MERE EXPOSURE AND AESTHETIC REALISM A RESPONSE TO PERCEPTUAL LEARNING, THE MERE EXPOSURE EFFECT AND AESTHETIC ANTI-REALISM BY BENCE NANAY

Similar documents
Mere Exposure to Bad Art Aaron Meskin, Mark Phelan, Margaret Moore, and Matthew Kieran

1/10. Berkeley on Abstraction

Types of perceptual content

California Content Standard Alignment: Hoopoe Teaching Stories: Visual Arts Grades Nine Twelve Proficient* DENDE MARO: THE GOLDEN PRINCE


Experiments and Experience in SP173. MIT Student

I like those glasses on you, but not in the mirror: Fluency, preference, and virtual mirrors

Comments on Bence Nanay, Perceptual Content and the Content of Mental Imagery

Kant: Notes on the Critique of Judgment

CARROLL ON THE MOVING IMAGE

Student Learning Assessment for ART 100 Katie Frank

The Power of Ideas: Milton Friedman s Empirical Methodology

Minds Work by Ear. What Positioning Taught Us. What Is a Picture Worth?

Fred Wilson s Un-Natural Histories: Trauma and the Visual Production of Knowledge

Object Oriented Learning in Art Museums Patterson Williams Roundtable Reports, Vol. 7, No. 2 (1982),

The Historian and Archival Finding Aids

Looking at and Talking about Art with Kids

Aesthetic Formalism, Reactions and Solutions

Seeing in: Two-fold, three-fold?

Chapter 14 Art Lesson Plans

Current Issues in Pictorial Semiotics

Between Concept and Form: Learning from Case Studies

1/8. The Third Paralogism and the Transcendental Unity of Apperception

Image and Imagination

Renaissance Old Masters and Modernist Art History-Writing

ARISTOTLE AND THE UNITY CONDITION FOR SCIENTIFIC DEFINITIONS ALAN CODE [Discussion of DAVID CHARLES: ARISTOTLE ON MEANING AND ESSENCE]

The Art of Time Travel: A Bigger Picture

Thomas Szanto: Bewusstsein, Intentionalität und mentale Repräsentation. Husserl und die analytische Philosophie des Geistes

HFCC Learning Lab Special Writing Forms How to Write a Review of a Book or Article

1000 Words is Nothing: The Photographic Present in Relation to Informational Extraction

Immanuel Kant Critique of Pure Reason

Publishing Your Research in Peer-Reviewed Journals: The Basics of Writing a Good Manuscript.

Inter-subjective Judgment

Early and Middle Childhood / Art. Component 1: Content Knowledge SAMPLE ITEMS AND SCORING RUBRICS

Leder Belke Oeberst & Augustin 2004

ANALYSIS OF THE PREVAILING VIEWS REGARDING THE NATURE OF THEORY- CHANGE IN THE FIELD OF SCIENCE

how does this collaboration work? is it an equal partnership?

WAYNESBORO AREA SCHOOL DISTRICT CURRICULUM AMERICAN LITERATURE

Rashid Johnson on David Hammons, Andy Goldsworthy, and His Own Anxiety of Movement

ART216: Term Project

Course Syllabus. Ancient Greek Philosophy (direct to Philosophy) (toll-free; ask for the UM-Flint Philosophy Department)

Visual Arts Prekindergarten

Taylor & Francis Style

KANT S TRANSCENDENTAL LOGIC

Preptests 63 Answers and Explanations (By Ivy Global) Section 4 Reading Comprehension

Continuum for Opinion/Argument Writing

Edward Winters. Aesthetics and Architecture. London: Continuum, 2007, 179 pp. ISBN

Media Literacy and Semiotics

The Oxford Compendium of Visual Illusions (2017), A. Shapiro, & D.Todorovic (Eds.), Oxford University Press, New York,

Mary: Well, I have a set of 78 rpm records from the 1920s that are an exercise program.

In collaboration with the National Gallery of Art. Page 1 of 12. Recovering the Golden Age: Activities

Policies and Procedures

Yes, it's rotten science, but it's in a worthy cause The tobacco industry's immoderate love of quote mining. Pascal Diethelm

Caught in the Middle. Philosophy of Science Between the Historical Turn and Formal Philosophy as Illustrated by the Program of Kuhn Sneedified

Studio Visit: Erin O Keefe

Medieval Art. artwork during such time. The ivory sculpting and carving have been very famous because of the

What Can Experimental Philosophy Do? David Chalmers

Politics in Reverse: The American Reception of American Constructivism (preliminary proposal submitted for Radford summer research 2009)

Indiana Academic Standards for Visual Arts Alignment with the. International Violin Competition of Indianapolis Juried Exhibition of Student Art

Art/STEAM Lesson: Designing Album Covers and Fashion Using Color Theory

McDowell, Demonstrative Concepts, and Nonconceptual Representational Content Wayne Wright

INSTRUCTIONS FOR AUTHORS

CUST 100 Week 17: 26 January Stuart Hall: Encoding/Decoding Reading: Stuart Hall, Encoding/Decoding (Coursepack)

Empirical Aesthetics. William Seeley, Bates College

THESIS MIND AND WORLD IN KANT S THEORY OF SENSATION. Submitted by. Jessica Murski. Department of Philosophy

SLIDE AND TRANSITIONAL MEDIA TASK FORCE CASE STUDY TEMPLATE

Mario Verdicchio. Topic: Art

SONGCRAFTERS' COLORING BOOK. Interpreting Interpretation by Bill Pere

Diversity in Proof Appraisal

Mixed Methods: In Search of a Paradigm

Université Libre de Bruxelles

Chapter 1. Rafe Is a Big, Fat Liar

SQA Advanced Unit specification. General information for centres. Unit title: Philosophical Aesthetics: An Introduction. Unit code: HT4J 48

Learning Outcomes After you have finished the course you should:

HISTORICAL & CONCEPTUAL BASES of ART HISTORY

Meaningful Forms and Fuzzy Geometry I: MPB & MGP

6AANA034 Aesthetics Syllabus Academic year 2016/17. Module description. Assessment methods and deadlines

Author Instructions for submitting manuscripts to Environment & Behavior

THE BEATLES: MULTITRACKING AND THE 1960S COUNTERCULTURE

A Critical Response to The Psychology of Creativity: A Critical Reading

Summer Assignment. B. Research. Suggested Order of Completion. AP Art History Sister Lisa Perkowski

Rethinking the Aesthetic Experience: Kant s Subjective Universality

Realism and Representation: The Case of Rembrandt s

2 nd Grade Visual Arts Curriculum Essentials Document

What is the Object of Thinking Differently?

Journal for contemporary philosophy

Summit Public Schools Summit, New Jersey Grade Level 3/ Content Area: Visual Arts

Helena Public Schools. Fine Arts Curriculum. Visual Arts

CONDENSATION JOHN PAUL CAPONIGRO

6 Bodily Sensations as an Obstacle for Representationism

1.4.5.A2 Formalism in dance, music, theatre, and visual art varies according to personal, cultural, and historical contexts.

NEW YORK STATE TEACHER CERTIFICATION EXAMINATIONS

Read in the most efficient way possible. You ll want to use a slightly different approach to prose than you would to poetry, but there are some

1/10. The A-Deduction

A Level. How to set a question. Unit F663 - Drama and Poetry pre

APA Publication Style

Student Performance Q&A:

E. H. Gombrich, (with David Carrier) THE BIG PICTURE: David Carrier talks with Ernst Gombrich, Art Forum, Vol. 34 (6), 1996, pp.66-9, 106, 109.

PHL 317K 1 Fall 2017 Overview of Weeks 1 5

Appalachian Center for Craft - Clay Studio. How to Write an Artist s Statement

Transcription:

MERE EXPOSURE AND AESTHETIC REALISM A RESPONSE TO PERCEPTUAL LEARNING, THE MERE EXPOSURE EFFECT AND AESTHETIC ANTI-REALISM BY BENCE NANAY JAMES E. CUTTING Department of Psychology, Cornell University Email: james.cutting@cornell.edu. Keywords: aesthetic realism, aesthetic antirealism, canons, mere exposure I admire much of Nanay s approach to understanding aesthetics, and not simply because I am an author to which much of the article is directed. In attacking aesthetic antirealism, the notion that quality in an artwork does not inhere in the artwork itself, he defends aesthetic realism. Within art history this latter view was perhaps last endorsed by Rosenberg (1968), and then swept away by the spread of semiotics. Nonetheless, it is hard to resist the notion that there is a kernel of something valid in aesthetic realism. But I need to set a number of things straight concerning Nanay s presentation. To be sure, Nanay is correct in that a general force of Impressionism and its Canon (Cutting, 2006), and more particularly its predecessor (Cutting, 2003), was to show that the repeated, diffuse exposure to artworks (a cultural generalization of the laboratory phenomenon of mere exposure) even if we can t remember having seen them increases our evaluation of their artistic quality. Beyond this Nanay concludes several things. Three are: that I am essentially, if not an all out, aesthetic antirealist; that the subsequent results by Meskin, Phelan, Moore and Kieran (2013) limit my conclusions; and that mere exposure has been shown to work for artistic tokens but not types. Let me address each of these ideas. Mere Exposure as One among Many Aesthetic Effects Nanay reports my position: And what maintains the canons of our Artworld is not the quality of the artworks, but the fact that we are exposed to those artworks that are part of the canon, making us like them more, which reinforces their place in the canon. This is essentially correct for my view of canon maintenance, but not for canon formation. Thus, according to Nanay, I am essentially an aesthetic antirealist. This would mean that I think that there is no such thing as aesthetic realism (and the inherent aesthetic quality) in a painting, and that only our experience with the painting itself guides our appreciation of it. But this isn t quite correct, and at best incomplete. For example, in the concluding chapter of Impressionism and its Canon (2006, pp. 201-202) I wrote: That is, it is perfectly legitimate to say: I want to understand A. I know that b is a part of the cause of A, but I really don t understand b at all. Thus, let me see how far 1

I can get with c, d, e, f, and g ignoring b completely in my account of A. And this is precisely the structure of theory I present here. I am interested in canon formation and maintenance A. I know that the quality of a painting b is likely to be important in some way, but I haven t a clue as to how to assess artistic quality so I am going to ignore it altogether. Instead, then, I will focus on historical coincidence, early accession into a museum and concurrent publicity, curatorial culling, sustained publicity, and mere exposure c, d, e, f, and g, respectively and see how far I can get. The procedure also allows for the omission of other factors perhaps h and i that are also currently unknown. Notice two things. First, I didn t deny the role of quality (aesthetic value) in the evaluation of art. Instead, I deliberately and openly skirted the issue. Indeed, Maynard (2007), in an otherwise very favorable review of my book, chastised me for exactly this tactic. I might add, however, that Nanay hasn t offered us a clue about assessing artistic quality either. Is it a priori? Are our abilities to assess art inborn? Or are we responding to authority Kenneth Clark, Ernst Gombrich, Giorgio Vasari, or perhaps Clement Greenberg? The point of my research effort was to help ground discussion of canons (collections of good art) in some data, and to show that subtle, personal perceptual experiences can play a role perhaps even for choosing Manilow over Mozart. Nanay is also off base in thinking my view is that mere exposure is the dominant factor in canon formation and maintenance. The above quotation should make clear that it is but one of several mechanisms. The others for paintings are: the historical coincidences of early purchases by collectors, early accession into a museums following bequests by those collectors, concurrent publicity in public media, curatorial culling after appearance in those museums (a negative factor), and sustained publicity by art historians. Mere exposure is a sixth mechanism, culturally important but certainly not dominant. Notice also that the first five of these lend force to the roles of authority in the historical agglomeration of images into a canon. Surely, such authority would be paramount over mere exposure for canon formation (perhaps as opposed to canon maintenance). But, of course, appeals to authority don t do much for aesthetic realism either (the Emperor s New Clothes). Mere Exposure as a Positive, Uniform Process? In showing potential limits to my results, Nanay writes that one could argue that the mere exposure effect only works for good art. This is not the place for a detailed critique of Meskin et al. (2013), whose results he cites to support this idea. The Meskin et al. paper is about mere exposure and its possible effect on the aesthetic denigration of bad art. Although that paper mirrored much of my methodology in two experiments, and found results roughly similar to mine for a good artist (John Everett Millais), it has other methodological and logical problems. In particular, as much as one might like to, one cannot generalize from one bad artist (Thomas Kinkade) to all of bad art. One needs, on statistical grounds alone, at least two bad artists, parallel results for those two, as well as at least two good artists, whose works yield results similar to each other but are different than those for the works of the two bad artists. And all of these artists should be from the same period in part so that style is controlled more on this later. Nonetheless, I am actually happy to endorse the general idea of Meskin et al.: Mere exposure might work differently for good art than 2

for bad art. Overexposure is a well-known laboratory (Bornstein, 1989) and cultural phenomenon. But again from Impressionism and its Canon (pp. 208-209): All other things being equal, we will prefer paintings reproduced more often. To be sure, it may be relatively rare that all such things are equal, but the bias [of positive effects from mere exposure] is omnipresent. I claim this bias has deep and lasting effects indeed, sufficiently lasting to help maintain a canon for a century, and more. (Quoted with clarification and new emphases not in the original passage.) In my methods (Cutting, 2003, 2006) I deliberately chose Impressionism as a venue because of its deep penetration into popular culture (lots of people will have seen lots of Impressionist paintings), I chose eight artists associated with Impressionism, and I chose the method of having viewers compare pairs of paintings by the same artist (Meskin et al. did not), painted at about the same time, with roughly the same content, painted the same general style, and with the same general color palettes. In other words, I was trying to make as many things as equal as I could (ceteris paribus). I find it charming that I am chastened for this, given that Google at this moment returns nearly 600,000 hits for the joint search of all things being equal and philosophy. Must we embrace ceteris paribus only for thought experiments? Types, Tokens and Mere Exposure Nanay makes a distinction between mere-exposure-effect tokens (MEE-tokens) and MEE-types, suggesting that most exposure experiments are of the MEE-type variety. However, my guess is that almost all mere exposure experiments, per se, are about MEE-tokens, at least as I would define them. Yes, we are exposed to individual people who look different every day, and we like them (mostly), but most experiments test mere exposure to an exactly repeating stimulus. Wollheim (1987) and Wölfflin aside, I think my art exposure experiments are about tokens, particularly since I don t have to assume that viewers have seen the actual paintings at all. Of course, we might get into a discussion of differences in reproductions early color reproductions can be quite bad and have often faded with time but I think this is another issue. To circumvent any idea that tokens might masquerade as a type, Nanay creates a distinction between MEE-superdeterminate vs. MEE-determinable exposures, where this distinction, I think, is being rallied to shore up the MEE-token vs. MEE-type distinction. If so, fine. However, Monahan, Murphy and Zajonc (2000) showed that certain MEE-superdeterminate and a MEE-determinable effects might be found within the same experiment. That is, those authors found larger effects for liking a specific Chinese character or polygon through mere exposure; and a smaller, general effect for other, previously unseen Chinese characters or polygons as compared against neutral, previously unseen tokens of previously unseen types. Next, Nanay argues that my experiments are MEE-superdeterminate, not MEE-determinable, and that only the latter could be used to support an antirealist position. Fine. This type of experiment might, for example, present many landscapes by Sisley and test for an increase in the appreciation of other Sisley landscapes, perhaps as opposed to those of Pissarro. This is a good idea. 3

But since by the arguments I presented above I don t think that I am an antirealist, this shouldn t have any force against my claims. I claim, ceteris paribus, that mere exposure can play a role in canon maintenance through the building up of our (the public s) professed liking of particular pictures. The intended force of my work was to show that aesthetic realism isn t enough; not that aesthetic antirealism is all. In Conclusion I confess that I don t think of myself as either an aesthetic antirealist or an aesthetic realist. I simply don t know where beyond the avenues that I have explored the perceived quality of an artwork can generally be said to come from. I thus find the only defensible position to be a hybrid view that endorses perceptual learning from mere exposure combined with cultural education on the one hand while maintaining an agnostic eye towards aesthetic realism on the other. This may be messy, but perhaps a psychologist is used to tolerating more mess than a philosopher. Personally, when reflecting on any artwork that has deeply affected me, I find that my perception of the virtuosity of the artist is very important. This reflection is general to all the arts that I enjoy graphic and sculptural arts, dance, music, literature and movies and it goes for sports, too. Nonetheless, I recognize that virtuosity without a something else can be pretty empty. For me, some of the something else has to do vaguely with form and my emotional response the work has to speak to me. But I can t volunteer much further insight beyond that. If anyone could convince me about how the inherent quality of an artwork might be assessed, it would be fun to try to test the idea. References Bornstein, Robert F. (1989). Exposure and affect: Overview and meta-analysis of research, 1968-1987, Psychological Bulletin, 106, 265-289. Cutting, James E. (2003). Gustave Caillebotte, French Impressionism, and mere exposure, Psychonomic Bulletin and Review, 10, 319-343. Cutting, James E. (2006). Impressionism and its canon. Washington, DC: University Press of America. Maynard, Patrick (2007). Review of Impressionism and its canon. Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 65, 246-248. Meskin, Aaron, Mark Phelan, Margaret Moore & Matthew Kieran (2013). Mere exposure to bad art, British Journal of Aesthetics, 53, 139-164. Monahan, Jennifer L., Sheila T. Murphy, & Robert B. Zajonc (2000). Subliminal mere exposure: Specific, general, and diffuse effects, Psychological Science, 11, 462-466. Nanay, Bence (2014). Perceptual learning, the mere exposure effect and aesthetic antirealism, forthcoming in Leonardo. Rosenberg, Jakob (1968). On quality in art. London: Phaidon Press. Wollheim, Richard (1987). Painting as an Art. London: Thames and Hudson. 4

Manuscript received 19 September 2014. James E. Cutting is a Susan Linn Sage Professor of Psychology at Cornell University and author of Perception with an Eye for Motion (MIT Press, 1986), Impressionism and its Canon (University Press of America, 2006) and over 100 scientific articles on various aspects of perception. 5