Normative and Positive Economics

Similar documents
Introduction to The Handbook of Economic Methodology

10/24/2016 RESEARCH METHODOLOGY Lecture 4: Research Paradigms Paradigm is E- mail Mobile

Department of Economics

THE RELATIONS BETWEEN ETHICS AND ECONOMICS: A COMPARATIVE ANALYSIS BETWEEN AYRES AND WEBER S PERSPECTIVES. By Nuria Toledano and Crispen Karanda

CHAPTER 2 THEORETICAL FRAMEWORK

Introduction to The Social Economics of Human Material Need

Department of Philosophy Florida State University

Interpretation of Interpersonal Utility Comparisons: Positive, Normative or Descriptive

EPISTEMOLOGY, METHODOLOGY, AND THE SOCIAL SCIENCES

What counts as a convincing scientific argument? Are the standards for such evaluation

INTRODUCTION TO THE POLITICS OF SOCIAL THEORY

Natika Newton, Foundations of Understanding. (John Benjamins, 1996). 210 pages, $34.95.

EXPANDED COURSE DESCRIPTIONS UC DAVIS PHILOSOPHY DEPARTMENT SPRING, Michael Glanzberg MWF 10:00-10:50a.m., 176 Everson CRNs:

Environmental Ethics: From Theory to Practice

Conclusion. One way of characterizing the project Kant undertakes in the Critique of Pure Reason is by

Bas C. van Fraassen, Scientific Representation: Paradoxes of Perspective, Oxford University Press, 2008.

Part IV Social Science and Network Theory

Political Economy I, Fall 2014

Philosophy 345/Economics 319: The Philosophy and Methodology of Economics Spring 2014

3. The knower s perspective is essential in the pursuit of knowledge. To what extent do you agree?

Kant: Notes on the Critique of Judgment


Sidestepping the holes of holism

The Psychology of Justice

UNIT SPECIFICATION FOR EXCHANGE AND STUDY ABROAD

Interdepartmental Learning Outcomes

Interpretive and Critical Research Traditions

The Embedding Problem for Non-Cognitivism; Introduction to Cognitivism; Motivational Externalism

PART II METHODOLOGY: PROBABILITY AND UTILITY

The only uses of this work permitted are private study or research.

Communication Studies Publication details, including instructions for authors and subscription information:

Introduction to The Elgar Companion to Economics and Philosophy

Contemporary Philosophy of Science and Neoinstitutional Thought

PHD THESIS SUMMARY: Phenomenology and economics PETR ŠPECIÁN

A Note on Analysis and Circular Definitions

Chapter 2. Critical Realism and Economics

Mark Blaug on the Historiography of Economics

These are some notes to give you some idea of the content of the lecture they are not exhaustive, nor always accurate! So read the referenced work.

Rethinking the Aesthetic Experience: Kant s Subjective Universality

Are There Two Theories of Goodness in the Republic? A Response to Santas. Rachel Singpurwalla

Nicholas Vrousalis Philippe Van Parijs. Analytical Marxism

The Meaning of Abstract and Concrete in Hegel and Marx

Hypatia, Volume 21, Number 3, Summer 2006, pp (Review) DOI: /hyp For additional information about this article

Discourse analysis is an umbrella term for a range of methodological approaches that

Lecture 3 Kuhn s Methodology

KINDS (NATURAL KINDS VS. HUMAN KINDS)

Lawson on Veblen on Social Ontology

1/8. The Third Paralogism and the Transcendental Unity of Apperception

INTRODUCTION TO NONREPRESENTATION, THOMAS KUHN, AND LARRY LAUDAN

SAMPLE COURSE OUTLINE PHILOSOPHY AND ETHICS GENERAL YEAR 12

PHI 3240: Philosophy of Art

Philosophy Department Expanded Course Descriptions Fall, 2007

that would join theoretical philosophy (metaphysics) and practical philosophy (ethics)?

UNIT SPECIFICATION FOR EXCHANGE AND STUDY ABROAD

observation and conceptual interpretation

TROUBLING QUALITATIVE INQUIRY: ACCOUNTS AS DATA, AND AS PRODUCTS

The topic of this Majors Seminar is Relativism how to formulate it, and how to evaluate arguments for and against it.

Kant, Peirce, Dewey: on the Supremacy of Practice over Theory

Necessity in Kant; Subjective and Objective

Against Posner against Coase against theory

HISTORY AND PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE AND TECHNOLOGY Vol. III - Philosophy of Economics - Adolfo García de la Sienra

PART ONE: PHILOSOPHY AND THE OTHER MINDS

Big Questions in Philosophy. What Is Relativism? Paul O Grady 22 nd Jan 2019

Ed. Carroll Moulton. Vol. 1. New York: Charles Scribner's Sons, p COPYRIGHT 1998 Charles Scribner's Sons, COPYRIGHT 2007 Gale

Logic and Philosophy of Science (LPS)

What do our appreciation of tonal music and tea roses, our acquisition of the concepts

WHY DO PEOPLE CARE ABOUT REPUTATION?

Aristotle on the Human Good

Guidelines for Manuscript Preparation for Advanced Biomedical Engineering

A Soviet View of Structuralism, Althusser, and Foucault

Colonnade Program Course Proposal: Explorations Category

Review of Krzysztof Brzechczyn, Idealization XIII: Modeling in History

REVIEW ARTICLE IDEAL EMBODIMENT: KANT S THEORY OF SENSIBILITY

Categories and Schemata

Stenberg, Shari J. Composition Studies Through a Feminist Lens. Anderson: Parlor Press, Print. 120 pages.

ALIGNING WITH THE GOOD

Practical Intuition and Rhetorical Example. Paul Schollmeier

By Rahel Jaeggi Suhrkamp, 2014, pbk 20, ISBN , 451pp. by Hans Arentshorst

Methodology in a Pluralist Environment. Sheila C Dow. Published in Journal of Economic Methodology, 8(1): 33-40, Abstract

Jacek Surzyn University of Silesia Kant s Political Philosophy

Philip Kitcher and Gillian Barker, Philosophy of Science: A New Introduction, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2014, pp. 192

Seven remarks on artistic research. Per Zetterfalk Moving Image Production, Högskolan Dalarna, Falun, Sweden

Review of Maynard Keynes, An Economist's Biography by D. Moggridge

Semiotics of culture. Some general considerations

Research Topic Analysis. Arts Academic Language and Learning Unit 2013

Watcharabon Buddharaksa. The University of York. RCAPS Working Paper No January 2011

The Teaching Method of Creative Education

Georg Simmel and Formal Sociology

Dabney Townsend. Hume s Aesthetic Theory: Taste and Sentiment Timothy M. Costelloe Hume Studies Volume XXVIII, Number 1 (April, 2002)

TOP5ITIS 1 by Roberto Serrano Department of Economics, Brown University January 2018

CRITIQUE OF PARSONS AND MERTON

Ithaque : Revue de philosophie de l'université de Montréal

Review of Carolyn Korsmeyer, Savoring Disgust: The foul and the fair. in aesthetics (Oxford University Press pp (PBK).

Cultural Studies Prof. Dr. Liza Das Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Guwahati

PROGRAMME SPECIFICATION FOR M.ST. IN FILM AESTHETICS. 1. Awarding institution/body University of Oxford. 2. Teaching institution University of Oxford

BOOK REVIEW: A HISTORY OF MACROECONOMICS: FROM KEYNES TO LUCAS AND BEYOND, BY MICHEL DEVROEY REVIEWED BY ROGER E. BACKHOUSE*

Challenging the View That Science is Value Free

Valuable Particulars

Theories and Activities of Conceptual Artists: An Aesthetic Inquiry

SIGNS, SYMBOLS, AND MEANING DANIEL K. STEWMT*

Transcription:

Marquette University e-publications@marquette Economics Faculty Research and Publications Business Administration, College of 1-1-1998 Normative and Positive Economics John B. Davis Marquette University, john.davis@marquette.edu Published version. "Normative and Positive Economics," in Encyclopedia of Political Economy. Eds. Phillip Anthony O'Hara. London: Taylor & Francis (Routledge), 1998: 804-807. Publisher Link. Taylor & Francis (Routledge) 1998. Used with permission.

not, and how one can evade it. See also: evolutionary economics: major contemporary themes; producer and consumer sovereignty Selected references Alderson, WE. (1957) Marketing Behaviour and Executive Action, Homewood, IL: Irwin. Carroll, G.R. (1990) "Concentration and Spezialisation: Dynamics of Niche Width in normative and positive economics Virtually every mainstream textbook in economics begins with a brief discussion of the difference between positive and normative economics, made a dogma by those who slavishly followed Lionel Robbins in his Essay on the Nature and Significance of Economic Science (1932). For example, Schotter's Microeconomics states that: 804

normative and positive "economics Normative or welfare economics deals with what ought to be rather than what is and involves prescriptive statements that may be based on value judgments. Positive economics deals with what is rather than what ought to be and involves descriptive statements that are objective and verifiable. (Schotter 1994: 4) Schotter's emphasis is not unusual. Since positive economics is thought to be objective and verifiable, normative economics by implication is subjective and not subject to rigorous validation. This view is inherited from David Hume, who argued that a gulf exists between "is" and "ought"; and, more recently, from the 1930s logical positivists, who claimed both that scientific statements alone are rational and that scientific statements are those that are empirically verifiable. Mainstream economists, accordingly, claim that their work is scientific on account of its being value-neutral. Facts are theory-laden Economic methodologists, however, deny that empirical evidence confirms a theory as scientific, because disconfirming evidence may always turn up in the future, and because any given set of facts may give support to conflicting theories. They also deny that theories that stand up to empirical tests designed to falsify theories must be scientific, because theorists can always add immunizing, auxiliary assumptions to protect core principles. Accordingly, it has not been shown that theories are scientific in virtue of their relation to facts and evidence. Indeed, philosophers of science since Norwood Russell Hanson (and later Thomas Kuhn) have argued that subjective factors are inevitably involved in the development of scientific ideas, and that facts are theory-laden because they are identified from the perspective of PARA DIGMS. At the same time, many philosophers reject the notion that value judgments are inevitably subjective, and, indeed, often argue that widely accepted value judgments may possess as much or more "objectivity" as many scientific propositions. Values permeate economics The mainstream view, then, that there exists a clear dividing line between positive and normative economics, is mistaken. Some traditional economists admit this when they allow that an individual's value judgments influence the views they develop. But this view is not widely supported in the mainstream of economics. Even when it is, value judgments are often understood as "individual motivation may shape theory," rather than as "the world views of economists in general influence the very questions they ask, the significance they attribute to some issues rather than others, and the concepts they select." For example, neoclassical economics focuses only upon instrumental rationality, and then characterizes decision making as rational when it is atomistic and self-interested. But this selective characterization of behavior has never been given any real scientific defense and, rather, represents a theoretical commitment one must have to be admitted to the ranks of neoclassical economists. Thus, while it cannot be said that a clear dividing line exists between positive and normative economics, it is still unlikely that anyone would deny that there is a difference between positive and normative statements. This suggests that the important issue for heterodox economists is to understand how positive and normative economics are related and influence one another. Wilber (1996) puts this especially well by rejecting the notion that value neutrality makes sense, and by asking how our values come to permeate economic reasoning (see VALUE JUDGMENTS AND WORLD VIEWS). Characterizing and appraising value judgments One proposal for how to do this, deriving from a reconsideration of the nature of values, is discussed by Blaug (1992). He draws attention to Nagel's (1961) distinction between two types of value judgments: characterizing value judgments and appraising value judgments. Characterizing value judgments concern the choice 805

normative and positive economics of subject matter, the mode of investigation to be followed and the criteria for judging results. Characterizing value judgments involve the sort of methodological judgments that are indispensable to any science. Appraising value judgments concern evaluative statements about the world, and are the basis for our claims about the relative desirability of different social outcomes. Appraising value judgments are usually considered to be normative economics, but it is obvious that characterizing value judgments are also normative and that they are essential to science. Hence, Blaug recognizes that the methodological judgments or ground rules employed by any theory, when it makes various characterizing value judgments, are not free of the normative commitments and appraising value judgments the theory's practitioners hold. For example, the neoclassical treatment of agents as rational maximizers can well be argued to depend on the view that it is desirable or morally praiseworthy that individuals pursue their own restricted well-being in market contexts, and that doing so produces the greatest social good through an "invisible hand" process. At the same time, this view of economic agents can easily be argued to rule out the idea that individuals ought morally to put justice in relations with others above individual gain, and that failure to do so furthers an alienated life dominated by impersonal market relations. Thus, value judgments of the appraising sort enter into economists' selection of concepts and methods at the most fundamental level, and we seem not to have improved our understanding of "positive" and " normative" economics using Nagel's distinction. Reconstituting means and ends A more promising approach, that also derives from a reconsideration of the nature of values, is to be found in institutionalist theory, which denies from the outset that positive and normative economics are mutually exclusive domains or categories. Dugger and Waller (1996), for example, accordingly argue that the positive deals with our evaluating means and the normative deals with evaluating ends. More importantly, however, what counts as a means and what counts as an end is relative to the situation at hand. Indeed, something can be a means on one occasion and an end on another. Thus, an evolutionary approach, which views the economy as being concerned with historical processes and PATH DEPEN DENCY, must be prepared to understand the continual reconstitution of means and ends. This explains the value permeation of economic reasoning at a fundamental level, and ushers in an alternative to normative positive dualism in the form of Thorstein Veblen's split between instrumental and ceremonial knowledge. Instrumental knowledge is concerned with facts, getting things done and solving problems. Ceremonial knowledge is opposed to instrumental knowledge, and is concerned with prestige, getting credit for getting things done, and with exercising power (see INSTRUMENTAL VALUE THEORY). Since, throughout human history, the ceremonial has tended to prevail over the instrumental, a progressive economics aims at a critical apprehension of the use of power in the economy to gain position and prestige. Social problems - not social theories - should be the focus of economics. Since society will never be free of problems, the aims and ends of society are always evolving, thus suggesting the idea of "evotopia" (moving toward an evolving good society) rather than utopia as a guiding view of good economics (Hodgson 1995). Ideology and analysis Finally, Dobb's Marxist appraisal of the positive and normative deserves attention. Dobb also begins with a re-characterization of values, and reconstructs the traditional Humean dualism between "is" and "ought" in terms of a distinction between IDEOLOGY and analysis. In contrast to Hutchison's view of values and ideology as an individual's personal predilections and commitments, Dobb defines ideology as "a whole system of thought, or coordinated set of beliefs and ideas, which form a frame- 806

North-South trade models work, or higher-level group of related concepts, for more specific and particular notions, analyses, applications and conclusions" (1973 : 1). As such, individuals are often unconscious of their ideological views, and tend to take many of their elements as having been established as "true" rather than "believed propositions." For example, Dobb takes the traditional fact- value distinction itself as being ideological in that most economists take it to be rooted in incontrovertible truths rather than an unexamined belief. A view related to Dobb's needs to be distinguished. Schumpeter (1954) wrote of the difference between economic analysis and an economist's vision of the nature of reality and the problems at hand. The latter is ideological, and involves "a preanalytical cognitive act" which must precede "analytic effort in any field" and which may also "re-enter the history of every established science each time somebody teaches us to see things in a light of which the source is not to be found in the facts methods, and results of the pre-existing state of the science" (Schumpeter 1954: 41). Yet, Schumpeter also claims that economic analysis can still be thought to be objective and independent of ideological views, indeed as a "box of tools" of a purely instrumental nature upon which scientific progress depends. Dobb rightly challenges this conception, arguing that this formal view of concepts as tools overlooks the way in which tools are developed for theoretical and ideological purposes. Thus, if we are to employ a distinction between positive and normative economics, it must be with great caution and an awareness of the ways in which values inevitably permeate theories. It is true that descriptive and prescriptive language differ and that there are important differences between facts and values. However, economics is highly value-laden and, thus, understanding the role of values in economics is necessary to doing good economics. See also: ethics and morality; modernism and postmodernism; natural rights; rhetoric Selected references Blaug, M. (1992) The Methodology of Economics, 2nd edn, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Dobb, M. (1973) Theories of Value and Distribution since Adam Smith, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Dugger, Wand Waller, W (1996) "Radical Institutionalism: From Technological to Democratic Instrumentalism," Review of Social Economy 54(2). Hodgson, G. (1995) "The Poltical Economy of Utopia," Review of Social Economy 53(2). Nagel, E. (1961) The Structure of Science: Problems in the Logic of Scientific Explanation, London: Routledge & Kegan Paul. Robbins, L. (1932) An Essay on the Nature and Significance of Economic Science 2nd edn London: Macmillan. ', Schotter, A. (1994) Microeconomics, New York: HarperColiins. Schumpeter, 1. (1954) History of Economic Analysis, New York: Oxford University Press. Wilber, C. (1996) "Ethics and Economics," in Charles 1. Whalen (ed.), Political Economy for the 21st Century: Contemporary Views on the Trend of Economics, Armonk, NY: M.E. Sharpe. JOHN B. DAVIS North-South trade models Models of North- South trade examine the interaction of two regions: the rich North (also called the metropolis, core or center) comprising "developed" economies, and the poor South (also called the periphery) comprising "less-developed" economies. Special reference is placed on international trade, factor movements, technology transfer and related factors. They consider the links between the two regions, and usually highlight the dynamic interaction between, and the structural differences between, the two regions. They can be seen as a reaction to the dominant microtheoretic Heckscher- Ohlin- Samuelson (HOS) 807