SENIOR SEMINAR 2015/2016 Gnothi Seauton Know Thyself : Conceptions of Self-Consciousness in German Idealism, Semantic Theory, and Psychoanalysis

Similar documents
SENIOR SEMINAR 2014/2015: AESTHETICS AND SUBJECTIVITY: HERMENEUTICS, DECONSTRUCTION, AND PSYCHOANALYSIS

PAUL REDDING S CONTINENTAL IDEALISM (AND DELEUZE S CONTINUATION OF THE IDEALIST TRADITION) Sean Bowden

Kant s Critique of Judgment

KANT S TRANSCENDENTAL LOGIC

POSTMODERN CRITICAL THEORY: FROM PHENOMOLOGY TO PYSCHOANALYSIS: BODY, LANGUAGE, DESIRE, AND IDEALOGY:

that would join theoretical philosophy (metaphysics) and practical philosophy (ethics)?

IMPORTANT QUOTATIONS

Foucault's Archaeological method

HEGEL, ANALYTIC PHILOSOPHY AND THE RETURN OF METAPHYISCS Simon Lumsden

Please cite the published version in Human Studies, available at Springer via

1/8. The Third Paralogism and the Transcendental Unity of Apperception

Truth and Method in Unification Thought: A Preparatory Analysis

Necessity in Kant; Subjective and Objective

Conclusion. One way of characterizing the project Kant undertakes in the Critique of Pure Reason is by

A Comprehensive Critical Study of Gadamer s Hermeneutics

Philosophical Background to 19 th Century Modernism

What counts as a convincing scientific argument? Are the standards for such evaluation

1/10. The A-Deduction

A Copernican Revolution in IS: Using Kant's Critique of Pure Reason for Describing Epistemological Trends in IS

UNIT SPECIFICATION FOR EXCHANGE AND STUDY ABROAD

Art, Social Justice, and Critical Theory Colloquium:

CAROL HUNTS University of Kansas

1/9. The B-Deduction

Foucault and Lacan: Who is Master?

By Tetsushi Hirano. PHENOMENOLOGY at the University College of Dublin on June 21 st 2013)

Philosophy Pathways Issue th December 2016

KANTIAN CONCEPTUALISM

The topic of this Majors Seminar is Relativism how to formulate it, and how to evaluate arguments for and against it.

PH th Century Philosophy Ryerson University Department of Philosophy Mondays, 3-6pm Fall 2010

Architecture as the Psyche of a Culture

Heideggerian Ontology: A Philosophic Base for Arts and Humanties Education

Making Modal Distinctions: Kant on the possible, the actual, and the intuitive understanding.

The Strengths and Weaknesses of Frege's Critique of Locke By Tony Walton

Having the World in View: Essays on Kant, Hegel, and Sellars

PH 360 CROSS-CULTURAL PHILOSOPHY IES Abroad Vienna

1. Freud s different conceptual elaborations on the unconscious: epistemological,

Phenomenology Glossary

Sidestepping the holes of holism

Notes on Gadamer, The Relevance of the Beautiful

On The Search for a Perfect Language

Immanuel Kant Critique of Pure Reason

A Letter from Louis Althusser on Gramsci s Thought

CRITIQUE AS UNCERTAINTY

The Polish Peasant in Europe and America. W. I. Thomas and Florian Znaniecki

TRAGIC THOUGHTS AT THE END OF PHILOSOPHY

The Teaching Method of Creative Education

CHAPTER 2 THEORETICAL FRAMEWORK

Edward Winters. Aesthetics and Architecture. London: Continuum, 2007, 179 pp. ISBN

Interdepartmental Learning Outcomes

Spatial Formations. Installation Art between Image and Stage.

By Rahel Jaeggi Suhrkamp, 2014, pbk 20, ISBN , 451pp. by Hans Arentshorst

foucault s archaeology science and transformation David Webb

INTRODUCTION TO THE POLITICS OF SOCIAL THEORY

An Intense Defence of Gadamer s Significance for Aesthetics

The Unconscious: Metaphor and Metonymy

THESIS MIND AND WORLD IN KANT S THEORY OF SENSATION. Submitted by. Jessica Murski. Department of Philosophy

Natika Newton, Foundations of Understanding. (John Benjamins, 1996). 210 pages, $34.95.

Mass Communication Theory

Università della Svizzera italiana. Faculty of Communication Sciences. Master of Arts in Philosophy 2017/18

Comments on Bence Nanay, Perceptual Content and the Content of Mental Imagery

Arnold I. Davidson, Frédéric Gros (eds.), Foucault, Wittgenstein: de possibles rencontres (Éditions Kimé, 2011), ISBN:

Jacek Surzyn University of Silesia Kant s Political Philosophy

Introduction. Fiora Salis University of Lisbon

From Kant to Hegel and Back again The Move Towards Detranscendentalization

SOME QUESTIONS ABOUT THE THEORY OF THE SUBJECT: THE DISCURSIVE POLITICS OF PSYCHOANALYTIC THEORIES

The Unfolding of Intellectual Conversion

Moral Judgment and Emotions

TERMS & CONCEPTS. The Critical Analytic Vocabulary of the English Language A GLOSSARY OF CRITICAL THINKING

Hypatia, Volume 21, Number 3, Summer 2006, pp (Review) DOI: /hyp For additional information about this article

Kant: Notes on the Critique of Judgment

Bas C. van Fraassen, Scientific Representation: Paradoxes of Perspective, Oxford University Press, 2008.

On Recanati s Mental Files

BRANIGAN, Edward. Narrative Comprehension and Film. London/New York : Routledge, 1992, 325 pp.

Pierre Hadot on Philosophy as a Way of Life. Pierre Hadot ( ) was a French philosopher and historian of ancient philosophy,

CONRAD AND IMPRESSIONISM JOHN G. PETERS

GRADUATE SEMINARS

Action, Criticism & Theory for Music Education

Review of S. J. McGrath and Joseph Carew (eds.). Rethinking German Idealism, London: Palgrave Macmillan, pp.

Kęstas Kirtiklis Vilnius University Not by Communication Alone: The Importance of Epistemology in the Field of Communication Theory.

Chapter Two. Absolute Identity: Hegel s Critique of Reflection

Kant on Unity in Experience

Kant s Argument for the Apperception Principle

Categories and Schemata

7. This composition is an infinite configuration, which, in our own contemporary artistic context, is a generic totality.

Interpretive and Critical Research Traditions

The Case for Absolute Spontaneity in Kant s Critique of Pure Reason. La defensa de la espontaneidad absoluta en la Crítica de la razón pura de Kant

Society for the Study of Symbolic Interaction SSSI/ASA 2002 Conference, Chicago

Aesthetics and meaning

REVIEW ARTICLE IDEAL EMBODIMENT: KANT S THEORY OF SENSIBILITY

What Can Experimental Philosophy Do? David Chalmers

Normative and Positive Economics

Penultimate draft of a review which will appear in History and Philosophy of. $ ISBN: (hardback); ISBN:

KANT, SELF-AWARENESS AND SELF-REFERENCE

WHITEHEAD'S PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE AND METAPHYSICS

Philosophical roots of discourse theory

SocioBrains THE INTEGRATED APPROACH TO THE STUDY OF ART

HEGEL S CONCEPT OF ACTION

Phenomenology and Non-Conceptual Content

Nature's Perspectives

Valuable Particulars

Transcription:

PHIL-490 SENIOR SEMINAR 2015/2016 Gnothi Seauton Know Thyself : Conceptions of Self-Consciousness in German Idealism, Semantic Theory, and Psychoanalysis KALAMAZOO COLLEGE PROFESSOR: Chris Latiolais Philosophy Department Kalamazoo College Humphrey House #202 Telephone # 337-7076 Offices Hours: Monday: 10:30 11:30 Tuesday: 11:30 12:30 Wednesday: 1:15 2:15 By Appointment. COURSE DESCRPTION: The imperative to know thyself, which addresses basic questions about human being in the world, lies at the foundation of western mythology, religion, and philosophy. In the Greek enlightenment, self-understanding knowing what or who I am and world-understanding knowing one s placement in the world are intimately interconnected. It s hard to overestimate the extent to which all questions in philosophy return, in some fashion or another, to this very question. Famously, the imperative or, better, caution, Gnothi Seauton written above the entrance to the Oracle to Zeus at Delphi forewarns those who seek answers from the Sybil to know how to interpret what is prophesied about one, making selfknowledge largely a matter of rightly reading what is said, written, or otherwise configured in one s life as if ignorance functions predominately in one s inability to understand or read one s own situation in the world. Of course, the ancient Greeks understood the forces at work in human life as multiple, different, competing, and yet taken together determinative of one s life course: namely, as impersonal fate, personal agency, and the intervention of individual gods whose purposes were quite often at odds. Modern philosophy was formed by a broad and sweeping rejection of impersonal fate, on the one hand, and personal divine intervention, on the other, as actual forces at work in human life, retaining only personal agency as the locus of responsibility an agency, however, subject to indifferent anonymous forces of the natural and social dimensions of modern life. The central theme of this course is self-consciousness, the way in which knowledge of self and world are inextricably interconnected. In this course, we will limit ourselves to three specific areas of contemporary scholarship: German idealist accounts of intentionality or mindedness, contemporary semantic theorizing about linguistic selfreference, and, finally, 20 th -century Neo-structuralist psychoanalytic theory. There is a fascinating convergence among these three disparate areas of contemporary scholarship in accounts of selfconsciousness: namely, that consciousness and self-consciousness are two inseparable sides of the same unitary phenomenon: namely, human intentionality. This is decidedly not to say, however, that our consciousness, our outlook upon and involvement with the world, is transparent to itself. On the contrary, the way in which consciousness-of-self is conceptually articulated in these three areas of scholarship condemns human agents to the essential opacity, density, thickness, or depth of our world involvement, an involvement that is, taken as a whole, constitutively removed from conscious availability. Quite

surprisingly, self-consciousness becomes the imperative of executive self-configuration or selfdetermination within the world, where our world involvement simply precludes the possibility of ever consciously grasping our entire openness to, or involvement with, the world as such. Dramatically stated, in the traditions we will study in this course, self-consciousness introduces a constitutive ignorance, unknowability, or cognitive displacement at the very heart of subjectivity itself a blind spot to the eye or non-sense to the ear, if you will. Moreover and most importantly, rather than diminishing our responsibility in conducting our own lives, this epistemic unavailability of the totality of our situatedness in the world dramatically sharpens and intensifies our taking responsibility for our beliefs, desires, and actions. Ancient Greek tragedy is dedicated to aesthetically addressing this ambiguous, paradoxical, and poignant nature of the human condition, a condition that demands action amidst forces that are simply not under our conscious control, though eerily interconnected with our agency. Perhaps psychoanalysis represents our most vibrant modern successor to Greek tragedy, it being no accident that Freud develops psychoanalysis in close proximity to the wisdom of the ancients so evident in their tragedic rituals and performances. Freud s discovery of the unconscious and its radical linguistic reformulation at the hands of Jacques Lacan re-assert, in altered modern form, Greek sensitivity to the peculiar intertwining of contingency and necessity, chance and fate, accident and inevitability. The Cartesian understanding of consciousness as consciousness-of-an-object forces a peculiarly misleading conception of self-consciousness as the self s taking itself as an object, a sort of mental gymnastics or contortionism that generates an infinite regress, since any object about which the subject is aware leaves out the very subject of such awareness, generating the endless and fruitless regress. The three areas of contemporary scholarship we examine in this course construe self-consciousness, not as the passive awareness of a given self object, but instead as the activity of holding oneself open to the world. This shift from noun to verb, from a given thing to a generative and executive activity, from having an object to taking oneself as confronting something, is initiated by Kant s famous Copernican Turn in philosophy, a radical reconceptualization of the possibility of knowledge based upon the fact of human freedom or spontaneity. Famously, Kant asserted that the objectivity of our mindedness is grounded in conditions of its subjectivity. The experiencing I stands under the imperative to comprise all of its representations. The transcendental unity of apperception is the principle of the necessary possibility of the I s attaching itself (sich haften) to each of its representations (A105-108). This founding imperative of the mind s directedness to the world, Kant argues, is based upon the constitutive unavailability of mind s presence to itself as a phenomenal object in the world. As the synthetic activity of self-configuration, the I knows itself, not as an object, but instead as carry out, conducting, or executing such cognitive operations. The implications of Kant s argument against a transcendental psychology, given in his famous Transcendental Dialectic, are far-reaching. We will track this far-reaching reconceptualization of the human understanding of self and world in the 19 th -Century critical reception of Kant s transcendental idealism through contemporary semantic theory, on the one hand, and psychoanalytic practice, on the other. In Kant and the Semantic Problem from Kant and the Analytic Tradition, Robert Hanna presents the working parts of Kant s idealist account of the human cognition of objects (Erkenntniss) in the Critique of Pure Reason, framing Kant s theory of knowledge in contemporary semantic terms. Hanna staunchly defends the basic framework of Kant s account of objective representations or experience (Erfahrung), connecting it to the tradition of 20 th -century Anglo-American analytic philosophy. In this important work, Hanna demonstrates that Kant conceives of consciousness of objects as essentially selfconsciousness, as a form of active, synthesizing, rule-governed executive cognitive processing. Simply put, the self is not a thing but, instead, an activity or, better, the execution of designated functions of unifying representations into full fledged judgment (Urteil) in modern parlance, a truth-evaluable proposition. By familiarizing ourselves with this basic model of the executive cognitive processing required to generate propositional content, we become familiar with the locus classicus of our contemporary cognitive sciences, with all of their attendant difficulties and problems. We then turn to Sebastian Roedel s far-reaching explication of self-consciousness in Kant s theoretical and practical philosophy, Kant s accounts of belief and action, and finally to his provocative account of our access to the second-person perspective of those with whom we interaction in an I-thou manner. Roedel s central claim is that human consciousness just is self-consciousness, full stop! Unique to human life is our rational capacity to raise questions about what we ought to believe or do, where our answer to such theoretical and practical questions causes, respectively, beliefs and actions. It s customary in contemporary philosophy to distinguish between two types of explanations, two ways of asking the question of why someone believes or does something: namely, causal explanation, on the one hand, and

normatively justification, on the other the real and the ideal, as Kant and Hegel would say. The core of Roedel s account is that the explanation of human belief and action requires the identification of rational capacities (Vermoegen) or powers (Kraefte) that allow us to confront the normative question of what we ought to believe or do, where our answers to such theoretical and practical questions causes belief and action. Explaining the human capacities to either form beliefs about the world or competently intervene in it unifies these two dimensions, the normative and the causal indeed, in such a way that the subject of belief and action is essentially conscious of itself as this very executive activity. The capacity to engage in theoretical and practical reason is structured as a form of self-reference, where the referential relation is not sustained by sensibility (alone) but, in contrast, the intellect. As Roedel puts it, the self refers to itself, not via sensibility but spontaneously, via the executive and generative capacity of the human mind. It s important to appreciate that such theoretical and practical human capacities are dedicated to forming true beliefs about the world, on the one hand, and, on the other, acting with either instrumental efficiency or moral rightness. Nevertheless, a capacity, precisely as a competency, can misfire. Having the capacity to raise questions about truth and rightness by no means guarantees that humans will form true beliefs or act rightly; instead, the capacity demands that we take stock of such congruity or incongruity. In short, such capacities cannot be explained without presupposing that they are dedicated to the unity of causal and normative dimensions of such human abilities. The Neo-empiricist tenor of so much Anglo- American analytic philosophy misconstrues such capacities, largely on the basis of continuing influence of Cartesian-style arguments from illusion, which drive a wedge between causal explanation and normative justification. Roedel s key point in this regard is that such capacities are dedicated to the unity of the causal and justificatory and that this unity of the order of reason is severely misunderstood by Neoempiricist models of mind. Roedel s painstaking clarification of this essentially idealist model of mind as self-consciousness has, or so he argues, far-reaching and surprising consequences for our conceptualization of second-person relations. If human agents refer to themselves, not via sensory receptivity, but instead via intellectual spontaneity, then reference to a second person is likewise via spontaneity. Simply put, the way in which I am present to myself and the way in which a second person is present to me are the same insofar as each demands the exercise of spontaneity. The famous problem of other minds generated by broadly empiricist models of perception i.e. only the body of another is present to me, not the mind, which must be inferred on the basis of the latter is, Roedel demonstrates, a pseudo problem. What s so remarkable about this closing chapter of the book is its unflinching emphasis upon the essentially social nature of human mindedness, not because two formerly integrated minds interact, but instead because what it is to be minded is to participate in a shared order of reason. Simply put, the demand for social cooperation does not generate rational structures; instead, rationality as such is mutual recognition among humans. From this perspective, much of the intersubjectivist turn in European-Continental philosophy most famously called for and carried out by Jurgen Habermas s theory of communicative action misconstrues the relationship between subjectivity and intersubjectivity, self-consciousness and consciousness of others. In the next portion of the course, we examine Francois Recanati s fascinating work on subjectivity and experience in contemporary semantic and pragmatic theorizing. Recanati s staunchly defends an approach in the philosophy of language, truth-conditional pragmatics, that moves beyond the traditional formal semantic approach characteristic of the first half of the 20 th Century. The key to understanding Recanati s philosophy of language is his emphatic and uncompromising demand to distribute the semantic content of utterances across the standard, dual components of the speech act: namely, across illocutionary force, on the one hand, and propositional content, on the other. The Duality Thesis claims that both force and content are potential carriers of meaning, and the Distribution Thesis is the claim that both illocutionary force and propositional content do indeed contribute distinctive elements to the encompassing content of the whole utterance. Traditional truth-conditional formal semantics is committed to minimizing the contribution of force the so-called pragmatic dimension of the utterance to utterance content, focusing almost exclusively upon propositional content. Decrying the fallacy of misplaced information, Recanati points out that formal semantic misplaces important dimensions of overall utterance content into the propositional content. The Duality and Distribution theses ensure that utterance content distributes across the dual components of speech acts. So too in the Recanati s philosophy of mind his account of intentionality the content of the experience or aim of the action distribute across the dual components of both act and content, highlighting the active nature of the experiencer or agent whose psychological attitude contributes elements of meaning not contained in the explicit content of the act. For instance, the causal self-referentiality built into both perception and action does not, Recanati insists, belong to the explicit

content of the perception or action but, instead, to the psychological force of the act. In this fashion, the entire intentional content of perception of action distributes across the dual components of perception and action, highlighting the active, executive nature of the subject who assumes such different psychological attitudes to the world. Recanati s model of perception and action which insists upon the two dimensional, force-content determination of intentional content provides a precise way of locating the essentially self-conscious nature of human mindedness. I want to suggest that consciousness of explicit content is always connected with self-consciousness of the subject s active attitude toward such content. In short, the force/content distinction captures important dimensions of the consciousness/self-consciousness distinction. Roedel demonstrates that the formation of belief and the conduct of action consists of an active, executive, generative accomplishment that combines both normative and causal dimensions. In both perception and action, what one explicitly perceives or does is accompanied by how the subject relates herself to such conceptual content, producing a double conscious/self-conscious structure that is, I am suggesting, similar to Recanati s analysis of content and force. The unfolding of perception and the conduct of actions consist of two interactive layers of meaning force and content the former implicit and the latter explicit, with the proviso that implicit meaning can be made explicit and therein domiciled in expanding propositional content. Our excursion into the semantic and pragmatic theorizing provides us with precise terms for analyzing the complex, multilayered, tandem nature of the determination of intentional content of perception, action, and speech. In the final section of the course we follow out our theme of self-consciousness in the domain of Lacanian psychoanalytic theory as interpreted by the Slovenian philosopher, Slavoj Zizek. Unlike Kantian idealism, which is broadly focused on epistemological and moral viewpoints, Lacanian analysis is exclusively focused on desire, erotic happiness (widely understood), and the unconscious, which manifests itself in symptomatic behaviors. Zizek has devoted his career to reading German idealism through the conceptual lens of Lacanian psychoanalytic theory, and this orientation greatly facilitates our reflective comparison of different areas of scholarship. This exegetical approach allows us to simply contextualize Roedel s idealist account of self-consciousness and Recanati s truth-conditional pragmatic account of intentionality into the domain of psychoanalysis. In short, Zizek offers a psychoanalytic reading of the idealist account of self-consciousness and pragmatic account of intentionality. According to Zizek, the fundamental operation of German idealism is the formation of a split subject divided between selfimages and self-symbols, on the one hand, and, on the other, that dimension of human life that escapes such imaginary and symbolic representations, which Lacan calls the real. As Henry Allison famously puts it, human beings incorporate what they perceive, believe, or do within conceptual content that articulates what it is that we confront, assume, or do, installing us within the articulated space of reasons. Zizek equates Allison s Incorporation Thesis with the psychoanalytic concept of castration: Human beings are in this sense subject to, or inscribed within language or conceptual self-articulation that is, selfimages and self-symbols constitute our primary access to ourselves and its precisely this cut or excision into any presumably immediate relation to our being that counts as the formation of the unconscious. It s fascinating that this dialogue between idealist and psychoanalytic models of mind appear to install the unconscious at the very heart of self-consciousness. Self-consciousness is structured by a constitutive blindspot located at its center. Another important feature of Lacan s account of the subject is his distinction between the subject of the enunciation and the subject of the enunciated, which is entirely isomorphic with our familiar pragmatic distinction between the force and the content of the utterance or state of mind. In the same way that pragmatics distinguishes between the one who speaks (force) and the one who is spoken about (propositional content), so too psychoanalysis demands that we distinguish, in the clinical setting of someone talking about herself, the locus of the speaker, on the one hand, and the content of what is said about the speaker, on the other with the overall concern being whether the analysand can stand independently in the first-person position of responsibility vis-à-vis another. During his middle period, Lacan famously claims that the subject begins analysis by speaking about himself without speaking to you, or by speaking to you but not about himself. When he can speak to you about himself, the analysis will be over (E, 373). The distinctive type of normative ideal of health or well being that defines psychoanalytic practice is precisely this coincidence of the first-person force provisionally coinciding with the propositional content of what one says about oneself to another. Here we see an important psychoanalytic appropriation of Recanati s account of the duality and distribution of meaning determination across force and content: only a full-fledged pragmatic analysis of utterance meaning allows

us to capture the complexity of speech and human desire, which is characteristically a symptomatic, transference laden exchange between a desiring speaker and a more or less fantasized interlocutor. Zizek draws upon these fascinating parallels between German idealism and Lacanian analysis to work out a complex account of human subjectivity. Zizek develops his conception of desiring indeed driven human subjectivity to underscore the fraught nature of political agency within modern social and systemic complexity. Like critical theorists, Zizek is concerned with agency amidst global capitalism, the worldwide web, pleasure-driven consumer society, religious extremism, and political disempowerment. His overall goal is to identify various forms of contemporary agonistic politics that are alike compromised, unresponsive the crisis of 21 st -century capitalism, and ultimately coopted. A good deal of what he says about such political factions hinges upon a lucid understanding of how desire and politics often produce imaginary foes and friends, political allergies and allegiances, then, that are more symptomatic of the crisis of modernity than responsive to it. More specifically still, Zizek draws attention to various basic options or approaches to the crisis of modernity created by the ontological options of materialism and idealism, along the vertical axis, and methodological options of historical and ahistorical, along the horizontal axis: namely and respectively, postmodern discursive historicism, reductive scientific naturalism, New Age Buddhism, and the philosophy of finitude. We will examine how the idealist model of self-consciousness and pragmatic model of intentionality, which we developed in the first part of the course, have important repercussions for critical social theory. REQUIRED TEXTS: Robert Hanna. Kant and the Semantic Problem, Chapter One of Kant the Foundations of Analytic Philosophy, Oxford, England: Oxford University Press, 2001. Roedel, Sebastian. Self-Consciousness. Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press, 2007. Recanati, Francois. Perspectival Thought: A Plea for (Moderate) Relativism. Oxford, England: Oxford University Press, 2000: o Introduction o Moderate Relativism: The Framework o Relativism and Indexicality o Content and Mode o Immunity to Error through Misidentification, Zizek, Slavoj. Less Than Nothing: Hegel and the Shadow of Dialectical Materialism. London: Verso 2012: o Fichte s Choice o Not Only as Substance, but also as Subject o Suture and Pure Difference o Objects, Object Everywhere o The Foursome of Struggle, Historicity, Will... and Gelassenheit BACKGROUND TEXTS: Fink, Bruce. Against Understanding: Commentary and Critique in a Lacanian Key: Volume One. New York, NY: Routledge, 2013. Fink, Bruce. Against Understanding: Cases and Commentary in a Lacanian Key: Volume Two. New York, NY: Routledge, 2013. Fink, Bruce, et. al eds. Reading Seminar XI: Lacan's Four Fundamental Concepts of Psychoanalysis. Albany, New York: SUNY Press, 1996. Fink, Bruce, et. al eds. Reading Seminars I and II: Lacan's Return to Freud. Albany, New York: SUNY Press, 1996. Fink, Bruce. A Clinical Introduction to Lacanian Psychoanalysis: Theory and Technique. Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press, 1997. Fink, Bruce. Lacan to the Letter: Reading Écrits Closely. Minneapolis, Minnesota: University of Minnesota Press, 2004. Fink, Bruce. Fundamentals of Psychoanalytic Technique: A Lacanian Approach. New York, NY:

W. W. Norton & Company, 2007. Bowie, Andrew. Aesthetics and Subjectivity: From Kant to Nietzsche. Manchester, England: Manchester University Press, 2003. Brockelman, Thomas P. Zizek and Heidegger: The Question Concerning Techno-Capitalism. New York, NY: Continuum International Publishing Company, 2008. Bohman, James. 1997. Two Versions of the Linguistic Turn: Habermas and Poststructuralism, in Passerin d Entreves 1997. Frank, Manfred. The Subject and the Text: Essays on Literary Theory and Philosophy. Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press, 1997. Eagle, Morris. From Classical to Contemporary Psychoanalysis: A Critique and Integration. Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press, 2011. Eagle, Morris. Recent Developments in Psychoanalysis: A Critique Evaluation. Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press, 1984. Lacan, Jacques Ecrits: http://www.mediafire.com/?3fzb5niljm2 Zizek, Slavoj. Tarrying with the Negative: Kant, Hegel, and the Critique of Ideology. Durham: Duke University Press, 1993.

INTRODUCTION TO SENIOR SEMINAR: READING SCHEDULE FALL TERM Week One: o Introduction to Senior Seminar. o Preliminary Discussion of Course Themes KANT S FUNDAMENTAL QUESTION IN THE CRITIQUE OF PURE REASON: Week Two: o Hanna: Kant and the Semantic Problem SEBASTIAN ROEDEL S ACCOUNT OF SELF-CONSCIOUSNESS: Week Three: o Roedel: Preface o First-Person Thought Week Four: o Roedel: Action and the First Person Week Five: o Roedel: Belief and the First Person Week Six: o Roedel: Reason, Freedom, and True Materialism Week Seven: o Roedel: Receptive Knowledge Week Eight. o Roedel: The Second Person CONTEMPORARY SEMANTIC AND PRAGMATIC THEORY: FRANCOIS RECANATI S MODERATE RELATIVISM & THE SOLIDIFICATION OF KANTIAN THEMES IN THE PHILOSOSPHY OF LANGUAGE: Week Nine: o Recanati: Introduction Week Ten: o Recanati: Moderate Relativism: The Framework

READING SCHEDULE WINTER TERM CONTEMPORARY SEMANTIC AND PRAGMATIC THEORY: FRANCOIS RECANATI S MODERATE RELATIVISM & THE SOLIDIFICATION OF KANTIAN THEMES IN THE PHILOSOSPHY OF LANGUAGE: Week One: o Recanati: Relativism and Indexicality Content and Mode Week Two: o Recanati: Immunity to Error through Misidentification, CONTEMPORARY PSYCHOANALYTIC CONCEPTIONS OF SELF-CONSCIOUSNESS: SLAVOJ ZIZEK S LACANIAN READING OF HEGEL S CONCEPTION OF SUBJECTIVITY AND ABSOLUTE KNOWING: SELF-CONSCIOUSENSS AND DESIRE Week Three: Fichte on Self-consciousness: o Zizek: Fichte s Choice Week Four: Hegel on Self-Consciousness: o Zizek: Not Only as Substance, but also as Subject Week Five: Lacan on Self-consciousness, the unconscious, and Subjectivity: o Zizek: Suture and Pure Difference Week Six: o Zizek: Lacan on Object Relations: Objects, Object Everywhere Week Seven: Heidegger s on Dasein, Sein, and the Ontological Difference: o Zizek: The Foursome of Struggle, Historicity, Will... and Gelassenheit Week Eight: Open Week Nine: Open Week Ten: Open Finals Week: Open