metonymy Research in Cognitive Linguistics. LUO Rui-feng

Philosophy Department Expanded Course Descriptions Fall, 2007

Mixed Methods: In Search of a Paradigm

Conceptions and Context as a Fundament for the Representation of Knowledge Artifacts

Towards a Phenomenology of Development

Understanding the Cognitive Mechanisms Responsible for Interpretation of Idioms in Hindi-Urdu

Hermeneutics and Science Education: the Role of History of Science. Fabio Bevilacqua & Enrico Giannetto

Discussing some basic critique on Journal Impact Factors: revision of earlier comments

INTRODUCTION TO ONTOLOGY

Computer Coordination With Popular Music: A New Research Agenda 1

Between Meaning and Meaningfulness Understanding Anecdotal Music. Tatjana Böhme-Mehner

Visual Arts Colorado Sample Graduation Competencies and Evidence Outcomes

Semiotics of culture. Some general considerations

Philosophy of Science: The Pragmatic Alternative April 2017 Center for Philosophy of Science University of Pittsburgh ABSTRACTS

Adisa Imamović University of Tuzla

-A means of constructing ontologies for knowledge representation -In domain of Chinese Medicine and Orthodox Medicine

Bibliometric glossary

Jacek Surzyn University of Silesia Kant s Political Philosophy

SIGNS, SYMBOLS, AND MEANING DANIEL K. STEWMT*

Social Semiotic Techniques of Sense Making using Activity Theory

Bibliometric analysis of the field of folksonomy research

Reply to Stalnaker. Timothy Williamson. In Models and Reality, Robert Stalnaker responds to the tensions discerned in Modal Logic

SocioBrains THE INTEGRATED APPROACH TO THE STUDY OF ART

Culture and Art Criticism

Phenomenology Glossary

Lecture (0) Introduction

Part I I On the Methodology oj the Social Sciences

41. Cologne Mediaevistentagung September 10-14, Library. The. Spaces of Thought and Knowledge Systems

13 René Guénon. The Arts and their Traditional Conception. From the World Wisdom online library:

Ontology as a formal one. The language of ontology as the ontology itself: the zero-level language

Foucault's Archaeological method

Truth and Tropes. by Keith Lehrer and Joseph Tolliver

Panel: Starting from Elsewhere. Questions of Transnational, Cross-Cultural Historiography

By Maximus Monaheng Sefotho (PhD). 16 th June, 2015

Using Rules to support Case-Based Reasoning for harmonizing melodies

CHAPTER III RESEARCH METHOD

A Demonstration Sample for Poetry Education: Poem under the Light of 'Poetics of the Open Work'

Society for the Study of Symbolic Interaction SSSI/ASA 2002 Conference, Chicago

Representation and Discourse Analysis

Precombination vs. Precoordination

The Debate on Research in the Arts

Peircean concept of sign. How many concepts of normative sign are needed. How to clarify the meaning of the Peircean concept of sign?

Ontology Representation : design patterns and ontologies that make sense Hoekstra, R.J.

Research Projects on Rudolf Steiner'sWorldview

2 nd Grade Visual Arts Curriculum Essentials Document

UNIVERSITÀ DEGLI STUDI DI MILANO Facoltà di Studi Umanistici Dottorato di ricerca in Filosofia (XXVIII Ciclo)

An ecological approach to multimodal subjective music similarity perception

Metodo Author Guidelines

Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 2016, xiii+372pp., ISBN: Publishing offers us a critical re-examination of what the book is hence, the

ROLAND BARTHES ON WRITING: LITERATURE IS IN ESSENCE

Martin, Gottfried: Plato s doctrine of ideas [Platons Ideenlehre]. Berlin: Verlag Walter de Gruyter, 1973

Revitalising Old Thoughts: Class diagrams in light of the early Wittgenstein

Ontology as Meta-Theory: A Perspective

International Journal of Advancements in Research & Technology, Volume 4, Issue 11, November ISSN

i n t r o d u c t i o n

Forms and Causality in the Phaedo. Michael Wiitala

In basic science the percentage of authoritative references decreases as bibliographies become shorter

Bas C. van Fraassen, Scientific Representation: Paradoxes of Perspective, Oxford University Press, 2008.

What is Character? David Braun. University of Rochester. In "Demonstratives", David Kaplan argues that indexicals and other expressions have a

Incandescent Diffusers Deflectors Photo boxes

Marx, Gender, and Human Emancipation

Community and Media: a Weakness of Phenomenology?

Transcription:

Cultural Specification and Temporalization An exposition of two basic problems regarding the development of ontologies in computer science Klaus Wiegerling TU Kaiserslautern, Fachgebiet Philosophie and Universität Stuttgart, Institut für Philosophie, Center of Excellence 627: Nexus Spacial World Models for Mobile Context-Aware Applications Abstract: This paper discusses current conceptions of ontology in computer science focussing on cultural specification and temporalization. It is pointed out, first, that ontologies arrange the world, they do not represent it; second, that ontologies, except logical Formal Ontologies, can be developed within a cultural framework; third, Top Level and Domain Ontologies have to be complemented by Pragmatic Ontologies, if they are to be used in every-day life; fourth, Pragmatic Ontologies magnify the problem of temporalizing ontologies. Keywords: Pragmatic Ontology, temporalization, cultural specification, sense of historicity According to Janich the use of the philosophical term ontology in the information sciences is not problem-free, as this term does not necessarily provide guidance and help respectively to finding solutions to informatory and especially semantic problems. [1] Despite this, the term ontology far removed from the philosophical discourse - has taken root in the computer sciences and by serving as a pragmatic category can contribute somewhat to describing and solving problems. This, however, poses the problem that ontologies have time and again been viewed in a representational context. But ontologies do not represent the world, they arrange the world. That is, the world is not reproduced or mirrored by the use of ontologies in information sciences but is arranged within a specific, actually culturally specific framework. Even the widespread concept, that philosophical ontologies are descriptive and ontologies in computer science are prescriptive is not substantive, insofar as ontologies do not describe actually anything. Ontologies are dealing with universalia, transcendentalia and most abstract categories respectively and thus help in arranging things and facts. However, they do not reflect a concrete subject and therefore it does not make any sense to call them representations. Ontologies classify the world in patterns, which are generally based on the language and the specific cultural disposition. For example, many Indian family sociologists have changed databases from English to Indian languages, because the English classification of relationships does not capture the specific relationships in an Indian family, especially the important hierarchic structures between first-born and younger siblings. Thus ontologies arrange supposed representations and this process of being arranged in a certain way, referenced or put into a hierarchical order, gives these representations meaning.

Ontologies in computer sciences could serve quite a useful purpose by serving as structural framework. The fact that ontologies do not represent the world but arrange it is evident in Foucault s famous foreword to Les mots et les choses [2], where he quotes Borges by referring to his mentioning of a Chinese encyclopedia according to which animals are arranged by a peculiar taxonomy. This taxonomy distinguishes between animals which are owned by the Emperor, embalmed animals and animals which act as if they are mad. This shows that arranging animals can be done according to very different cultural preferences or classifications. Just think of the significance of cows in every-day life of Hindu India or the value of dogs in our culture compared to China. The taxonomy we apply is only one of many possible ones. Especially if an ontology is to be developed as a Common Ontology (actually an absurd term, there is simply no common ontology, because the term is part of a meta language) cultural specifications or rather cultural bias cannot be avoided. Any arrangement of things or - as in our case the arrangement of representations is a symbolic linking [3], which requires a common prior knowledge. The problem of this common prior knowledge was discussed by Rafael Capurro as early as 1986 in his book Hermeneutik und Fachinformation [4] for the field of data bank systems in view of classic hermeneutical considerations. The level of common prior knowledge which makes understanding and knowing possible had to be defined prior to creating an informatory system. But ontologies claim to integrate this level of common prior knowledge into the system itself. This applies especially to adaptive systems, which claim to have hermeneutic capabilities. That means these systems claim to cover spheres, which were considered belonging to the humanities and the human existence respectively. At present we distinguish between two main types of ontologies: general ontologies, which integrate various fields, so-called Top Level Ontologies, and ontologies, which define specific ranges of application, called Domain Ontologies. This distinction generally corresponds with the classic philosophical distinction between formal ontologies and content-defined or regional ontologies [5]. The question remains, however, whether this suffices to cover all types of ontologies. It seems that this distinction works in areas of classic, i.e. scientific or specified data bank information systems (Fachinformationssysteme), even if an applicationoriented expansion is necessary as in the case of medical implementations.

Problems arise, however, when our every day work is to be supported by ubiquitous computing. While Top Level Ontologies, designed in a rather logical and abstract way respectively, are assessing the top level structures and the general laws governing reality, and Domain Ontologies are busy arranging the world according to content into certain spheres, a Pragmatic Ontology should be developed based on the permanently and fast changing ranges of application. Aspects of temporalization especially are of significant importance in this area. Generally a Pragmatic Ontology merely intensifies problems inherent to a lesser degree in the two basic types of ontologies. Domain Ontologies and Top Level Ontologies just prove to be more stable and show a sort of greater logical consistency. But as soon as we leave the level of formal logic there these systems are influenced by temporal and cultural factors. The descriptive level already contains cultural implications. Even scientific ways of describing are just an expression of a certain cultural perspective of European science as Husserl demonstrated in his famous Krisis-book [6]. These two basic systems of informatory ontologies are all in all relatively stable systems of structuring. Top Level Ontologies and Domain Ontologies actually gain their stability by means of disarticulation ( Desartikulation according to Rothacker [7]), for example aesthetic and emotional moments are disarticulated, whereas Pragmatic Ontologies are faced with constant change and therefore have to undergo permanent temporalization and historicization respectively. Pragmatic Ontologies have to be sensitively tuned into cultural and historical factors and have to be distinguished clearly from naive naturalistic Ontologies, regardless how variedly differentiated they may be. Ideas in naturalistic Ontologies do not disclose their roots in history or Lebenswelt and thus also do not disclose that they are subject to change. Pragmatic Ontologies on the other hand exacerbate a problem which is inert in other types of ontologies. This problem, which is not that obvious in the two other types, is the fact that any arranging of so-called representations is done by culturally specific factors and is thus historic, i.e. influenced by cultural and historical preferences. This means that each and every way of arranging is subject to culturally specific articulations and disarticulations. Furthermore there are linguistic and therefore cultural connotations that cannot simply be transferred to other cultures or languages. The term Euthanasie in German has a different connotation than its translation in Dutch or English. But less problematic examples clearly show that systems of arranging cannot just be adapted to other languages or cultures. Die Sonne (engl.: the sun)

has a different connotation than the masculine le soleil in French. Cultural and historical specifications respectively cannot be avoided in any ontology which is to be used for actual spoken language. The general problem is that not just stores of scientific knowledge but applications as well become outdated. It would therefore make sense to equip data with time indicators and expiration dates respectively. Moreover, within certain areas of application assessment preferences should be created a more difficult challenge- preferences which should reflect the reason for use. Certain applications, for example, depend on whether the user is handicapped or not, or what kind of situation the user finds himself in, i.e. whether he is in an emergency or not. Especially higher-level applications require the system to make temporal or historical judgments. For example, it has to be understood that in certain contexts Austria has to be defined as a major power. Briefly spoken, the system has to be equipped with some sense of historicity, if it is to support the user successfully in certain applications. It is however obvious that temporalization of ontologies is not merely concerned with temporal logic. Especially historical aspects as such are not merely concerned with temporal logic but primarily a thing of rating, of connotation and referencing respectively, a thing of superposition and hierarchisation of data. It is, however, doubtful, if it is possible to implement a sense of historicity at all, because historicity can only be viewed in terms of quality. Whether a system could have a sensitivity for and thus develop a sense of the significance of historical events (Ereignishaftigkeit ) depends on the possibility of actually living with us. This would also be a question to be discussed in the Artificial Intelligence community. Despite this, it is necessary to at least implement elements of a historical sense, which are quantitative; for example, historical events, which can be dated exactly like the end of WWII or periods in which the meaning of a term is changing or becomes ambivalent. Generally we can distinguish between three aspects of temporalization. To integrate these aspects into ontologies poses various levels of difficulty:

a) Temporalization by equipping data with a time index. This procedure is without doubt easy to implement and already has been used in many areas. b) Temporalization as a preference of assessment. According to certain situations of use data is hierarchised differently and is therefore listed in different time sequences. This aspect of temporalization can be more easily designed for scientific fields and scientific information systems than every-day use, as this field is not made up of users who share a clearly defined terminology. c) Temporalization as historic interpretive level. This aspect of temporalization requires a system which can adapt in a way as to change preferences according to change in society. A mere statistical assessment of data would not be enough, rather statistical assessments would have to be aligned permanently with possible application situations and qualitative assessments. Only this act of aligning will make obvious when terms have become outdated in certain areas and which terms in which field prove to be largely immune to change and which ones do not. If a system could develop a sort of historic sense then the fact that such a sensor has been developed would carry tremendous meaning for higher-level applications, that is applications which transcend processing topical information. References 1) Janich, Peter: Wozu Ontologie für Informatiker? Objektbezug durch Sprachkritik (http://www.tfhberlin.de/~giak/arbeitskreise/softwaretechnik/publikationen/janich6.pdf.) 2) Foucault, Michel: Les mots et les choses. Paris 1966. 3) A case could be made for using Ernst Cassirer s symbol-theoretical approach to problems connected with ontologies, as his approach deals strictly with questions of arranging and the linking of representations respectively. 4) Capurro, Rafael: Hermeneutik und Fachinformation. Freiburg i.br. 1986. 5) Husserl, Edmund: Formale und transzendentale Logik Versuch einer Kritik der logischen Vernunft. Den Haag 1974. (Husserliana Bd. XVII). 6) Husserl, Edmund: Die Krisis der europäischen Wissenschaft und die transzendentale Phänomenologie. Den Haag 1954 (Husserliana Bd. VI). 7) Rothacker, Erich: Probleme der Kulturanthropologie. Bonn 1988. P. 112-122.