PETER - PAUL VERBEEK. Beyond the Human Eye Technological Mediation and Posthuman Visions

Similar documents
Spatial Formations. Installation Art between Image and Stage.

1/6. The Anticipations of Perception

Heideggerian Ontology: A Philosophic Base for Arts and Humanties Education

A Comprehensive Critical Study of Gadamer s Hermeneutics

The Public Thing: On the Idea of a Politics of Artefacts

The Constitution Theory of Intention-Dependent Objects and the Problem of Ontological Relativism

Hans-Georg Gadamer, Truth and Method, 2d ed. transl. by Joel Weinsheimer and Donald G. Marshall (London : Sheed & Ward, 1989), pp [1960].

Varieties of Nominalism Predicate Nominalism The Nature of Classes Class Membership Determines Type Testing For Adequacy

The phenomenological tradition conceptualizes

The erratically fine-grained metaphysics of functional kinds in technology and biology

PROFESSION WITHOUT DISCIPLINE WOULD BE BLIND

Postphenomenology, Embodiment and Technics

Mixing Metaphors. Mark G. Lee and John A. Barnden

Theory or Theories? Based on: R.T. Craig (1999), Communication Theory as a field, Communication Theory, n. 2, May,

Naïve realism without disjunctivism about experience

Crystal-image: real-time imagery in live performance as the forking of time

Current Issues in Pictorial Semiotics

Metaphors we live by. Structural metaphors. Orientational metaphors. A personal summary

Theory or Theories? Based on: R.T. Craig (1999), Communication Theory as a field, Communication Theory, n. 2, May,

BDD-A Universitatea din București Provided by Diacronia.ro for IP ( :46:58 UTC)

Observations on the Long Take

observation and conceptual interpretation

Aesthetics and meaning

2014 HSC Visual Arts Marking Guidelines

Book Review. John Dewey s Philosophy of Spirit, with the 1897 Lecture on Hegel. Jeff Jackson. 130 Education and Culture 29 (1) (2013):

The red apple I am eating is sweet and juicy. LOCKE S EMPIRICAL THEORY OF COGNITION: THE THEORY OF IDEAS. Locke s way of ideas

REFERENCES. 2004), that much of the recent literature in institutional theory adopts a realist position, pos-

Student Performance Q&A: 2001 AP Music Theory Free-Response Questions

No Proposition can be said to be in the Mind, which it never yet knew, which it was never yet conscious of. (Essay I.II.5)

Strategies for Writing about Literature (from A Short Guide to Writing about Literature, Barnett and Cain)

Encoding/decoding by Stuart Hall

The Spell of the Sensuous Chapter Summaries 1-4 Breakthrough Intensive 2016/2017

SocioBrains THE INTEGRATED APPROACH TO THE STUDY OF ART

REVIEW ARTICLE IDEAL EMBODIMENT: KANT S THEORY OF SENSIBILITY

WHAT IS CALLED THINKING IN THE FOURTH INDUSTRIAL REVOLUTION?


Artifacts and Attachment: A Post-Script Philosophy of Mediation

Posthuman Exhibitionism. by Niekolaas Johannes Lekkerkerk

2015 Arizona Arts Standards. Theatre Standards K - High School

KINDS (NATURAL KINDS VS. HUMAN KINDS)

Brandom s Reconstructive Rationality. Some Pragmatist Themes

Early Modern Philosophy Locke and Berkeley. Lecture 2: Primary and Secondary Qualities

INTERVIEW: ONTOFORMAT Classical Paradigms and Theoretical Foundations in Contemporary Research in Formal and Material Ontology.

CHAPTER IV RETROSPECT

Phenomenology Glossary

ENVIRONMENTAL EXPERIENCE: Beyond Aesthetic Subjectivism and Objectivism

Kęstas Kirtiklis Vilnius University Not by Communication Alone: The Importance of Epistemology in the Field of Communication Theory.

A New Approach to the Paradox of Fiction Pete Faulconbridge

PRACTICE Midterm Examination SWU 252: Aesthetics for Life

Conclusion. One way of characterizing the project Kant undertakes in the Critique of Pure Reason is by

Michael Lüthy Retracing Modernist Praxis: Richard Shiff

Fractal Narrative About the Relationship Between Geometries and Technology and Its Impact on Narrative Spaces

1/10. Berkeley on Abstraction

Truth and Method in Unification Thought: A Preparatory Analysis

Incommensurability and Partial Reference

Reply to Stalnaker. Timothy Williamson. In Models and Reality, Robert Stalnaker responds to the tensions discerned in Modal Logic

Tourism. Reading Practice

High School Photography 1 Curriculum Essentials Document

Hamletmachine: The Objective Real and the Subjective Fantasy. Heiner Mueller s play Hamletmachine focuses on Shakespeare s Hamlet,

Narrating the Self: Parergonality, Closure and. by Holly Franking. hermeneutics focus attention on the transactional aspect of the aesthetic

Sound visualization through a swarm of fireflies

GLOSSARY for National Core Arts: Visual Arts STANDARDS

Reading paintings and poetry Astrid Lorange

Visual Argumentation in Commercials: the Tulip Test 1

Merleau-Ponty s Transcendental Project

On Recanati s Mental Files

The Human Intellect: Aristotle s Conception of Νοῦς in his De Anima. Caleb Cohoe

COLOUR IMAGERY: THE ROAD

Philosophy of sound, Ch. 1 (English translation)

Edward Winters. Aesthetics and Architecture. London: Continuum, 2007, 179 pp. ISBN

Postmodernism. thus one must review the central tenants of Enlightenment philosophy

Years 9 and 10 standard elaborations Australian Curriculum: Drama

Costin Lianu. Bucharest University. Keywords: Aristotle, semantics, images, perception, brands, branding, homo economicus

Early Modern Philosophy Locke and Berkeley. Lecture 6: Berkeley s Idealism II

Perception and Mind-Dependence Lecture 3

SUMMARY BOETHIUS AND THE PROBLEM OF UNIVERSALS

CRITICAL THEORY BEYOND NEGATIVITY

ST10XME Power Extension Cable Test

Artification and the Ontology of Art

HERMENEUTIC PHILOSOPHY AND DATA COLLECTION: A PRACTICAL FRAMEWORK

Action Theory for Creativity and Process

My thesis is that not only the written symbols and spoken sounds are different, but also the affections of the soul (as Aristotle called them).

Dawn M. Phillips The real challenge for an aesthetics of photography

History Admissions Assessment Specimen Paper Section 1: explained answers

scholars have imagined and dealt with religious people s imaginings and dealings

Do Universals Exist? Realism

6. Embodiment, sexuality and ageing

Habit, Semeiotic Naturalism, and Unity among the Sciences Aaron Wilson

Nepean Creative & Performing Arts High School

MAKING INTERACTIVE GUIDES MORE ATTRACTIVE

New Hollywood. Scorsese & Mean Streets

And then, if we have an adequate theory of the rhetorical situation, what would that then allow (in Bitzer s view)?

AESTHETICS. Key Terms

Culture, Space and Time A Comparative Theory of Culture. Take-Aways

Existential Cause & Individual Experience

Art, Vision, and the Necessity of a Post-Analytic Phenomenology

A Process of the Fusion of Horizons in the Text Interpretation

6 The Analysis of Culture

Philosophical roots of discourse theory

Curriculum Framework for Visual Arts

Transcription:

PETER - PAUL VERBEEK Beyond the Human Eye Technological Mediation and Posthuman Visions In myriad ways, human vision is mediated by technological devices. Televisions, camera s, computer screens, spectacles, car windows in virtually all situations of our daily lives, technological artifacts mediate the ways we perceive reality. What does this imply for the human condition the state of being of people living in this technological culture? What kind of subject emerges from these technological mediations? And how do the visual arts help to produce and understand these subjects? In this short essay, I will elaborate three approaches to these questions: one modern, another postmodern and the last one posthuman. These approaches have strongly differing analyses of the relations between human beings, mediating technologies, and reality. I will argue that contemporary forms of art take us to the limits of what can be called human. After having helped us to exercise mediated visions, we might be entering a period in which art helps us to exercise posthuman vision. 1. TECHNOLOGICAL MEDIATION How to analyze the phenomenon of technological mediation? Don Ihde s phenomenological approach of technology offers a valuable framework here. In his analyis, he understands technological mediation as the role technology plays in the relation between human beings and their world. Ihde discerns several relationships human beings can have with technological artifacts. Firstly, technologies can be embodied by their users, making it possible that a relationship comes about between humans and their world. This embodiment relation, for instance, occurs when looking through a pair of glasses; the artifact is not noticed explicitly but yet it co-shapes our relationship with our environment. Technological artifacts are incorporated here, as it were: they become extensions of the human body. Secondly, technologies can be the terminus of our experience. This alterity relation occurs when interacting with a device as if it were another living being, as is the case when buying a train ticket at an automatic ticket dispenser. A third human-technology relation finds itself in between embodiment and alterity: the hermeneutic relation, in which technologies provide representations of reality, which need to be interpreted by humans in order to constitute a perception. A good example here is the thermometer, which does not give human beings an actual experience of heat or cold, but delivers a value which needs to be read in order to tell something about temperature. And, finally, in the fourth human-technology relation Ihde distinguishes, technologies play a role at the background of our experience, creating a context for our perceptions. An example of this background relation is the lighting and heating in a room, the buzz of the computer and the switching on and off of the refrigerator, et cetera. These four human-technology relationships, on the basis of which technologies play their mediating roles, are indicated schematically below. 01 07 Peter Paul Verbeek

embodiment relation hermeneutic relation alterity relation background relation (human technology) apple world human apple (technology world) human apple technology (- world) human ( technology world) Figure 1: Human-technology relationships (after Ihde, 1990) During the past centuries, artists have been investigating this phenomenon of technological mediation and explored the ways in which it constitutes the objectivity of reality and the subjectivity of the perceiver. In what follows below, I will discuss three philosophical and artistic approaches to the phenomenon of technological mediation: modernism, postmodernism, and posthumanism. From a modernist point of view, technological mediation can simply be conceived as a way to establish contact between humans and reality, enabling human beings to observe the world and acquire accurate knowledge of it. From a postmodern perspective, mediation can be seen as an event in which competing perspectives are disclosed simultaneously, constituting the human perceiver not as a neutral observer but as an active editor of reality. And from a posthumanist perspective, to conclude, it will become possible to explore the very intentionality of mediating technologies themselves, in relation to human intentionality. 2. MODERN VISIONS A modernist interpretation of technological mediation takes as its starting point the separation of subject and object. In this view, subject and object have a fixed identity and a separate existence. This only leaves room to approach the mediating role of technology as determining how the objects can be present to the subject, and how the subject can be present in the objective world. Mediation does not affect subjectivity and objectivity themselves in this perspective, but only concerns the relation between both. Don Ihde s illuminating analysis in this volume of the role of the camera obscura in Renaissance art illustrates this position perfectly. Renaissance art is well-known for its realism: its adequate and accurate representations of reality. At the same time, these representations are supposed to have been made by autonomous individuals, who possess the skills and ability to produce these impressively realistic works of art. When David Hockney reminds us that many Renaissance paintings were actually produced with the help of the camera obscura, he reinforces not only the importance of realism in Renaissance art (as provided by the camera), but also of the autonomy of the subject. The fact that using the camera obscura is seen as a form of cheating, debunking what was seen as an autonomous expression of individual genius to simply drawing by the lines, reveals the modernist occupation with the authenticity of the subject: it needs to be genuine or pure, which means that it should not be augmented or polluted by technological instruments. 02 07 Peter Paul Verbeek

Hockney s debunking of Renaissance art shows how much irony there is in this modernist interpretation of mediation. The modernist focus on the objectivity of its knowledge and the autonomy of its subjects, after all, fails to see how its objectivism and subjectivism are themselves products of technological mediation, rather than being a natural state of being. As Ihde argues in line with Panofsky, the Renaissance the dawn of modernism was embodied trough technologies, with the camera obscura being one favorite optical toy. Only after the introduction of the camera it became possible to produce realistic depictions of reality on a screen and to understand human beings in terms of autonomous subjects, having a separate existence from the world of objects. The modernist claim of objectivity needs to be seen in the light of the production of automatically-reduced-to-renaissance perspective images by the camera obscura. Linear perspective should not be seen as the one best way to draw a realistic image, but as a technically produced disclosure of reality. The camera obscura made available images of reality in linear perspective formatting, and this thoroughly mediated representation of reality got to be seen as coming closest to the real thing. Therefore, rather than viewing Renaissance art in terms of realism, as a long-awaited technique to produce adequate representations of reality, it should be seen as a form of exercising the new visual regime imposed by the camera obscura, a way to explore a new technologically mediated manifestation of reality. The camera obscura did not only produce a new form of objectivity, though, but also a new form of subjectivity. The subject is approached as isolated from the objects in the world; it can only relate to representations. In this way the camera obscura served as a model for understanding the human subject: a dark room in which representations were generated of an external world. A modernist reading of the phenomenon of technological mediation, therefore, cannot do. As soon as it becomes clear that subjectivism and objectivism are themselves products of technological mediation, the modern isolation of subjects and objects loses its status as an unshakable basis. But how to get beyond this modernist interpretation? 3. POSTMODERN VISIONS In his contribution to this volume, Don Ihde also elaborates a postmodern approach to technological mediation. He explains how contemporary imaging technologies excavate realist interpretations of mediation as producing one-on-one depictions of reality. Contemporary technologies like radio telescopes make visible realities to us that cannot be perceived without these mediations. That is to say: the realities revealed by these mediating technologies do not have an equivalent to the naked eye. Such technologies necessarily need to translate what they perceive to something that can be perceived by human beings. In many cases, even multiple translation technologies are used at once; medical diagnostics, for instance, often make use of ultrasound, CT scanning and MRI scanning at the same time. The concept of realism does not make sense here, because the original 03 07 Peter Paul Verbeek

which has to be represented cannot be known directly at all, but only through mediation. What reality is, is co-shaped by the instruments with which it is perceived. While reality is constituted here as context-dependent, the subject is constituted as edifying: it needs to construct its reality on the basis of the fragments that are given to it. Rather than a heroic individual locked up in a dark room to study depictions of reality, the postmodern subject resembles the movie director, sitting behind a wall of screens and constructing a contingent reality from the many perspectives that are at his or her disposal. This view of mediation can be called postmodern, since it connects to the postmodern focus on the role of contexts and frames of reference in the coming about of meaning, truth, and reality. With one major difference, that is: human interpretations of reality are not to be understood in terms of textual and linguistic structures only, as is the predominant approach in postmodern thinking but also as mediated by artifacts. This approach to mediation requires an entirely different reading of the phenomenological human-technology-world scheme. Humans, technologies, and the world to which humans are related via technologies can no longer be seen here as fixed entities around which relations emerge. Rather, in these human-world relationships, both the objectivity of the world and the subjectivity of those who are experiencing and existing in it are constituted. Our world needs to be understood as interpreted reality, and our existence as situated subjectivity. What the world is and what subjects are, arises from the interplay between humans and reality, as it is mediated by technology. Technologies help to constitute the relationships between humans and reality by shaping people s perceptions and interpretations on the one hand and their actions and forms of engagement with reality on the other. In this slightly modified version of phenomenology, humans and world, or subject and object, do not have fixed essences. They exist, and their existence gets dressed with temporary essences in the process of mediation. Entities do not have one single essence; what is essential about them, depends on the context in which they find themselves and on the relations they have with other human and nonhuman entities. This reading of mediation is therefore beyond realism and the autonomy of the subject. 4. POSTHUMAN VISIONS Yet, the question remains to what extent this postmodern approach to technological mediation is able to explain all roles that contemporary mediating technologies can play. The works of artists like De Realisten, Wouter Hooijmans, and Esther Polak, which are discussed elsewhere in this book more extensively, strike new dimensions of perception, which cannot be adequately dealt with from a postmodern point of view. These artworks explore new regimes of perception, by experimenting with new forms of mediation. They embody a play with intentionality, in which they explicitly explore and demonstrate the intentionalities of technological artifacts as opposed to human intentionality. Rather than putting these intentionalities in the service of human relations to the world as is the case in what Don Ihde 04 07 Peter Paul Verbeek

calls hermeneutic relations, where technologies produce representations of reality that need to be interpreted by humans in order to constitute a perception they explore technological intentionalities as relevant in themselves. While in a modernist approach mediating technologies can only play a neutral role, simply generating adequate representations of reality for human observers, and in a postmodern approach technologies are seen as active generators of representations of reality, which need to be read and edited by human perceivers, here we face a posthumanist approach of technological mediation. Technologies give their own intentionalities a central place here, without putting it in the service of producing contingent representations of reality as input for the compound eye of humans. For however much postmodernism undermines the autonomy of the subject, it still remains a human-centered approach, approaching humans as the ultimate source of contingent and constructed interpretations of realities. The artworks of De Realisten, Wouter Hooijmans, and Esther Polak show in intriguing ways how this humanist bias in postmodernism can be overcome. The intentionality deployed by these works of art can be called posthumanist, in the sense that they involve perceptions that no human being could ever have, of a world that has no equivalent in the human experiential world. These artworks show several ways in which nonhuman observers can experience reality: they involve artifactual intentionalities rather than human intentionalities stretched over technological artifacts. Each of these works therefore embodies a different way of decentering the human subject. AUGMENTED INTENTIONALITY The night photographs of Wouter Hooijmans embody the mildest form of posthumanism. Hooijmans makes landscape photographs using shutter times of several hours, which allows him to make use of starlight for exposing his pictures. This has stunning effects. All short incidents, like animals walking through the image, movements of the leaves on a tree, ripplings of the water in a lake, become irrelevant. Only things that last make it to the picture. Hooijmans s photographs reveal the world as it would look if we would not need to blink our eyes a serenity which creates an immediate association with the timelessness of death: beyond the realm of human beings. In a sense, Hooijmans s pictures can be said to embody Husserl s method of essential intuition. This particular philosophical method consisted of imaginatively transforming a phenomenon in various ways so as to determine which aspects are essential to it and which not. We can, for instance, imagine dogs with stripes and spots, with short ears and long ears, with pointed and flat noses, but never with wings or gills, and in this way we can arrive at a general idea of dog. For Husserl, this essence can never be found in the world itself, but is a pure idea; yet Hooijmans s images seem to come close to a depiction of the essence of landscape obtained by eliminating all irrelevant variations of it. What Hooijmans s photographs accomplish, is an extreme mechanical amplification of some aspects of the intentionality of the human vision. 05 07 Peter Paul Verbeek

Contrary to the most common use of the photo camera, Hooijmans does not create instantaneous exposures, but rather sustained exposures. His photographs blend together an infinite number of visual impressions into one single representation of the world, which the human eye could never produce itself. We could call this nonhuman form of intentionality augmented intentionality, since it consists in an artificially magnified and expanded form of human intentionality. CONSTRUCTIVE INTENTIONALITY The stereophotographic work of De Realisten ( The Realists ) embodies a different form of posthumanist intentionality. As a part of their work, De Realisten have been making stereographic photographs of several sets of identically shaped objects, made out of different and non-blending materials e.g. wood and bronze. Looking at these photographs with the help of 3d equipment, one is confronted with highly realistic, three-dimensional representations of a reality which cannot exist in everyday experience. These photographs do not represent reality, but generate a new reality in the act of looking at them. They make visible objects that can only exist in this virtual way: three-dimensional, photorealistic representations of amalgams which have no original counterpart in everyday reality. The intentionality De Realisten gave to their stereographic camera is therefore not directed at making visible an existing reality but at constructing a new reality. Therefore, the posthumanist intentionality involved here can be called constructive intentionality. For an adequate analysis of these two intentionalities in terms of Don Ihde s framework, the human-technology-world scheme needs to be augmented. For what we are primarily witnessing in the phenomena of augmented and constructive intentionality, is a technology-world relation, rather than a human -world relation mediated by technology. This implies that there is a double intentionality involved here; one of technology toward its world, and one of human beings toward the result of this technological intentionality. Humans are directed at the ways in which a technology is directed at the world. This gives the following scheme: Posthuman vision, variant 1: human apple (technology apple world) REFLEXIVE INTENTIONALITY A third posthumanist form of mediation is presented by Esther Polak s intriguing project Drawing with GPS, in which she makes technologies perceive the ways in which human beings perceive the world and ultimately makes these technological perceptions perceptible to human beings. She asked several people in Amsterdam to carry a GPS device with them for some time, which enabled her set down the movements of these people on a map of the city. Every person participating in the project thus drew his or her own map of Amsterdam. Once confronted with these graphical 06 07 Peter Paul Verbeek

representations of the way in which the GPS system had perceived their movements, the participants in the project often indicated that these representations gave them a renewed experience of what they had been doing and seeing, and sometimes even revealed aspects of their dealings that were new to them. This artwork stages a situation in which human beings are experiencing their world, while a technological device perceives these experiences, which will ultimately allow the people involved to experience these technological experiences of their own experiences. This implies that there is a triple intentionality involved here; a third intentionality is added to the double intentionality involved in the first variant of posthumanist vision. This third intentionality the human experience of the world is posthumanistically experienced by a technological device, and then represented in an experiential way to the person who had the initial experience. This intentionality can be called reflexive intentionality: technology is directed at the ways in which humans are directed at reality, in order to let human beings experience themselves as experiencer. In Ihde s terms, the schematic structure of this reflexive intentionality is: human apple (technology apple [human apple world]). The posthumanist dimension in this situation is the technological experience of human experience: Posthuman vision, variant 2: technology apple (human apple world) Ecce homo posthumanus. By revealing several posthumanist forms of intentionality, these works of art show us a glimpse of the new human condition, which gets ever more manifest. The lifeworld of human beings is becoming crowded with devices that have intentionalities of their own and that constantly help to shape our experiences and dealings with the world. Philosophical reflection is not enough to explore and understand this new posthuman condition. It is the artists who show us the way, experimenting with what is going on and confronting us with this in an experiential rather than a discursive way. Dr. Ir. Peter - Paul Verbeek ( NL ), university lecturer in the philosophy of technology, University of Twente, Enschede. Publications include What Things Do: Philosophical Reflections on Technology, Agency, and Design ( Penn State University Press, 2005 ). 07 07 Peter Paul Verbeek