Ithaque : Revue de philosophie de l'université de Montréal

Similar documents
Metaphors we live by. Structural metaphors. Orientational metaphors. A personal summary

Brandom s Reconstructive Rationality. Some Pragmatist Themes

Tamar Sovran Scientific work 1. The study of meaning My work focuses on the study of meaning and meaning relations. I am interested in the duality of

Necessity in Kant; Subjective and Objective

Sidestepping the holes of holism

Truth and Method in Unification Thought: A Preparatory Analysis

Thomas Szanto: Bewusstsein, Intentionalität und mentale Repräsentation. Husserl und die analytische Philosophie des Geistes

Edward Winters. Aesthetics and Architecture. London: Continuum, 2007, 179 pp. ISBN

Mixing Metaphors. Mark G. Lee and John A. Barnden

An Intense Defence of Gadamer s Significance for Aesthetics

What Can Experimental Philosophy Do? David Chalmers

Action, Criticism & Theory for Music Education

WHITEHEAD'S PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE AND METAPHYSICS

Cover Page. The handle holds various files of this Leiden University dissertation.

POST-KANTIAN AUTONOMIST AESTHETICS AS APPLIED ETHICS ETHICAL SUBSTRATUM OF PURIST LITERARY CRITICISM IN 20 TH CENTURY

1/9. The B-Deduction

1/8. Axioms of Intuition

that would join theoretical philosophy (metaphysics) and practical philosophy (ethics)?

Investigating subjectivity

REVIEW ARTICLE IDEAL EMBODIMENT: KANT S THEORY OF SENSIBILITY

Interdepartmental Learning Outcomes

Gestalt, Perception and Literature

MODULE 4. Is Philosophy Research? Music Education Philosophy Journals and Symposia

Philip Kitcher and Gillian Barker, Philosophy of Science: A New Introduction, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2014, pp. 192

The Body in the Mind: The Bodily Basis of Meaning, Imagination and Reason by Mark Johnson, Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1987

Sight and Sensibility: Evaluating Pictures Mind, Vol April 2008 Mind Association 2008

Natika Newton, Foundations of Understanding. (John Benjamins, 1996). 210 pages, $34.95.

Phenomenology Glossary

How 'Straight' Has Developed Its Meanings - Based on a metaphysical theory

SocioBrains THE INTEGRATED APPROACH TO THE STUDY OF ART

Part IV Social Science and Network Theory

Editor s Introduction

Action, Criticism & Theory for Music Education

Heideggerian Ontology: A Philosophic Base for Arts and Humanties Education

Embodied music cognition and mediation technology

Intersubjectivity and Language

Conclusion. One way of characterizing the project Kant undertakes in the Critique of Pure Reason is by

Creative Actualization: A Meliorist Theory of Values

Qualitative Design and Measurement Objectives 1. Describe five approaches to questions posed in qualitative research 2. Describe the relationship betw

Kant, Peirce, Dewey: on the Supremacy of Practice over Theory

Philosophy of Science: The Pragmatic Alternative April 2017 Center for Philosophy of Science University of Pittsburgh ABSTRACTS

AN INSIGHT INTO CONTEMPORARY THEORY OF METAPHOR

Methods, Topics, and Trends in Recent Business History Scholarship

The Cognitive Nature of Metonymy and Its Implications for English Vocabulary Teaching

Chapter One. Introduction to the Dissertation: Philosophy, Developmental Psychology, and Intuition

PROFESSION WITHOUT DISCIPLINE WOULD BE BLIND

PAUL REDDING S CONTINENTAL IDEALISM (AND DELEUZE S CONTINUATION OF THE IDEALIST TRADITION) Sean Bowden

The Strengths and Weaknesses of Frege's Critique of Locke By Tony Walton

Rusudan Japaridze SYNESTHETIC METAPHORS IN WILLIAM BUTLER YEATS POETRY

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at

TERMS & CONCEPTS. The Critical Analytic Vocabulary of the English Language A GLOSSARY OF CRITICAL THINKING


How to write a RILM thesis Guidelines

THESIS MIND AND WORLD IN KANT S THEORY OF SENSATION. Submitted by. Jessica Murski. Department of Philosophy

David Katan. Translating Cultures, An Introduction for Translators, Interpreters and Mediators. Manchester, St. Jerome Publishing, 1999, 271 p.

Introduction SABINE FLACH, DANIEL MARGULIES, AND JAN SÖFFNER

How Semantics is Embodied through Visual Representation: Image Schemas in the Art of Chinese Calligraphy *

observation and conceptual interpretation

The Human Intellect: Aristotle s Conception of Νοῦς in his De Anima. Caleb Cohoe

Postmodernism. thus one must review the central tenants of Enlightenment philosophy

GRADUATE SEMINARS

44 Iconicity in Peircean situated cognitive Semiotics

Seven remarks on artistic research. Per Zetterfalk Moving Image Production, Högskolan Dalarna, Falun, Sweden

KANT S TRANSCENDENTAL LOGIC

Naïve realism without disjunctivism about experience

Visual Argumentation in Commercials: the Tulip Test 1

THE ECOLOGICAL MEANING OF EMBODIMENT

Metaphors in the Discourse of Jazz. Kenneth W. Cook Russell T. Alfonso

Spatial Formations. Installation Art between Image and Stage.

Challenging the View That Science is Value Free

IMPORTANT QUOTATIONS

Theories and Activities of Conceptual Artists: An Aesthetic Inquiry

1/8. The Third Paralogism and the Transcendental Unity of Apperception

VALUES AND VALUING [Adapted from Carl Mitcham, ed., Encyclopedia of Science, Technology, and Ethics (New York: Macmillan Reference, 2005).

Humanities Learning Outcomes

Inter-subjective Judgment

ENVIRONMENTAL EXPERIENCE: Beyond Aesthetic Subjectivism and Objectivism

CHAPTER 2 THEORETICAL FRAMEWORK

1. What is Phenomenology?

Profile of requirements for Master Theses

Architecture is epistemologically

PHD THESIS SUMMARY: Phenomenology and economics PETR ŠPECIÁN

What is (an) emotion?

Robert Pirsig offers a critique of academic writing.

1/10. The A-Deduction

National Standards for Visual Art The National Standards for Arts Education

2015, Adelaide Using stories to bridge the chasm between perspectives

M. Chirimuuta s Adverbialism About Color. Anil Gupta University of Pittsburgh. I. Color Adverbialism

The Debate on Research in the Arts

Is composition a mode of performing? Questioning musical meaning

Pragmatism and Experience in Contemporary Debates

Review of David Woodruff Smith and Amie L. Thomasson, eds., Phenomenology and the Philosophy of Mind, 2005, Oxford University Press.

Categories and Schemata

Meaning, Being and Expression: A Phenomenological Justification for Interdisciplinary Scholarship

UNIT SPECIFICATION FOR EXCHANGE AND STUDY ABROAD

The Enactive Approach to Qualitative Ontology: In Search of New Categories

The design value of business

PHILOSOPHY. Grade: E D C B A. Mark range: The range and suitability of the work submitted

10/24/2016 RESEARCH METHODOLOGY Lecture 4: Research Paradigms Paradigm is E- mail Mobile

Department of American Studies M.A. thesis requirements

Transcription:

Cet article a été téléchargé sur le site de la revue Ithaque : www.revueithaque.org Ithaque : Revue de philosophie de l'université de Montréal Pour plus de détails sur les dates de parution et comment soumettre un article, veuillez consulter le site de la revue : http://www.revueithaque.org Pour citer cet article : Westra, A. (2008) «Mark Johnson, The Meaning of the Body : Aesthethics of Human Understanding, Chicago, The University of Chicago Press, 2007, 308 p.», Ithaque, 2, p. 163-168. URL : http://www.revueithaque.org/fichiers/ithaque2/12westra.pdf Cet article est publié sous licence Creative Commons «Paternité + Pas d utilisation commerciale + Partage à l'identique» : https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-sa/2.5/ca/deed.fr

Mark JOHNSON, The Meaning of the Body: Aesthetics of Human Understanding, Chicago, The University of Chicago Press, 2007. 308 pages. Adam Westra Mark Johnson is Knight Professor of Liberal Arts and Sciences in the Department of Philosophy at the University of Oregon. His name is most widely known in conjunction with that of his collaborator, George Lakoff, who is Professor of Linguistics at the University of California, Berkeley. In their popular book Metaphors We Live By (1980), Lakoff and Johnson argued for the pervasive role of metaphor in human language, cognition, and everyday life. Their second major collaboration, Philosophy in the Flesh: The Embodied Mind and Its Challenge to Western Thought (1999), applied the theses and analytical techniques of the first work to the philosophical tradition. Lakoff and Johnson argued for the ubiquity of metaphor in philosophical concepts and theories, and criticized traditional and contemporary philosophical treatments of metaphor. The metaphorical nature of cognition, and the structuring of metaphor by the body, lead logically to the notion of embodiment; i.e. the thesis that human thinking intimately depends on the human body. It is this theme that Johnson pursued in The Body in the Mind: The Bodily Basis of Meaning, Imagination, and Reason (1990), and, most recently, in The Meaning of the Body: Aesthetics of Human Understanding (2007). Johnson identifies the topic of The Meaning of the Body in his characteristically direct and simple style: This book is about meaning what it is, where it comes from, and how it is made. The guiding theme is that meaning grows from our visceral connections to life and the bodily conditions of life (ix). The bulk of the book advances the thesis that what we call mind and what we call body are not two things, but rather aspects of one organic process, so that all our meaning, thought, and language emerge from the aesthetic

Adam Westra dimensions of this embodied activity (1). 1 Johnson s real target, however, is not metaphysical dualism so much as the disembodied view of meaning to which it gives rise (7). In the Introduction, entitled Meaning Is More Than Words and Deeper Than Concepts, Johnson contrasts his embodied theory of meaning with what he sees as the dominant approach to meaning in contemporary Anglo-American analytic philosophy; according to the conceptual-propositional theory, meaning derives solely from concepts in propositions, which are taken to have no inherent connection to the human body. John Dewey s principle of continuity, which will appear in many guises over the course of the investigation and serve as its guiding thread, is here introduced, but its exact meaning and status are not made sufficiently clear. 2 The book is organized into three main sections. Part I gives a thick description of the bodily origin of meaning at its most primitive. The first chapter draws on contemporary phenomenology to suggest that human beings first begin to make sense of their bodies and their environments through the primordial experience of bodily movement. This form of sense-making is qualitative, pre-linguistic, and mostly non-conscious, yet it forms the ultimate basis for even the most abstract conceptualization. Here, Johnson jumps ahead to give the reader a sense of how the overall argument of the book unfolds. In addition to concepts whose meanings seem obviously to depend on the experience of bodily motion, such as curved, straight, and vertical, so too does the abstract concept of time: We (adults) conceptualize time via deep, systematic, spatial-movement metaphors in which the passage of time is understood as relative motion in space (28). Our body-based, experiential understanding of how objects move in space relative to our bodies is mapped, via metaphor, onto the concept of time. We metaphorically conceptualize the passage of 1 While Johnson prefers to describe his investigation by the term aesthetics, it could also be called a hermeneutics of embodiment. 2 The status of this principle does not seem to be entirely consistent in Johnson s argument; at various points, it seems to function as an assumption, formal theoretical requirement, methodological principle, hypothesis, or conclusion. 164

The Meaning of the Body time as though it were an object moving towards us in space (this is not, Johnson stresses, a literal comparison). This body-based understanding then finds its expression in language, as, for example, when we speak of Tuesday following (or coming after) Monday (30). Conceptual metaphor realizes the crucial continuity that exists between our mostly non-conscious experience of embodied meaning and our seemingly disembodied acts of thinking and reasoning (31). The rest of Part 1 describes other qualities and structures of embodied meaning. 3 Chapter 2 posits continuity between adult sensemaking and the pre-linguistic, affective, and inter-subjective ways in which infants begin to make sense of themselves and their environments. In Chapter 3, Johnson draws on the cognitive neuroscience of Antonio Damasio to argue that embodied humans interpret their environment through their emotional responses, which are physiologically realized in the body. Chapter 4 presents Dewey s notion that the analysis of any situation takes place within its overall felt quality. In Chapter 5, Johnson endorses William James s radical thesis that all thinking, including logical reasoning, is grounded in feeling; Johnson writes: Human thinking is a continuous feeling-thinking process that is forever tied to our body s monitoring of its own states (98). 4 While the first part of the book draws on phenomenology, psychology, and pragmatism, the second part turns to the cognitive sciences. Johnson places human cognition on a continuum with that of animals, with the aim of showing that human thinking is embodied, situated, and goal-directed and does not, contra representationalist theories of mind, rely on internal symbols which represent and refer to external things and events, as Jerry Fodor maintains (112). Johnson then gives a fuller account of how abstract concepts come to be vested with bodily meaning through conceptual metaphor, along 3 It is a pity that Johnson has apparently not read Proust, as the latter s works would have provided excellent illustrations of many of his phenomenological descriptions, and would also have reminded him of the crucial importance of memory in perception, which he neglects to discuss. 4 Incidentally, this thesis suggests an experiment to test its own truth: read it to an analytic philosopher and then observe whether his hackles do indeed physically rise. 165

Adam Westra the lines of the time as a moving object analysis outlined above. Furthermore, Johnson puts forward the fascinating (albeit admittedly tentative) suggestion that the structural mappings inherent to metaphor may have neural correlates in the brain. The overall thrust of this section is to provide empirical evidence from contemporary cognitive science to support the embodied theory of meaning. Part 3 is an excursus into the realm of art. Johnson endeavors to defend, through analyses of particular works of art taken from painting, literature, and music, that artistic creation is meaning-making at its most powerful, and, furthermore, that the meaning manifested by works of art is intrinsically connected to the human body. The aesthetics of embodied meaning developed in the previous two sections is here illustrated and applied. The argument relies heavily on Dewey, whose strongly positive appraisal of the value of art is set up in opposition to the subjectivization of the aesthetic (Johnson cites Gadamer s phrase) brought about by Kant s Critique of Judgment and its legacy in the analytic tradition, i.e. the denial that aesthetic judgments carry cognitive value and the subsequent marginalization of aesthetics as a discipline. 5 In the final chapter, Johnson recapitulates the book s argument and explicates, in a series of numbered points, his notions of meaning and of body, explicitly contrasting his views with the conceptions of analytic philosophy. Just as in Metaphors We Live By and Philosophy in the Flesh, a strong polemical element runs right through this work. The methodology alone, which draws on pragmatism, phenomenology, the cognitive sciences, and art, challenges conventional analytic argumentation. Johnson s primary criticism of the tradition in which he was educated is not that its theories of meaning are false, but that contemporary analytic philosophy as a whole is not meaningful. Seen from this angle, Johnson s own thesis of embodied meaning forms just one premise in the book s overall polemical argument, which can be reconstructed as follows: philosophy ought to be meaningful to people. Meaningful philosophy deals with 5 Johnson regularly gives courses on Kant s aesthetics at the University of Oregon. 166

The Meaning of the Body human meaning. Human meaning is embodied. Analytic philosophy does not recognize embodied, hence, human meaning. Therefore, analytic philosophy is not meaningful. Therefore, the necessary remedy for our current problematic state must be a non-dualistic, embodied view of meaning, concepts, mind, thought, language, and values... a new philosophy (264). Johnson s essentially humanistic critique, whether or not one agrees with all of the stages of its argument, is an interesting phenomenon in and of itself. It is indeed, if nothing else, a new philosophy: Johnson and Lakoff s approach has only been visible on the philosophical scene for the last twenty-five years, and the bibliography of this 2007 publication contains references to numerous recent, current, and forthcoming titles in a range of up-and-coming fields. 6 Johnson s interdisciplinary methodology, expressed in an accessible style, has made a new form of philosophical writing available to a relatively wide audience. In addition, this critique of analytic philosophy is distinct from those voiced from outside of the tradition, and even from that of Richard Rorty, who, like Johnson, mounted a pragmatism-inspired rejection of the tradition in which he had been schooled. 7 Reflection upon the polemical aspect of Johnson s work raises important questions about the nature of contemporary philosophy. Ought philosophy to be meaningful? The answer is not self-evident; the history of philosophy bears witness to many different conceptions of what philosophy ought first and foremost to be, such as true (e.g. Leibniz), revolutionary (e.g. Marx), or scientifically rigorous (e.g. Husserl). Moreover, is a philosophical theory of meaning, ipso facto, meaningful? This too requires reflection a theory of truth, 6 Referring to the most recent developments in the empirical sciences of the mind is a methodological principle for Johnson. 7 Johnson mentions Rorty, with whom he parts ways because of the latter s dismissal of metaphor. Curiously, and disappointingly, Johnson at no point refers to the later Wittgenstein, who bitingly criticized literal/logical conceptual analysis, and stressed the importance of the human body and of the pragmatic principle of use to the meanings of words. 167

Adam Westra for example, is not necessarily true. Furthermore, meaning itself is perhaps not the topic that is most meaningful to people generally; ethical issues, it could be argued, are more directly relevant to human life. Indeed, Johnson s own theory of meaning is not as meaningful as could be desired. While the book contains fascinating ideas and discoveries from several fields that are not usually found together and is well worth reading for this reason alone the result is more an agglomeration or enumeration than a powerful philosophical synthesis. 8 A challenging and promising new direction in contemporary philosophy, embodiment theory needs to be fleshed out. 8 For example, the body, for Johnson, is biological, ecological, phenomenological, social, and cultural; such an account is commendably broad and inclusive, but the full meanings of these concepts can only emerge from a consideration of their relations to each other in a theoretical synthesis. 168