PANTOGRAPHS FOR GEOMETRICAL TRANSFORMATIONS: AN EXPLORATIVE STUDY ON ARGUMENTATION

Similar documents
NON-EXAMPLES AND PROOF BY CONTRADICTION

META-COGNITIVE UNITY IN INDIRECT PROOFS

GESTALT CONFIGURATIONS IN GEOMETRY LEARNING

EUROPEAN RESEARCH IN MATHEMATICS EDUCATION III

THE SENSUAL AND THE CONCEPTUAL: ARTEFACT-MEDIATED KINESTHETIC ACTIONS AND SEMIOTIC ACTIVITY

RAFAEL BOMBELLI S ALGEBRA (1572) AND A NEW MATHEMATICAL OBJECT : A SEMIOTIC ANALYSIS

Cognitive Units, Connections and Mathematical Proof

INTERNATIONAL CONFERENCE ON ENGINEERING DESIGN ICED 05 MELBOURNE, AUGUST 15-18, 2005 GENERAL DESIGN THEORY AND GENETIC EPISTEMOLOGY

ONTOLOGICAL BELIEFS AND THEIR IMPACT

STUDENTS EXPERIENCES OF EQUIVALENCE RELATIONS

Learning Geometry and Music through Computer-aided Music Analysis and Composition: A Pedagogical Approach

1/8. Axioms of Intuition

abc Mark Scheme Mathematics 4302 Specification B General Certificate of Secondary Education Module 5 Paper 1 Tier F 43005/1F

How the sense of mathematical objects changes when their semiotic representations undergo treatment or conversion

Evolution of proof form in Japanese geometry textbooks

Springer is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Educational Studies in Mathematics.

Lecture 7: Incongruent Counterparts

Evolution of proof form in Japanese geometry textbooks

The Object Oriented Paradigm

INTRODUCTION OF AN HISTORICAL AND ANTHROPOLOGICAL PERSPECTIVE IN MATHEMATICS: AN EXAMPLE IN SECONDARY SCHOOL IN FRANCE

PGDBA 2017 INSTRUCTIONS FOR WRITTEN TEST

Interface Design of Wide-View Electronic Working Space Using Gesture Operations for Collaborative Work

Cover Page. The handle holds various files of this Leiden University dissertation.

The promises and problems of a semiotic approach to mathematics, the history of mathematics and mathematics education Melle July 2007

Face Time K 12 th Grades. South Carolina Visual Arts Standards

Formalizing Irony with Doxastic Logic

INTUITION IN SCIENCE AND MATHEMATICS

Partitioning a Proof: An Exploratory Study on Undergraduates Comprehension of Proofs

CRYSTALLINE CONCEPTS IN LONG-TERM MATHEMATICAL INVENTION AND DISCOVERY

Permutations of the Octagon: An Aesthetic-Mathematical Dialectic

How Semantics is Embodied through Visual Representation: Image Schemas in the Art of Chinese Calligraphy *

A Note on Analysis and Circular Definitions

Bas C. van Fraassen, Scientific Representation: Paradoxes of Perspective, Oxford University Press, 2008.

Visual Argumentation in Commercials: the Tulip Test 1

Do Universals Exist? Realism

observation and conceptual interpretation

Research Methodology for the Internal Observation of Design Thinking through the Creative Self-formation Process

Sets, Symbols and Pictures: A Reflection on Euler Diagrams in Leonhard Euler s Tercentenary (2007)

Dividing Notes: Division with Fractions

Music and Mathematics: On Symmetry

Visualisation and proof: a brief survey of philosophical perspectives

Connecting Mathematics and the Arts through the Magic of Escher for Elementary School Students

Ontology as a formal one. The language of ontology as the ontology itself: the zero-level language

PRECEDING PAGE BLANK NOT t_ilmed

The Effects of Web Site Aesthetics and Shopping Task on Consumer Online Purchasing Behavior

Instrumental Music Curriculum

On The Search for a Perfect Language

Logic and Philosophy of Science (LPS)

Christopher W. Tindale, Fallacies and Argument Appraisal

Viewer-Adaptive Control of Displayed Content for Digital Signage

SYNTAX AND MEANING Luis Radford Université Laurentienne, Ontario, Canada

Humanities Learning Outcomes

2 nd Grade Visual Arts Curriculum Essentials Document

Criterion A: Understanding knowledge issues

Approaching Aesthetics on User Interface and Interaction Design

Kuhn. History and Philosophy of STEM. Lecture 6

Module 8 : Numerical Relaying I : Fundamentals

Postprint.

PHILOSOPH ICAL PERSPECTI VES ON PROOF IN MATHEMATI CS EDUCATION

Typography & Page Layout

Semiotics of culture. Some general considerations

SocioBrains THE INTEGRATED APPROACH TO THE STUDY OF ART

Computational Parsing of Melody (CPM): Interface Enhancing the Creative Process during the Production of Music

DATA COMPRESSION USING THE FFT

METHOD TO DETECT GTTM LOCAL GROUPING BOUNDARIES BASED ON CLUSTERING AND STATISTICAL LEARNING

Journal of Undergraduate Research Submission Acknowledgment Form

Visualizing Euclidean Rhythms Using Tangle Theory

THE IMPLEMENTATION OF INTERTEXTUALITY APPROACH TO DEVELOP STUDENTS CRITI- CAL THINKING IN UNDERSTANDING LITERATURE

10/24/2016 RESEARCH METHODOLOGY Lecture 4: Research Paradigms Paradigm is E- mail Mobile

Theory or Theories? Based on: R.T. Craig (1999), Communication Theory as a field, Communication Theory, n. 2, May,

Knowledge Representation

UW-La Crosse Journal of Undergraduate Research

Recommended Operations

Musical Sound: A Mathematical Approach to Timbre

Metaphors: Concept-Family in Context

How Mathematics and Art Are Interconnected. Liz Sweetwood. October 24th, 2016

arxiv: v1 [cs.fl] 26 May 2010

Incommensurability and the Bonfire of the Meta-Theories: Response to Mizrahi Lydia Patton, Virginia Tech

Introduction to Psychology Prof. Braj Bhushan Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Kanpur

Supplementary Course Notes: Continuous vs. Discrete (Analog vs. Digital) Representation of Information

Greeley-Evans School District 6 High School Vocal Music Curriculum Guide Unit: Men s and Women s Choir Year 1 Enduring Concept: Expression of Music

This project builds on a series of studies about shared understanding in collaborative music making. Download the PDF to find out more.

The Debate on Research in the Arts

The Shimer School Core Curriculum

Ontology as Meta-Theory: A Perspective

Theory or Theories? Based on: R.T. Craig (1999), Communication Theory as a field, Communication Theory, n. 2, May,

Arts Education Essential Standards Crosswalk: MUSIC A Document to Assist With the Transition From the 2005 Standard Course of Study

A Meta-Theoretical Basis for Design Theory. Dr. Terence Love We-B Centre School of Management Information Systems Edith Cowan University

Penultimate draft of a review which will appear in History and Philosophy of. $ ISBN: (hardback); ISBN:

High-Definition, Standard-Definition Compatible Color Bar Signal

Precise Digital Integration of Fast Analogue Signals using a 12-bit Oscilloscope

THE MATHEMATICS. Javier F. A. Guachalla H. The mathematics

Instance and System: a Figure and its 2 18 Variations

Computer based composition in the Primary School: An investigation of children s creative responses using Dance ejay

Managing cognitive aspects of conceptual modeling and design in the arrow diagram logic framework: A mathematician s view 1

Shape in Mathematical Discourse, As Observed by an Artist Explorer

The theory of representations as viewed from the onto-semiotic approach to mathematics education

EUROPEAN JOURNAL OF PRAGMATISM AND AMERICAN PHILOSOPHY. The History of Reception of Charles S. Peirce in Greece 1

Escher s Tessellations: The Symmetry of Wallpaper Patterns. 27 January 2014

Escher s Tessellations: The Symmetry of Wallpaper Patterns

Transcription:

PANTOGRAPHS FOR GEOMETRICAL TRANSFORMATIONS: AN EXPLORATIVE STUDY ON ARGUMENTATION Samuele Antonini Francesca Martignone University of Pavia, Italy University of Modena and Reggio Emilia, Italy The geometrical machines, like pantographs for geometrical transformations, have revealed educational potentialities as tools for teaching and learning mathematical proof: they provide situations that can promote the formulation of conjectures and the generation of argumentations. In this paper, we propose a first analysis of the argumentations produced in activities with the machines. In particular, we show that the argumentation can refer to different elements of the pantograph (the structure, the movement, and the drawings traced by the machine) and to different components (figural and conceptual) of the geometrical figures representing the linkages. INTRODUCTION The Laboratory of Mathematical Machines (MMLab), at the Department of Mathematics of University of Modena and Reggio Emilia (Italy), contains a collection of instruments, called Mathematical Machines, which have been reconstructed with a didactical aim, according to the design described in historical texts. In this paper, we refer to the geometrical machine as a tool that forces a point to follow a trajectory or to be transformed according to a given law (Bartolini Bussi & Maschietto, 2008). The MMLab organizes activities with the Mathematical Machines for secondary school students, groups of university students, pre-service and practicing school teachers (Maschietto & Martignone, 2008; Bartolini Bussi & Maschietto, 2008). The design and the development of these activities are carried out by the MMLab research group with the aim to provide a suitable learning context in which to activate important processes, such as the construction of meanings and the construction of proof (Bartolini Bussi, 2000). Our research focuses on machines that establish a correspondence between points of the plan regions, like reflection, central symmetry, translation, rotation, and homothety. These transformations are physically performed through two leads fixed in two plotter points of an articulated system composed by some rigid rods and some pivots (see fig. 1). These machines, named pantographs or linkages, incorporate The study is realized within the project PRIN 2007B2M4EK ( Instruments and representations in the teaching and learning of mathematics: theory and practice ) jointly funded by MIUR, by University of Modena e Reggio Emilia and by University of Siena.

some mathematical properties in such a way as to allow the implementation one geometrical transformation. Fig.1: The Scheiner s pantograph for the homothety The study presented in this paper is part of a wider research about the didactical potentiality of the machines as tools for teaching and learning mathematical proof. Our goal is to investigate the cognitive processes involved in the proof construction in activities with the geometrical machines (some first results are in Martignone & Antonini, 2009a, 2009b): in order to do that, we study the processes that can lead to the construction of a proof or that can be an obstacle to this construction. In particular, we deal with the analysis of argumentations proposed by subjects to support their conjectures. THEORETICAL FRAMEWORK The study presented here focus on argumentation in geometry context. In the following sections we will expose some theoretical considerations on argumentation and proof and on the geometrical figures. Argumentation and proof Many papers have been written on the relationships between argumentation and proof (Mariotti 2006). In general, a mathematical proof of a statement consists of a logical sequence of propositions that states the validity of the statement. Differently, an argumentation consists of a rhetoric means that have the goal to convince somebody of the truth or the falsehood of a statement. Some authors focus on the differences between argumentation and proof (see, for example, Duval, 1992-93). On the other hand, focussing on the processes of argumentation and proof generation, the theoretical framework of Cognitive Unity (Garuti et al., 1996; Mariotti et al., 1997; Garuti et al., 1998; Pedemonte, 2002; Boero, 2007), without forgetting the differences, underlines the analogies between

them. In particular, these studies suggest that, in open-ended problems (where students are asked to produce a conjecture, to generate an argumentation and a proof that support the conjecture), a continuity between the argumentation and the subsequent mathematical proof may or may not occur. For these reasons, it is important to identify the factors that can favour continuities and the elements that can lead to a gap between argumentation and proof. One goal of our research project is to investigate the continuity between argumentation and proof during the machine exploration that led to the identification of the mathematical law made by the machine. In this paper, we focus on the argumentations, in the particular situation in which students are involved with pantographs or linkages for geometrical transformations of the plane. We underline that a mathematical proof is necessarily linked to a theory, a theoretical framework within which the proof makes sense (see Mariotti et al., 1997), while an argumentation in geometry can also concern some figural aspects (as magnitude, shape, etc.) without reference to a theory. In order to take into account these aspects we refer to the theoretical framework of figural concepts. The theory of figural concepts The theory of figural concepts (Fischbein, 1993) provides us with an efficient theoretical tool, suitable to analyse cognitive processes in geometrical problem solving. According to Fischbein (1993), mental entities involved in geometrical reasoning cannot be considered either pure concept or mere image. Geometrical figures are mental entities that simultaneously possess both conceptual properties (as general propositions deduced in the Euclidean theory) and figural properties (as shape, position, magnitude). Fischbein called them figural concepts. A productive reasoning, as an efficient process of proof generation, can be generally explained by the fact that the figural and the conceptual aspect blend in a figural concepts (see, for example Mariotti, 1993; Mariotti & Fischbein, 1997). Our analysis of the argumentation will take into account the distinction and the duality between the components of a figural concept. METHODOLOGY The goal of our research is to study the argumentation generated by subjects that are asked to discover what the machine does and to prove it. In this first step of the research we needed to analyse rich argumentation activities linked to the particular situation in which a mathematical machine are the object that has to be explored. For this reason, we selected subjects who were familiar with geometry and with problem-solving but that have not seen these machines before. The subjects were three pre-service teachers, two university students and one young researcher in mathematics. The task was identifying the geometrical transformation and to prove that the machine performed that transformation. Data were collected through clinical

interviews that were videotaped. Subjects were asked to express their thinking process aloud. The analysis of the interviews is based both on the transcripts and on the manipulative activities on the pantographs. In this paper we report some results about the explorations of a linkage for reflection (fig. 2) and of a pantograph for homothety (Scheiner s Pantograph, see fig. 3). Fig. 2: An image of pantograph for reflection and its products. Two opposite vertices (A and B) of a rhombus, composed of four equal rods pivoted together, can move in a groove (a straight path r). The other opposite vertices (P and Q) are corresponding in the reflection of axis r. Fig.3: An image from Scheiner s pantograph. Four rods are pivoted so that they form a parallelogram AQCB. The point O is pivoted on the plane. It is possible to prove that P, Q and O are on the same line and that P and Q correspond in the homothety of centre O and ratio BO/AO.

ARGUMENTATION IN EXPLORING THE GEOMETRICAL MACHINES The argumentations justifying that the machine implements a particular geometrical transformation are closely related to three elements: the drawings traced by the machine, the structure of the machine (as a figural or a conceptual component), and the machine movement. Notice that the same subject could propose more than one type of argumentation. This is common in task requiring the production of a conjecture and a proof, when one arguments with different goals: producing, testing, supporting, and proving a conjecture. Argumentation that refers to the drawings traced by the machine These argumentations refer to the shape of the drawings traced by the machine and to their comparison. There are not theoretical references in this type of argumentation. The machine is used to perform effectively the transformation and the argumentation is based on the products of the transformation. We notice that the drawings can be traced by the leads of the machine but there is also the possibility that the subject sees the drawings only through the movement of the plotter points. For example, some of the pre-service teachers, exploring the Scheiner s pantograph, state that the machine performs a homothety because one of the two drawings traced by the machine appears as an enlargement of the other one. Argumentation that refers to the structure of the machine These argumentations refer to one or more elements of the static structure of the machine, that is the structure of the machine when it is stopped in some position. We give two examples. In the first, the subject refers to the figural aspect of the structure, in the second to the conceptual aspect of the geometrical figure represented by the articulated system. Example 1. Lucia, a pre-service teacher, exploring the Scheiner s pantograph, conjectures that the transformation is a homothety and she justifies her statement saying that it has these two pivots [she points at A and B], and this rod [BP] is longer than this [AQ]. This, for Lucia, explains the fact that the drawing made by the lead put in the point Q is an enlargement of the drawing traced by the lead put in the point P. According to the theory of figural concepts, the argumentation refers to the figural aspect (a qualitative relationship between the length of BP and the length of AQ) of the geometric figure represented by the articulated system, without any reference to a mathematical theory. In a following section we will present a deeper analysis of another example. Example 2. Anna, a pre-service teacher, exploring the linkage for reflection (fig. 2), justifies that the transformation is a reflection showing that the two plotter points (P and Q) are on the segment whose groove is the perpendicular bisector. Then Anna refers to some conceptual properties of rhombus to support this fact. According to the theory of figural concepts, the argumentation refers to the conceptual aspects of

the geometric figure represented by the articulated system. Another example will shown in a following section. Argumentation that refers to the movement of the machine These argumentations refer to some dynamic properties of the articulated system, i.e. to some characteristics of its movement. Example. In the transcript we will analyse below, Carlo proposes many argumentations to support his conjecture about the linkage for the reflection (fig. 2). One of these argumentations refers to the movement of the machine, in particular to the fact that if one plotter point approaches the reflection axis, then also the other plotter point approaches that (see below). ANALYSIS OF A TRANSCRIPT In this section, we analyse a transcript of an interview in which the subject proposes more than one argumentation to support his conjecture about the transformation made by the machine: one argumentation referring to the figural aspect of the structure, one referring to the movement and one referring to the conceptual aspect of the articulated system. Only after these argumentations he generates a mathematical proof. Carlo is a young researcher in mathematics and this is his first experience with mathematical machine. He is exploring the pantograph for the reflection. [ ] I see a line in the centre and I think to a symmetry (he makes a gesture opening his hands in a symmetric way, like he is opening a book). I have thought to a symmetry reflection, because there is this line, it could not be, but it s all quite so symmetric that (he makes a rhombus with his hands) Carlo considers the figural aspects of the machine structure. It is the shape, the symmetry, underlined by the groove in the centre, that starts to convince Carlo that the transformation is the reflection (argumentation referring to the figural aspect of the structure of the machine). [ ] well, so, then I remind that this will be the transformation [ ] symmetry as it is called... reflection I had seen it immediately for the shape. Carlo recalls the previous argumentation and the fact that it refers to the figural aspect of the structure of the articulated system. Because these are rigid (he points at the rods and then he starts to move the articulated system) then probably there can be some properties linked to the (he stops the movement of the machine) rhombus. The observation of the structure of the articulated system ( these are rigid ) leads Carlo to anticipate that there could be some mathematical properties related to the figure now identified as rhombus. These properties can justify that the machine

implements the reflection. There is here an important transition, anticipated and not yet implemented, from an argumentation linked to the figural aspects of the machine structure to an argumentation related to the conceptual aspect of a geometrical figure (rhombus) that represents the articulated system. For the moment it is only an anticipation that will lead later to the construction of a mathematical proof. Anyway, now we will see Carlo postpones the generation of the proof: what he has said about the properties of the rhombus remains only an anticipation. As we can see below, it seems that he feels the need of other argumentations before constructing the proof. And also the movement (he starts again to move the machine with two hands), the movement seems to me quite significant for this: if I approach the axis with this point [P], also the other point [Q] approaches it, both perpendicularly... the fact that there is a movement also in this direction (he moves the articulated system by sliding the pins, the points A and B in the fig. 2, in the groove) This argumentation is linked to a property of the machine movement, showing a dynamic relationship between the two corresponding points (P and Q) of the transformation; for Carlo it supports again the fact that this is a reflection (argumentation referring to the movement of the machine). I do not need the leads. He does not feel the need to use the leads, he does not consider important to have an argument based on the tracks. The different argumentations produced have convinced Carlo but probably the use of the leads is not taken into consideration also because he is aware that they would not give any new contribution to the knowledge of the machine functioning and then to the construction of a proof. Then, why it works... so if they all have the same length, we have a figure... this is a geometric figure with four equal sides... where this (he follows the groove with his finger) is a diagonal, therefore it's a rhombus... for the rhombus properties the two diagonals are perpendicular, this tells me that this diagonal (he tracks with his finger an imaginary diagonal that joints the pointer point with the tracer point) is perpendicular and also they (the two diagonals) bisect each other. Here, Carlo proposes an argumentation based on the geometrical properties of the articulated system (argumentation referring to the conceptual aspect of the structure of the machine). We observe that Carlo has no difficulties in the identification of the transformation. Nevertheless he needs to look for additional argumentations before constructing the proof. After a first argumentation based on the figural components of the structure of the machines, he proposes an argumentation referring to the relationships between

the movement of the two points involved in the transformation. Finally he comes back to the structure of the articulated systems but this time he considers the conceptual components, supporting his statement in the geometrical theory. We think that the different argumentations proposed by Carlo have the goal of strengthening the conviction that the conjecture is true, but also to offer a more complete argumentation that can take into account different perspectives about the machine and its use. It is interesting to notice that, differently from students processes, the only type of argumentation not generated by Carlo is that linked to the drawings traced by the machine. This type of argumentation is very useful to generate a conjecture and to test it, and for this reason it is very common among students with minor experience. Nevertheless, as Carlo feels, it could not give contributions neither to the explanation of the movement nor to the proof construction. CONCLUSIONS The subjects, as we have shown in the Carlo s protocol, produced different types of argumentations, even during the same exploration phase. It is important to underline that mathematical culture, but also familiarity with the machines, seem to promote the emergence and the development of different types of argumentations. In fact, we have noticed that the experts produce several argumentations and they refer to the drawings traced by the machine only when they have difficulties in identifying the mathematical law incorporated in the machine; differently, the argumentations referring to drawings are very common in students activities. The proposed analysis of the machines explorations paves the way for the generation of hypotheses on the transition from argumentation to proof. In particular, we hypothesize that, in the case of argumentations referring to the conceptual part of the machine structure, there can be cognitive unity between argumentation and proof, in other cases it seems plausible to attend to cases of cognitive break. A special case seems to be the argumentations based on movement, because they often lead to further argumentations that explain the motion through the structure of the articulated system, and a cognitive unity may or may not occur. Regarding the transition between argumentation and proof, we mention briefly that in the interviews we have carried on, the interviewer s interventions has been relevant in guiding the students to the proof construction. In fact, it seems that some interventions, aimed to put an emphasis also on argumentations that students do not spontaneously generate, can be educationally effective in the activities with machines oriented to stimulate and to develop argumentative and proving processes.

REFERENCES Bartolini Bussi M.G. (2000). Ancient Instruments in the Mathematics Classroom. In Fauvel J., van Maanen J. (eds), History in Mathematics Education: The ICMI Study, Dordrecht: Kluwer Ac. Publishers, 343-351. Bartolini Bussi M. G. & Maschietto M. (2008). Machines as tools in teacher education. In Wood, B. Jaworski, K. Krainer, P. Sullivan, D. Tirosh (eds.), International Handbook of Mathematics Teacher Education, vol. 2 (Tools and Processes in Mathematics Teacher Education), Rotterdam: Sense Publisher. Boero, P. (ed.) (2007). Theorems in school: from history, epistemology and cognition to classroom practice, Sense Publishers. Duval, R.(1992-93). Argumenter, demontrer, expliquer: coninuité ou rupture cognitive?, Petit x 31, pp.37-61. Fischbein, E. (1993). The theory of figural concepts. Educational Studies in Mathematics, 24 (2), 139-162. Garuti, R.,Boero, P.,Lemut, E.&Mariotti, M.A.(1996). Challenging the traditional school approach to theorems: a hypothesis about the cognitive unity of theorems, in Proc. of the 20th PME Conference, Valencia, v. 2, 113-120. Garuti, R.,Boero, P.,Lemut, E.(1998). Cognitive Unity of Theorems and Difficulties of Proof, in Proc. of the 22th PME Conference, Stellenbosch, South Africa, v. 2, 345-352. Mariotti M.A. (1993). The influence of standard images in geometrical reasoning, in Proc. of the 17th PME Conference, Tsukuba, Japan, v. 2, 177-182. Mariotti, M.A. (2006), Proof and Proving in Mathematics Education, in A. Gutierrez & P. Boero (Eds.), Handbook of Research on the Psychology of Mathematics Education: Past, present and future. Sense Publishers, Rotterdam, Netherlands, 173-204. Mariotti, M. A., Bartolini Bussi, M., Boero, P., Ferri, F., & Garuti, R. (1997). Approaching geometry theorems in contexts: from history and epistemology to cognition. In E. Pehkonen (Ed.), Proc. of the 21th PME Conference, Finland, Lathi, v. 1, 180 195. Mariotti M.A. & Fischbein, E. (1997). Defining in classroom activities. Educational Studies in Mathematics, 34, 219-24. Martignone, F., Antonini, S. (2009a), Exploring the mathematical machines for geometrical transformations: a cognitive analysis. In Tzekaki, M., Kaldrimidou, M., & Sakonidis, H. (Eds.), Proceedings of the 33rd Conference of the International Group for the Psychology of Mathematics Education, Thessaloniki, Greece, vol. 4, pp. 105-112.

Martignone, F. & Antonini, S. (2009b). Students utilization schemes of pantographs for geometrical transformations: a first classification. Proceedings of Cerme6, Lyon, France, pp. 1250-1259. Maschietto, M. & Martignone, F. (2008). Activities with the Mathematical Machines: Pantographs and curve drawers. Proc. of the 5th European Summer University On The History And Epistemology In Mathematics Education, Univerzita Karlova, Prague. Pedemonte, B. (2002). Etude didactique et cognitive des rapports de l argumentation et de la démonstration dans l apprentissage des mathématiques, Thèse, Université Joseph Fourier, Grenoble.