CHARLES T WOLFE SCOUTS THE ANSWERS

Similar documents
THE LOGICAL FORM OF BIOLOGICAL OBJECTS

1/6. The Anticipations of Perception

observation and conceptual interpretation

Reductionism Versus Holism: A Perspective on Perspectives. Mr. K. Zuber. November 1, Sir Wilfrid Laurier Secondary School

REVIEW ARTICLE IDEAL EMBODIMENT: KANT S THEORY OF SENSIBILITY

Philip Kitcher and Gillian Barker, Philosophy of Science: A New Introduction, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2014, pp. 192

What do our appreciation of tonal music and tea roses, our acquisition of the concepts

Philosophical Background to 19 th Century Modernism

Necessity in Kant; Subjective and Objective

INTRODUCTION TO NONREPRESENTATION, THOMAS KUHN, AND LARRY LAUDAN

PAUL REDDING S CONTINENTAL IDEALISM (AND DELEUZE S CONTINUATION OF THE IDEALIST TRADITION) Sean Bowden

Darwinian populations and natural selection, by Peter Godfrey-Smith, New York, Oxford University Press, Pp. viii+207.

Phenomenology Glossary

Natural Genetic Engineering and Natural Genome Editing, Salzburg, July

UNIT SPECIFICATION FOR EXCHANGE AND STUDY ABROAD


Journal of Nonlocality Round Table Series Colloquium #4

THE EVOLUTION OF RELIGION AND THE EVOLUTION OF CULTURE TAYLOR THIEL DAVIS. B.Sc., The University of Georgia, 2000 M.A., Tufts University, 2011

WHAT S LEFT OF HUMAN NATURE? A POST-ESSENTIALIST, PLURALIST AND INTERACTIVE ACCOUNT OF A CONTESTED CONCEPT. Maria Kronfeldner

Bas C. van Fraassen, Scientific Representation: Paradoxes of Perspective, Oxford University Press, 2008.

ARISTOTLE AND THE UNITY CONDITION FOR SCIENTIFIC DEFINITIONS ALAN CODE [Discussion of DAVID CHARLES: ARISTOTLE ON MEANING AND ESSENCE]

Kuhn s Notion of Scientific Progress. Christian Damböck Institute Vienna Circle University of Vienna

A Comprehensive Critical Study of Gadamer s Hermeneutics

Categories and Schemata

Philosophy of Science: The Pragmatic Alternative April 2017 Center for Philosophy of Science University of Pittsburgh ABSTRACTS

Kuhn Formalized. Christian Damböck Institute Vienna Circle University of Vienna

SYSTEM-PURPOSE METHOD: THEORETICAL AND PRACTICAL ASPECTS Ramil Dursunov PhD in Law University of Fribourg, Faculty of Law ABSTRACT INTRODUCTION

Natural Kinds and Concepts: A Pragmatist and Methodologically Naturalistic Account

Quine s Two Dogmas of Empiricism. By Spencer Livingstone

Holism, Concept Individuation, and Conceptual Change

On Structured Societies and Morphogenetic Fields: A Response to Joseph Bracken

Objectives: Performance Objective: By the end of this session, the participants will be able to discuss the weaknesses of various theories that suppor

Social Mechanisms and Scientific Realism: Discussion of Mechanistic Explanation in Social Contexts Daniel Little, University of Michigan-Dearborn

du Châtelet s ontology: element, corpuscle, body

KANT S TRANSCENDENTAL LOGIC

WHITEHEAD'S PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE AND METAPHYSICS

A Confusion of the term Subjectivity in the philosophy of Mind *

Lithuanian Philosophy in Exile

Lecture 3 Kuhn s Methodology

PHI 3240: Philosophy of Art

Kant s Critique of Judgment

UNIT SPECIFICATION FOR EXCHANGE AND STUDY ABROAD

Challenging Times. Introduction. Evolution of Galilean Newtonian Scientific Thinking

Art, Vision, and the Necessity of a Post-Analytic Phenomenology

GV958: Theory and Explanation in Political Science, Part I: Philosophy of Science (Han Dorussen)

that would join theoretical philosophy (metaphysics) and practical philosophy (ethics)?

Thomas Kuhn's "The Structure of Scientific Revolutions"

Logic and Philosophy of Science (LPS)


The Moral Animal. By Robert Wright. Vintage Books, Reviewed by Geoff Gilpin

In Defense of the Contingently Nonconcrete

Is Genetic Epistemology of Any Interest for Semiotics?

University of Groningen. Holism and reductionism in biology and ecology Looijen, Richard

Habit, Semeiotic Naturalism, and Unity among the Sciences Aaron Wilson

Science and Values: Holism and Radical Environmental Activism

Creative Actualization: A Meliorist Theory of Values

GRADUATE SEMINARS

The Language Revolution Russell Marcus Fall Class #7 Final Thoughts on Frege on Sense and Reference

Keywords: Canguilhem; Vitalism; Biology; Logic of life; Autopoietic/Heteropoietic; Analysis/Synthesis; Living individual

KINDS (NATURAL KINDS VS. HUMAN KINDS)

Scientific Philosophy

Four Characteristic Research Paradigms

Scientific Revolutions as Events: A Kuhnian Critique of Badiou

What Can Experimental Philosophy Do? David Chalmers

The Philosophy of Language. Frege s Sense/Reference Distinction

In Search of Mechanisms, by Carl F. Craver and Lindley Darden, 2013, The University of Chicago Press.

The Debate on Research in the Arts

Improving Scientific Language

My thesis is that not only the written symbols and spoken sounds are different, but also the affections of the soul (as Aristotle called them).

MAURICE MANDELBAUM HISTORY, MAN, & REASON A STUDY IN NINETEENTH-CENTURY THOUGHT THE JOHNS HOPKINS PRESS: BALTIMORE AND LONDON

The Shimer School Core Curriculum

Published in: International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 29(2) (2015):

Aristotle. Aristotle. Aristotle and Plato. Background. Aristotle and Plato. Aristotle and Plato

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

Environmental Ethics: From Theory to Practice

The Human Intellect: Aristotle s Conception of Νοῦς in his De Anima. Caleb Cohoe

SOCI 421: Social Anthropology

The Superorganism: The Beauty, Elegance, And Strangeness Of Insect Societies Free Download PDF

Mixed Methods: In Search of a Paradigm

Ontological Categories. Roberto Poli

2 Unified Reality Theory

Guide to the Republic as it sets up Plato s discussion of education in the Allegory of the Cave.

TROUBLING QUALITATIVE INQUIRY: ACCOUNTS AS DATA, AND AS PRODUCTS

Kant Prolegomena to any Future Metaphysics, Preface, excerpts 1 Critique of Pure Reason, excerpts 2 PHIL101 Prof. Oakes updated: 9/19/13 12:13 PM

Ontology as a formal one. The language of ontology as the ontology itself: the zero-level language

PROFESSORS: Bonnie B. Bowers (chair), George W. Ledger ASSOCIATE PROFESSORS: Richard L. Michalski (on leave short & spring terms), Tiffany A.

Foundations in Data Semantics. Chapter 4

The Nature of Time. Humberto R. Maturana. November 27, 1995.

Qualitative Design and Measurement Objectives 1. Describe five approaches to questions posed in qualitative research 2. Describe the relationship betw

Chapter 2: The Early Greek Philosophers MULTIPLE CHOICE

AN ALTERNATIVE TO KITCHER S THEORY OF CONCEPTUAL PROGRESS AND HIS ACCOUNT OF THE CHANGE OF THE GENE CONCEPT. Ingo Brigandt

EXPANDED COURSE DESCRIPTIONS UC DAVIS PHILOSOPHY DEPARTMENT SPRING, Michael Glanzberg MWF 10:00-10:50a.m., 176 Everson CRNs:

Emotions from the Perspective of Analytic Aesthetics

Sidestepping the holes of holism

Deep Ecology A New Paradigm 19 September 2012 Page 1 of 6

Action, Criticism & Theory for Music Education

1/8. The Third Paralogism and the Transcendental Unity of Apperception

An Alternative to Kitcher s Theory of Conceptual Progress and His Account of the Change of the Gene Concept

No General Structure

The erratically fine-grained metaphysics of functional kinds in technology and biology

Transcription:

forum/organism The organism reality or fiction? CHARLES T WOLFE SCOUTS THE ANSWERS 96 What is an organism? A state of matter, or a particular type of living being chosen as an experimental object, like the fruit fly or the roundworm c. elegans, which are model organisms? Organisms are real, in a trivial sense, since flies and Tasmanian tigers and Portuguese men-o-war are (or were, in the case of the Tasmanian tiger) as real as tables and chairs and planets. But at the same time, they are meaningful constructs, as when we describe Hegel or Whitehead as philosophers of organism in the sense that they insist on the irreducible properties of wholes sometimes, living wholes in particular. In addition, the idea of organism is sometimes appealed to in a polemical way, as when biologists or philosophers angrily oppose a more holistic sense of organism to a seemingly cold-hearted, analytic and dissective attitude associated with mechanism and reductionism. We murder to dissect, or as the famous physicist Niels Bohr warned, we may kill the organism with our too-detailed measurements. Historically, the word organism emerged in the late seventeenth and early eighteenth centuries, in particular, in the debate between the philosopher and polymath Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz and the chemist and physician Georg- Ernest Stahl, the author of a 1708 essay On the difference between mechanism and organism. Both Leibniz and Stahl agree that organisms are not the same as mere mechanisms, but they differ on how to account for this difference. For Leibniz, it is more of a difference in complexity (for him, organisms are machines which are machines down to their smallest parts), whereas for Stahl, the organism is a type of whole governed by the soul (at all levels of our bodily functioning, from the way I blink if an object comes too close to my eyes, to my fighting off tpm 4TH QUARTER 2014

forum/organism Mechanical duck (via Wikimedia Commons) an infection, to fully involuntary processes like digestion). After this one doesn t find the term much used in our sense until the late eighteenth century. It occurs rarely in the Enlightenment (people spoke more of organised bodies or organisation ); thus Kant s insistence, in his third Critique, on the unique kind of purposive arrangement found in organisms, uses the language of organised bodies. A curious feature about the notion of organism is that it is located from the outset at the intersection of philosophical inquiry into the nature of living beings (Leibniz, Kant like Aristotle before them) and properly biological reflection. For this is also the period when biology as a science is emerging. Some of the motivation was a reaction to the popularity of the notion of machine. The mechanical philosophy of the seventeenth century Boyle, Hobbes, Descartes but also attempts in medicine to study bodies and body parts as if they were mechanical rested on the notion that natural phenomena result from interactions between material particles governed by the laws of mechanics. This enabled the formulation of laws of motion and the invention of particular mechanisms, the latter allowing one to explain particular phenomena. One thinks of the popularity of clockwork metaphors, but also of actual automata, designed to replicate the functioning of animals (as in the case of Vaucanson s duck). Aside from the classic philosophers mentioned above, philosophers in the twentieth century have had a certain interest in the concept of organism. Originally, the interest came especially from phenomenologically motivated authors such as Kurt Goldstein, Hans Jonas, and on the other side of the Rhine, Henri Bergson and Gilbert Simondon. (Whitehead is hard to fit in a neat conceptual box here.). In biology, 97 4TH QUARTER 2014 tpm

With the rise of genetics the organism was consigned to the dustbin of history forum/organism 98 for a long time with the rise of genetics and popular concepts such as the selfish gene, the organism was viewed as consigned to the dustbin of history. Any privileged status granted to irreducible wholes will disappear on this view in favour of the molecularisation of biological entities. Thus the journal American Zoologist asked in 1989, Do organisms exist?, and described the organism as the Phoenix of biology. As the distinguished philosopher of biology David Hull put it, both scientists and philosophers take ontological reduction for granted. Organisms are nothing but atoms, and that is that. Yet the story does not end there. Biologists interested in evolution, but also developmental processes, ecosystems, and problem cases such as coral reefs or symbiotic organisms, have begun to ask questions again concerning the nature of biological identity and individuality, which as a side effect brings back in a role for philosophy. Perhaps it is a false or empty promise to insist that the world is made up of atoms or genes and replicators, and nothing else; perhaps we should speak, with the biologists Queller and Strassman, of degrees of organismality. The degree of reality of the concept of organism, then, is bound up with a variety of other issues. One is the status of biology and biological entities with regard to physics: how do we decide what gets to be the most real sorts of entities? Another is the role for philosophy. For there is a kind of symbiotic or is it parasitical? relationship between the metaphysician looking to examples from the biological world to support her claims about identity, and the biologist appealing to metaphysical notions to differentiate the systems she studies from atoms, or machines, or numbers. Thirdly, the more ideological implications of the organism concept tie it directly to what sort of position we take on the relation between humanity and scientific explanations. Let s distinguish between strong and weak conceptions of organism, where the weak conception simply holds that organisms are types of organisation with some specific features, like homeostasis, which are not found in storms or supernovas, whereas the strong conception insists on a real, irreducible uniqueness of organisms and challenges our entire scientific world-picture on the basis thereof. Thus the defender of the strong concept of organism, not content to assert like Heidegger that science does not think and end it there, will try and shift the conflict into the territory of science, and will say that there should be a science of the organism itself, a holistic science, a new paradigm, which would overcome or refute the excessively reductionist paradigm we have been saddled with since the Scientific Revolution. The problem with all of this, whether or not one accepts the verdict of mainstream science that the organism in itself either does not exist or does not matter, is that this kind of defence or challenge has something very normative about it. It is in the name of a certain idea of value that tpm 4TH QUARTER 2014

one defends a particularity of living beings; think of the expression pro-life! To those who insist that there is something about life, the fact of life, and the unique features of living beings which almost prior to argument is a value, I would reply with Nietzsche s comment that Life is not an argument. Among the conditions of life might be error, a comment which harks back to old Epicurean themes (the world is composed of atoms and chance) but which can also be heard in Darwinian terms: the fact that one species rather than other survived has a dimension of accident to it. I suggest that a useful concept of organism, if we are to have one a concept of organism worth wanting, in Daniel Dennett s phrase will have to be compatible with a broad commitment to philosophical naturalism. That is, it will not seek to oppose organisms to the rest of physical nature, neither in terms of their possessing a mysterious inner life which other beings do not possess, nor because they possess a mysterious vital force. The word organism emerged in a debate between Leibniz and the chemist Georg- Ernest Stahl In some sense, as the great eighteenth-century French naturalist Buffon wrote, the organic is the most ordinary product of nature. Of course, if we push that notion of ordinariness too far, we lose sight of an interesting feature of organisms, including ourselves: that they live in their own environments. Lizards, finches, tarantulas, primates and humans all live in, interact with, and customise their environments which we can describe as meaningful (think e.g. of the bower bird): they are worlds. Rather than arguing over what is most real atoms and protons, or hearts and lungs it could be interesting to take account of the way in which organisms relate to the meaningful traits of their environment (this is partly discussed by biologists as niche construction ), since it is also our own doing. How do we decide what gets to be the most real? Rather than asserting that organisms are special because of their special relation between whole and parts (as in Aristotle s arresting image that a hand severed from the body is no longer a hand), or more empirically, organisms are special because they digest, sweat, fear, love, have high blood pressure or low blood sugar (a claim partly weakened by artificial constructions from Vaucanson s duck to Wim Delvoye s Cloaca ), we would be better off acknowledging that there is always an imaginative, and even a fictional component in our attempts to make sense of organisms. Even the most die-hard mechanists make use of analogies and models to understand that most complex of machines, the living body. A mechanical model is nothing else than a heuristic model designed to explain something about the object which strong organicists seek a monopoly on, Life. When Kant (in)famously declared that there will never be a Newton of even a mere blade of grass that is, that science, which he understood forum/organism 99 4TH QUARTER 2014 tpm

forum/organism 100 as mathematically specifiable mechanistic science, could never account for or discover the laws governing organic beings or when Leibniz insisted that the difference between a machine of nature (his term for an organism) and an artificial machine is that a machine of nature, a living being, is a machine to infinity, they are both clinging to the idea of a certain special something, whether that be wonder tissue or selfhood, which constructions and reconstructions cannot grasp. In contrast, we should recall that an important dimension of mechanical models is their heuristic dimension: mechanisms are also built so as to see what is inside them. If organisms are particular, complex cases of mechanisms, this does not amount to the rather knee-jerk reductionist insistence that Life does not exist, or that there are only atoms or genes. Let me put this point differently, and draw out some of its implications. First, organisms are not free from our acts of imaginative construction. Second, there is no absolute separation between organisms and mechanisms, or organisms and the physical world as a whole. Third, if our desire to preserve the uniqueness of flesh-and-blood, living, breathing, suffering and/or joyous entities over and against an imagined cold, dead, inert Necropolis takes the form of a list of irreducible empirical features, we are not on the right track. For one thing, we do not have any absolute, empirical or conceptual criterion with which we could distinguish a living being from a non-living being, whether the integrity of the organism, its self-regulation (homeostasis), or metabolism. These features are always post facto observations, starting from within a temporal process. In that sense, the relation between living and non-living, Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz, oils on wood by Johann Friedrich Wentzel c1700 (via Wikimedia Commons) organism and machine, is an empirical relation, which does not allow one to posit qualitative differences between laws of nature. As the theoretical biologist Robert Rosen says, there is as yet no list of tests, characteristics or criteria we can apply to a given material system that can decide whether that system is an organism or not ; the decision as to whether a given system is an organism is entirely a subjective, intuitive one, based on criteria that have so far resisted formalization. Any strong claims about the reality of organisms will be based on (a) heuristic fiction(s)! The tpm 4TH QUARTER 2014

latter phrase is meant to convey, also, that organisms are a cognitive construct of our minds: in order to be able to understand an entity we need to project certain features onto it; but these features should not be held to be constitutive of certain regions of the real. Those of us who are fond of Darwinian flourishes would add that it may be a survival trait to be able to read certain organisms as organisms rather than as bundles of molecules. Thus, in an evocative example suggested by Dennett, if I am being pursued by a tiger in a jungle, it is a better idea for me to view that tiger as an organism as a total, interconnected system of parts with unified functions and goals, including eating me rather than as a set of atoms or molecules which I try to calculate the laws of: if I view it in the latter way, the chances of my making it out alive are much reduced. Thus, seeing the world, or at least parts of the world, from an organismic standpoint would be a competitive advantage. The category of organism has returned, if not to centre stage then at least to the horizon of the active interests of biologists whether they are concerned with evolution, ecosystems, systems biology, physiology, developmental processes and the like and philosophers concerned either with what the life sciences tell us about some of our fundamental preoccupations, and/ or with classic metaphysical problems like individuality and personal identity. In what sense am I one with the bacteria in my gut? In what sense is a coral reef one organism, or colony individuals like the Portuguese man-o-war, or symbiotic cases like the squid which ingests phosphorescent bacteria so that it can hunt at night, rendered invisible by the luminescence on its back? The other question I have discussed, concerning, not the individuality of organisms but their reality what is different, or special about them as compared to machines, or physical Nature as a whole, including as it pertains to the old what is Life? question (where the difference is more, a living body versus a corpse ) has faded away, in comparison with that of individuality. But if such a question were asked, we Organisms are not free from our acts of imaginative construction might say that the organism is nothing other than the production of a vital artificiality or fiction; and it is never alone: an organism can only be a paradigmatic individual in and through its relation to a population, a group or an environment as a whole. If there is nothing unique about organisms over and against the rest of Nature; if, as Buffon thought, the organic is the most ordinary product of nature, what does exist is a certain approach to reality, a fiction, the way a particular bundle of living matter exists, feels joy and regret, remembers, ages and thereby briefly saturates a particular intersection in the great causal nexus of the world. Charles T Wolfe is a research fellow in philosophy at Ghent University, in Belgium forum/organism 101 4TH QUARTER 2014 tpm