KINDS (NATURAL KINDS VS. HUMAN KINDS)

Similar documents
1 Mind-Independence and Realism. Muhammad Ali Khalidi Mind-Dependent Kinds

Some problems for Lowe s Four-Category Ontology

PHIL 480: Seminar in the History of Philosophy Building Moral Character: Neo-Confucianism and Moral Psychology

How to Fix Kind Membership: A Problem for HPC-Theory and a Solution

Capricious Kinds Jessica Laimann

WHAT S LEFT OF HUMAN NATURE? A POST-ESSENTIALIST, PLURALIST AND INTERACTIVE ACCOUNT OF A CONTESTED CONCEPT. Maria Kronfeldner

What Can Experimental Philosophy Do? David Chalmers

Natural Kinds and Concepts: A Pragmatist and Methodologically Naturalistic Account

10/24/2016 RESEARCH METHODOLOGY Lecture 4: Research Paradigms Paradigm is E- mail Mobile

Habit, Semeiotic Naturalism, and Unity among the Sciences Aaron Wilson

Brandom s Reconstructive Rationality. Some Pragmatist Themes

Moral Judgment and Emotions

that would join theoretical philosophy (metaphysics) and practical philosophy (ethics)?

The erratically fine-grained metaphysics of functional kinds in technology and biology

The Debate on Research in the Arts

An introduction to biological essentialism. John Wilkins Biohumanities Project University of Queensland

Science and Values: Holism and Radical Environmental Activism

observation and conceptual interpretation

An Aristotelian Puzzle about Definition: Metaphysics VII.12 Alan Code

The Constitution Theory of Intention-Dependent Objects and the Problem of Ontological Relativism

What do our appreciation of tonal music and tea roses, our acquisition of the concepts

Social Mechanisms and Scientific Realism: Discussion of Mechanistic Explanation in Social Contexts Daniel Little, University of Michigan-Dearborn

Reply to Stalnaker. Timothy Williamson. In Models and Reality, Robert Stalnaker responds to the tensions discerned in Modal Logic

The Nature of Time. Humberto R. Maturana. November 27, 1995.

Peircean concept of sign. How many concepts of normative sign are needed. How to clarify the meaning of the Peircean concept of sign?

Mass Communication Theory

Types of perceptual content

PHL 317K 1 Fall 2017 Overview of Weeks 1 5

Uskali Mäki Putnam s Realisms: A View from the Social Sciences

Kęstas Kirtiklis Vilnius University Not by Communication Alone: The Importance of Epistemology in the Field of Communication Theory.

Incommensurability and Partial Reference

MAURICE MANDELBAUM HISTORY, MAN, & REASON A STUDY IN NINETEENTH-CENTURY THOUGHT THE JOHNS HOPKINS PRESS: BALTIMORE AND LONDON

Conclusion. One way of characterizing the project Kant undertakes in the Critique of Pure Reason is by

Thomas Szanto: Bewusstsein, Intentionalität und mentale Repräsentation. Husserl und die analytische Philosophie des Geistes

Imitating the Human Form: Four Kinds of Anthropomorphic Form Carl DiSalvo 1 Francine Gemperle 2 Jodi Forlizzi 1, 3

Philosophy Department Expanded Course Descriptions Fall, 2007

ANALYSIS OF THE PREVAILING VIEWS REGARDING THE NATURE OF THEORY- CHANGE IN THE FIELD OF SCIENCE

Kant: Notes on the Critique of Judgment

Course Description: looks into the from a range dedicated too. Course Goals: Requirements: each), a 6-8. page writing. assignment. grade.

The Strengths and Weaknesses of Frege's Critique of Locke By Tony Walton

Resemblance Nominalism: A Solution to the Problem of Universals

Krisis. Journal for contemporary philosophy

Ridgeview Publishing Company

Historical/Biographical

THE LOGICAL FORM OF BIOLOGICAL OBJECTS


Is Genetic Epistemology of Any Interest for Semiotics?

du Châtelet s ontology: element, corpuscle, body

Lisa Randall, a professor of physics at Harvard, is the author of "Warped Passages: Unraveling the Mysteries of the Universe's Hidden Dimensions.

Perceptions and Hallucinations

WHY IS BEAUTY A ROAD TO THE TRUTH? 1. Introduction

Discourse analysis is an umbrella term for a range of methodological approaches that

Philosophy of Science: The Pragmatic Alternative April 2017 Center for Philosophy of Science University of Pittsburgh ABSTRACTS

REVIEW ARTICLE IDEAL EMBODIMENT: KANT S THEORY OF SENSIBILITY

Searle on External Realism and Privileged Conceptual Scheme

The topic of this Majors Seminar is Relativism how to formulate it, and how to evaluate arguments for and against it.

Introduction. Lior Rabi. José Ortega y Gasset is the most prominent Spanish philosopher in the 20 th century.

Holism, Concept Individuation, and Conceptual Change

Environmental Ethics: From Theory to Practice

124 Philosophy of Mathematics

PROFESSORS: Bonnie B. Bowers (chair), George W. Ledger ASSOCIATE PROFESSORS: Richard L. Michalski (on leave short & spring terms), Tiffany A.

Social Construction. Ásta Sveinsdóttir* San Francisco State University

Representation and Discourse Analysis

Emotion, an Organ of Happiness. Ruey-Yuan Wu National Tsing-Hua University

Perception and Mind-Dependence Lecture 3

Department of Philosophy Florida State University

Sidestepping the holes of holism

Análisis Filosófico ISSN: Sociedad Argentina de Análisis Filosófico Argentina

CUST 100 Week 17: 26 January Stuart Hall: Encoding/Decoding Reading: Stuart Hall, Encoding/Decoding (Coursepack)

GLOSSARY for National Core Arts: Visual Arts STANDARDS

Ontology as a formal one. The language of ontology as the ontology itself: the zero-level language

Università della Svizzera italiana. Faculty of Communication Sciences. Master of Arts in Philosophy 2017/18

Penultimate Draft- Final version forthcoming in Philosophical Psychology

Semiotics of culture. Some general considerations

UNIT SPECIFICATION FOR EXCHANGE AND STUDY ABROAD

What counts as a convincing scientific argument? Are the standards for such evaluation

Part IV Social Science and Network Theory

LCU 1. Subjectivity. An Assignment Submitted by. Name of Student. Name of Establishment. Class XXXX, Section XXXX, Summer 2012

THE EVOLUTION OF RELIGION AND THE EVOLUTION OF CULTURE TAYLOR THIEL DAVIS. B.Sc., The University of Georgia, 2000 M.A., Tufts University, 2011

Verity Harte Plato on Parts and Wholes Clarendon Press, Oxford 2002

Having the World in View: Essays on Kant, Hegel, and Sellars

Evolutionary Explanation and the Hard Problem of Consciousness. Steven Horst Wesleyan University

On Language, Discourse and Reality

LeBar s Flaccidity: Is there Cause for Concern?

Aristotle on the Human Good

What is (an) emotion?

A Comprehensive Critical Study of Gadamer s Hermeneutics

ARISTOTLE AND THE UNITY CONDITION FOR SCIENTIFIC DEFINITIONS ALAN CODE [Discussion of DAVID CHARLES: ARISTOTLE ON MEANING AND ESSENCE]

Wilfrid Sellars from Philosophy and the Scientific Image of Man

Université Libre de Bruxelles

Embodied music cognition and mediation technology

Goldie s Puzzling Two Feelings: Bodily Feeling and Feeling Toward

SOCIAL AND CULTURAL ANTHROPOLOGY

INTRODUCTION TO THE POLITICS OF SOCIAL THEORY

Normative and Positive Economics

Second Grade: National Visual Arts Core Standards

Composition, Counterfactuals, Causation

Scientific Philosophy

BOOK REVIEW. William W. Davis

THE PROBLEM OF NOVELTY IN C.S. PEIRCE'S AND A.N. WHITEHEAD'S THOUGHT

Transcription:

KINDS (NATURAL KINDS VS. HUMAN KINDS) Both the natural and the social sciences posit taxonomies or classification schemes that divide their objects of study into various categories. Many philosophers hold that what makes some taxonomic schemes more legitimate than others is that they correspond to actually existing divisions in nature, which they label natural kinds. In other words, some classification schemes carve nature at the joints (to use a phrase inspired by Plato), while others are merely arbitrary or gerrymandered. In the natural world, examples of natural kinds would be insect and metal, but not bug and rock, or insects-born-on-monday and metals-whose-names-start-with- s, which are non-natural or artificial kinds. When it comes to the social sciences, the question is: do some categories correspond to social kinds or human kinds (the two terms are often used interchangeably), just as some categories in the natural sciences correspond to natural kinds? Social scientists posit kinds of human beings (e.g. consumer, psychopath), kinds of social institution (e.g. political party, economic market), kinds of social process (e.g. ritual, immigration), and so on. But is it enough for a social scientist simply to invoke a human or social category to conclude that such a kind really exists and that it ought to be admitted into our ontology? This entry begins by examining purported differences between natural kinds and human or social kinds. Then, whether or not human kinds are fundamentally different from natural kinds, it will ask how we can distinguish genuine human kinds from spurious ones. Finally, the issue of natural kinds and human kinds will be related to the common claim that certain categories in both the natural and the social sciences are social constructs.

Differences Between Natural Kinds and Human Kinds Recent philosophical work has tended to favor an essentialist understanding of what it is for a category to correspond to a natural kind. Although essentialists are not united on the precise features that characterize natural kinds, they tend to posit that each natural kind is characterized by all or some of the following: (1) properties that are necessary and sufficient for membership in the kind, (2) micro-structural properties, (3) intrinsic properties, (4) modally necessary properties, and (5) properties that are discoverable by science. If one understands natural kinds in this essentialist fashion, then it is fairly clear that most, if not all, social categories will fail to qualify as natural kinds. Without going into these features in detail, it would appear that many social categories are not definable in terms of necessary and sufficient properties, are not characterized by an underlying microstructure, are not wholly determined by their intrinsic properties, and do not have their properties as a matter of metaphysical necessity. Moreover, if they are discoverable by science, it will be a social rather than a natural science. Hence, this essentialist account of natural kinds would seem to be a non-starter for the social domain. But the essentialist account of natural kinds, though currently popular among some philosophers, is not universally held. Without taking the social sciences into account, the essentialist consensus is showing signs of unraveling under the pressure of categories in biology and many of the other special sciences (e.g. geology, biochemistry, and so on). Still, even if one does not endorse an essentialist understanding of natural kinds, there may yet be fundamental differences between natural kinds and human or social kinds. The first obstacle to assimilating human kinds to natural kinds lies in the fact that real entities are often distinguished from artificial ones on the grounds that the latter are minddependent or a result of human artifice. But if we adopt that criterion, then we would be led to

judge all human or social kinds to be non-real. Even though they may not be intentionally and consciously produced by human beings, all human or social kinds are influenced in some way by human action and social forces and cannot be regarded as independent of human beings and their minds. This seems to be one obvious way in which human kinds are different from natural kinds. A second difference between human and natural kinds has been elaborated by Ian Hacking, who argues that human kinds are interactive or subject to the looping effect. Hacking has illustrated this claim with various categories, such as child abuse, multiple personality disorder, fugue ( mad traveler syndrome), and others. Consider the category of child abuse. Once this practice is identified and labeled, those who engage in it may alter their behavior, either by refraining from the practice altogether, or by engaging in it more covertly, or in some other way. In these cases, the phenomenon may be altered as a result of human intervention, for instance by becoming less visible. Since the very nature of the phenomenon has changed, it then loops back to influence our beliefs about it, which may in turn have further effects on this practice, and so on. Though looping effects undoubtedly influence the nature of social phenomena, it is not clear that such effects are confined to the social realm. For instance, some have suggested that biological species that are a product of artificial selection can be subject to looping effects too, such as the domestic dog (Canis familiaris), whose phenotypical traits have been shaped by the beliefs and actions of human beings. A third difference between natural kinds and human or social kinds has been emphasized by John Searle, who says that what it is for some social kind, x, to be x is simply to be regarded as x. For example, what it is for something to be money is for it to be regarded as money, to be used as money, and to be believed to be money. Hence, social kinds are ontologically subjective, being dependent for their very existence on human attitudes towards them, which distinguishes

them from natural kinds. But critics have observed that Searle s account seems to apply only to the most conventional of social kinds, such as money or government, which depend for their very existence on human attitudes concerning those very categories. Other social kinds, such as racism or economic recession, do not seem to depend on our having attitudes towards them at all. They are therefore arguably not ontologically subjective, at least not in the same sense as kinds such as money. Finally, perhaps the most widely cited difference between natural kinds and human kinds pertains to their purported value-ladenness or their alleged normative dimension. Some social scientists and philosophers regard many social categories to be evaluative and consider that their range of application and the properties associated with them are not determined solely by the nature of social phenomena themselves, but at least partly by our moral and ideological attitudes towards those social phenomena. If categories like race, gender, and child abuse are shaped by our value judgments or ideological stances, then that may set them apart from categories denoting natural kinds. But even those social theorists who insist that the very aims of social science ought to be normative (for example, aiming at human empowerment or emancipation) seem to distinguish between the descriptive and normative dimensions of social theorizing. If so, this leaves room for the possibility that at least some of our social categories can serve a more purely descriptive and explanatory purpose. Genuine and Spurious Human Kinds Whether or not there are fundamental differences between natural kinds and human or social kinds, it is possible to maintain that at least some social categories correspond to social or human kinds. The next challenge consists in saying just which categories delineate genuine as opposed

to spurious human kinds, or how to distinguish between real and non-real kinds in the social domain. One promising route might be to return to one of the original sources of the notion of a natural kind (or real kind ) in the work of the 19 th century English philosopher John Stuart Mill. Mill was skeptical as to whether races constituted real kinds of humans that would constitute species or subspecies of human beings. His reasoning depended on the idea that a real or natural kind, whether in the natural or social sciences, ought to be characterized by a multitude of properties that are not simply deducible from one another. These properties ought to be scientifically important in the sense of being explanatory and playing a role in inductive inference. Moreover, he accorded primary responsibility for determining whether this was the case to the investigators in each branch of knowledge, also accepting that there may be different classification schemes deployed by theorists in different scientific disciplines or sub-disciplines. If we follow Mill broadly in this approach, we may consider human kinds to correspond to those categories identified by social scientists and investigators studying the properties of human beings and human society. The categories that they arrive at as a result of their investigations, provided they are genuinely explanatory and feature in inductive inference, would be the ones that correspond to real human kinds, while those that are not can be safely dismissed. Also following Mill, there need be no unique classification of human beings, their institutions, processes, and so on, into a hierarchy of categories. Rather, we may end up classifying humans into many crosscutting systems of kinds (for instance, in terms of both class and ethnicity) without undermining the reality of those kinds.

Social Kinds and Social Construction What should we make of ubiquitous claims that at least some social kinds are social constructions? There is a sense in which any such claim about a social kind is vacuous, since social processes, institutions, and attitudes are all in some way constructed by human society. But is there a more interesting sense in which such claims are warranted? There would seem to be at least two possibilities. The first is that a socially constructed kind is one that is more deliberately a result of human artifice than might appear at first. (This may occur along the lines of Hacking s looping effect, or in the manner of Searle s conventional social kinds.) In connection with this, social constructionists may provide informative accounts of the way in which the process of construction took place, tracing it back to particular historical eras or identifying it with certain social movements with specific ideologies or interests. A second possibility is that saying that a kind is a social construct is opposed to regarding it as being biological or physiological in nature. Such claims are often made with regard to kinds that are commonly thought to be in the domain of the natural sciences, but should rather be regarded as pertaining to the social sciences, such as race and gender. In such cases, to claim that a kind is a social construct is to say that the basis of the kind is not biological but can be found in social processes and relations instead. Conclusion Categories in the social sciences may be more mind-dependent, interactive, conventional, and normative than those in the natural sciences, but that may not prevent them from corresponding to genuine human or social kinds. Moreover, genuine human kinds may be distinguished from

spurious kinds on the basis of such features as their role in inductive inference and their explanatory value. This may enable us to better address some questions regarding categories that arise in the practice of social science, such as the reality of the category of race, or how many gender categories there are in the human species. See also: Essentialism; Metaphysics and Science; Race, Theories of; Searle and the Construction of Social Reality; Social Ontology, Recent Theories of; Social Constructivism; Social Construction of reality; Relativisms and their Ontologies Muhammad Ali Khalidi FURTHER READINGS Griffiths, P. E. (2004). Emotions as natural and normative kinds. Philosophy of Science, 71, 901 911. Hacking, I. (1999). The social construction of what? Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Haslanger, S. (2006). What good are our intuitions? Philosophical analysis and social kinds. Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume, 80, 89 118. Khalidi, M. A. (2010). Interactive kinds. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 61, 335 360. Mallon, R. (2007). Human categories beyond non-essentialism. Journal of Political Philosophy, 15, 146 168. Mill, J. S. (1974). A system of logic ratiocinative and inductive. Toronto, Canada: University of Toronto Press. (Original work published 1843) Millikan, R. G. (1999). Historical kinds and the special sciences. Philosophical Studies, 95, 45 65. Searle, J. (1995). The construction of social reality. New York, NY: Free Press.

Thomasson, A. (2003). Realism and human kinds. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 67, 580 609.