Draft Date 10/20/10 Draft submitted for publication: Please do not cite without permission

Similar documents
PHIL 480: Seminar in the History of Philosophy Building Moral Character: Neo-Confucianism and Moral Psychology

Repugnance as Performance Error: The Role of Disgust in Bioethical Intuitions

Moral Judgment and Emotions

The Unbearable Vagueness of Essence : Forty-Four Clarification Questions for Gray, Young, and Waytz

The Neosentimentalist Argument Against Moral Rationalism: Some Critical Observations

Evaluative Mind: Extraneous Influences on Morality, Aesthetics, and Perception

The Psychology of Justice

Understanding the Effects of Disgust and Political Ideology on Moral Judgment Through Photography

Intentionality, morality, and the incest taboo in Madagascar. Paulo Sousa* Queen s University, Belfast, Institute of Cognition and Culture.

Image and Imagination

What Can Experimental Philosophy Do? David Chalmers

THE EMPIRICAL IDENTITY OF MORAL JUDGEMENT

Looking Past Pleasure : Anger, Confusion, Disgust, Pride, Surprise, and Other Unusual Aesthetic Emotions

The Embedding Problem for Non-Cognitivism; Introduction to Cognitivism; Motivational Externalism

Chapter 6: Ways of knowing Emotion (p. 145)

Confusion and Interest: The Role of Knowledge Emotions in Aesthetic Experience

The Emotion Challenge Towards A Sentimentalist Account of Universal Moral Grammar

Get Your Own Top-Grade Paper

The Limits of Appealing to Disgust

Psychopathy and internalism

Philosophical Issues, 18, Interdisciplinary Core Philosophy, 2008 SENTIMENTALIST PLURALISM: MORAL PSYCHOLOGY AND PHILOSOPHICAL ETHICS

Whose Mind Matters More The Agent or the Artist? An Investigation of Ethical and Aesthetic Evaluations

With thanks to Seana Coulson and Katherine De Long!

Can emotion-based moral disagreements be resolved?

Emotions from the Perspective of Analytic Aesthetics

Music Performance Panel: NICI / MMM Position Statement

Exploring the Role of Identification and Moral Disengagement in the Enjoyment of an Antihero Television Series

Simulated killing. Michael Lacewing

What do our appreciation of tonal music and tea roses, our acquisition of the concepts

UNIT SPECIFICATION FOR EXCHANGE AND STUDY ABROAD

Sentimentalism and Moral Dilemmas. András SZIGETI UiT The Arctic University of Norway/Linköping University

WHY DO PEOPLE CARE ABOUT REPUTATION?

THE EMOTIONAL BASIS OF MORAL JUDGMENTS

BENTHAM AND WELFARISM. What is the aim of social policy and the law what ends or goals should they aim to bring about?

Expressive information

1/8. The Third Paralogism and the Transcendental Unity of Apperception

PROFESSORS: Bonnie B. Bowers (chair), George W. Ledger ASSOCIATE PROFESSORS: Richard L. Michalski (on leave short & spring terms), Tiffany A.

Normative and Positive Economics

Chapter 14 Art Lesson Plans

Sentimentalism, Affective Response, and the Justification of Normative Moral Judgments

Katie Rhodes, Ph.D., LCSW Learn to Feel Better

Welcome to Interface Aesthetics 2008! Interface Aesthetics 01/28/08

Moral Agency. An Embodied Narrative Approach. R. E. Hardt. PhD Philosophy The University of Edinburgh

I like those glasses on you, but not in the mirror: Fluency, preference, and virtual mirrors

PSYCHOLOGY (PSY) Psychology (PSY) 1

Natural Scenes Are Indeed Preferred, but Image Quality Might Have the Last Word

Learning Approaches. What We Will Cover in This Section. Overview

The Roles of Politeness and Humor in the Asymmetry of Affect in Verbal Irony

Ideological and Political Education Under the Perspective of Receptive Aesthetics Jie Zhang, Weifang Zhong

Comparison, Categorization, and Metaphor Comprehension

The Role of Public Opprobrium in Adjusting Socio-Legal Behavior

Aesthetic experience of beautiful and ugly persons: a critique

Bas C. van Fraassen, Scientific Representation: Paradoxes of Perspective, Oxford University Press, 2008.

Affective response to a set of new musical stimuli W. Trey Hill & Jack A. Palmer Psychological Reports, 106,

The Human Intellect: Aristotle s Conception of Νοῦς in his De Anima. Caleb Cohoe

Boyd, Robert and Richerson, Peter J., The Origin and Evolution of Cultures, Oxford University Press, 2005, 456pp, $35.00 (pbk), ISBN X.

This manuscript was published as: Ruch, W. (1997). Laughter and temperament. In: P. Ekman & E. L. Rosenberg (Eds.), What the face reveals: Basic and

Semi-Fundamental Moral Disagreement and Non- Morally Fundamental Moral Disagreement

Psychology PSY 312 BRAIN AND BEHAVIOR. (3)

Surprise & emotion. Theoretical paper Key conference theme: Interest, surprise and delight

Kant: Notes on the Critique of Judgment

Psychological Science

Empathy and Engagement with Beauty. Amy Smith. Rhett Diessner. Dan M. Mayton II. Lewis-Clark State College

ALIGNING WITH THE GOOD

MELODIC AND RHYTHMIC CONTRASTS IN EMOTIONAL SPEECH AND MUSIC

DETERMINING HOW PEOPLE FEEL DURING MOVIES Kennedy Byrd Cary Academy ABSTRACT

Can parents influence children s music preferences and positively shape their development? Dr Hauke Egermann

Department of Philosophy, University of Utah, Salt Lake City, UT 84112

Consumer Choice Bias Due to Number Symmetry: Evidence from Real Estate Prices. AUTHOR(S): John Dobson, Larry Gorman, and Melissa Diane Moore

Deconstructing Prinz s moral theory. Desconstruindo a teoria moral de Prinz

Introduction SABINE FLACH, DANIEL MARGULIES, AND JAN SÖFFNER

CAROL HUNTS University of Kansas

Recently Published Book Spotlight: The Theory and Practice of Experimental Philosophy

Lecture 24. Social Hierarchy. Social Power Inhibition vs. disinhibition

UNIT SPECIFICATION FOR EXCHANGE AND STUDY ABROAD

What is music as a cognitive ability?

Tinnitus can be helped. Let us help you.

Satoshi Kawase Soai University, Japan. Satoshi Obata The University of Electro-Communications, Japan. Article

Disposition development in drama: the role of moral, immoral and ambiguously moral characters

REVIEW ARTICLE IDEAL EMBODIMENT: KANT S THEORY OF SENSIBILITY

Psychology. 526 Psychology. Faculty and Offices. Degree Awarded. A.A. Degree: Psychology. Program Student Learning Outcomes

Formalization: methodology and concrete examples

Praxis Filosófica ISSN: Universidad del Valle Colombia

Advanced Placement English Language & Composition Summer Reading Assignment

Why Pleasure Gains Fifth Rank: Against the Anti-Hedonist Interpretation of the Philebus 1

What counts as a convincing scientific argument? Are the standards for such evaluation

Domains of Inquiry (An Instrumental Model) and the Theory of Evolution. American Scientific Affiliation, 21 July, 2012

Psychology. Psychology 499. Degrees Awarded. A.A. Degree: Psychology. Faculty and Offices. Associate in Arts Degree: Psychology

The Power of Listening

Trauma & Treatment: Neurologic Music Therapy and Functional Brain Changes. Suzanne Oliver, MT-BC, NMT Fellow Ezequiel Bautista, MT-BC, NMT

Rational Agency and Normative Concepts by Geoffrey Sayre-McCord UNC/Chapel Hill [for discussion at the Research Triangle Ethics Circle] Introduction

Manipulation through Emotion: An Analysis of Save the Whales, Screw the Shrimp

KINDS (NATURAL KINDS VS. HUMAN KINDS)

Moral Geography and Exploration of the Moral Possibility Space

Psychology. PSY 199 Special Topics in Psychology See All-University 199 course description.

Thesis-Defense Paper Project Phi 335 Epistemology Jared Bates, Winter 2014

Moral Stages: A Current Formulation and a Response to Critics

Is Architecture Beautiful? Nikos A. Salingaros University of Texas at San Antonio May 2016

PART ONE: PHILOSOPHY AND THE OTHER MINDS

Challenging the View That Science is Value Free

Transcription:

On disgust and moral judgment David Pizarro 1, Yoel Inbar 2, & Chelsea Helion 1 1 Cornell University 2 Tilburg University Word Count (abstract, text, and refs): 1,498 Word Count (abstract): 58 Draft Date 10/20/10 Draft submitted for publication: Please do not cite without permission Contact info: David Pizarro 224 Uris Hall Department of Psychology Cornell University Ithaca, NY 14853 Phone: 607-255-3835 Email: dap54@cornell.edu

Abstract Despite the wealth of recent work implicating disgust as an emotion central to human morality, the nature of the causal relationship between disgust and moral judgment remains unclear. We distinguish between three related claims regarding this relationship, and argue that the most interesting claim (that disgust is a moralizing emotion) is the one with the least empirical support.

On disgust and moral judgment Disgust, an emotion that most likely evolved to keep us away from noxious substances and disease, seems especially active in our moral lives. People report feeling disgust in response to many immoral acts (e.g., Rozin, Lowery, Haidt, & Inada, 1999), make more severe moral judgments when feeling disgust (e.g., Wheatley & Haidt, 2005), and are more likely to view certain acts as immoral if they have a tendency to be easily disgusted (Horberg, Oveis, Keltner, & Cohen, 2009; Inbar, Pizarro, Knobe & Bloom, 2009). Yet despite this work implicating disgust as important to moral judgment, the nature of the causal relationship between the two remains unclear. This may be because, although the bulk of empirical work on the topic may lend support to the general claim that disgust and moral judgment are causally connected, little attempt has been made to distinguish between more specific claims about how they are connected. In what follows, we distinguish between three versions of this general claim, review evidence for each, and argue that the most interesting of the three is the one with the least empirical support. Disgust as a consequence of moral violations. The first version of the claim that disgust bears a special causal relationship to moral judgment is that disgust is experienced as a result of an appraisal that a moral violation has occurred. For instance, some have argued that disgust is uniquely experienced in response to moral purity violations (e.g., Rozin, Lowery, Imada, & Haidt, 1999), or other taboo moral violations (Gutierrez & Ginner-Sorolla, 2007). In support of this view, researchers have

shown that participants report disgust at moral violations that cannot be justified by appeals to harm (e.g., zoophilic acts). However, because the moral violations described in these experiments often contain references to non-moral core disgust elicitors (e.g., Moll et al., 2005), it is unclear that the disgust felt by participants actually results from the moral appraisal. One notable exception comes from recent evidence demonstrating that participants who receive unfair offers in an ultimatum game demonstrate facial muscle activation (as measured by EMG) consistent with the expression of disgust even in the absence of a core disgust elicitor (Chapman, Kim, Susskind, & Anderson, 2009). Disgust as an amplifier of moral judgment. A second claim regarding the relationship between disgust and morality is that disgust amplifies moral evaluations it makes wrong things seem even more wrong. This has been demonstrated in experiments in which disgust is manipulated in a manner that is extrinsic to the moral act being evaluated (e.g., through the use of film clips). Note, however, that these studies typically do not show that disgust exerts a domain-specific causal influence on moral judgment, rather than simply shifting all judgments toward the negative. For instance, while it has been demonstrated that inducing disgust can make individuals harsher judges of moral violations (Wheatley & Haidt, 2005), it may be that individuals induced to feel disgust would also judge individuals more harshly for other actions (e.g., job performance or a social interaction) or in other domains (e.g., attractiveness, intelligence). Experimental designs that include only judgments of moral violations (or that limit their dependent variables to moral evaluations) cannot distinguish between the

claim that disgust can influence moral judgment and the claim that they exert a special influence on moral judgment. Disgust as a moralizing emotion. The strongest claim regarding the relationship between disgust and moral judgment is that morally neutral acts can enter the moral sphere by dint of their being perceived as disgusting. This claim is consistent with the finding that morally dumbfounded participants defend their (admittedly) irrational moral judgments with an appeal to the disgusting nature of an act. In these cases the presence of disgust appears to be neither a consequence of the moral appraisal (claim #1), nor does it appear that disgust is simply amplifying a moral judgment that would have been made in its absence (claim #2). Rather, the feeling of disgust seems to be taken as evidence by the participant that the act is wrong (consistent with the feelingas-information approach; Schwarz & Clore, 1988). Researchers (including us) often appear to endorse this claim despite the correlational nature of their findings. For instance, we have argued that disgust toward homosexual behavior may be the causal force underlying anti-gay moral attitudes (e.g., Inbar et al, 2009; researchers investigating moral vegetarianism and incest avoidance have argued similarly; Borg, Lieberman, & Kiehl, 2008; Rozin, Markwith, & Stoess, 1997). Yet despite its intiuitive appeal, the evidence for this claim is the weakest of the three. For one, moving beyond correlational evidence to the experimental work (in which disgust is manipulated) yields little in the way of support for this claim. Most of the experimental evidence suggests only amplification--that disgust causes immoral behaviors to seem more immoral. We are aware of two notable exceptions. The first is

from Wheatley & Haidt (2005), in which individuals who were hypnotized to feel disgust while evaluating a set of scenarios judged a neutral act (as judged by participants in the non-disgust control condition) to be immoral. The second is reported by Horberg et al. (2009) in which participants made to feel disgust by watching a film clip rated morally neutral but purity-violating behaviors (such as wearing mismatched clothes) as morally worse than did control subjects (who watched a sad film clip). Although these two pieces of evidence are promising indicators of disgust as exerting a moralizing effect, more experimental support is needed. Yet even with greater experimental support, a more obvious objection to the moralization hypothesis remains disgust cannot be sufficient for moralization to occur because there are a plethora of behaviors that are judged by most as disgusting but not immoral, such as eating pig brains or picking oneʼs nose in private (e.g., Royzman, Leeman & Baron, 2009). A credible defense of the claim that disgust exerts a moralizing influence would seem to require a plausible account of why it does not seem to moralize behaviors in most cases. One possibility is that disgust exerts a moralizing influence only on behaviors for which there already exist non-moral proscriptive norms (e.g., smoking; Nichols, 2004). In these cases, the pairing of disgust with (or the tendency to be disgusted by) the behavior might cause it to be pushed into the moral domain. Evidence for this view could be defended with longitudinal data comparing moral attitudes toward disgusting and non-disgusting behaviors that either have an existing (but non-moral) proscriptive norm and those which do not. If this view is correct, one

would expect moralization over time to occur only in the disgusting behaviors for which there are already conventional norms in place.

References Borg, J. S. Lieberman, D., & Kiehl, K. A. (2008) Infection, incest, & iniquity: Investigating the neural correlates of disgust and morality. Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience, 20(9), 1529-1546. Chapman, H., Kim, D., Susskind, J., & Anderson, A. (2009). In bad taste: Evidence for the oral origins of moral disgust. Science, 323(5918), 1222. Gutierrez, R., & Giner Sorolla, R. (2007). Anger, disgust, and presumption of harm as reactions to taboo-breaking behaviors. Emotion, 7(4), 853-868. Horberg, E. J., Oveis, C., Keltner, D., & Cohen, A. B. (2009). Disgust and the moralization of purity. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 97, 963-976. Inbar, Y., Pizarro, D.A., & Bloom, P. (2009) Conservatives are more easily disgusted than liberals. Cognition and Emotion, 23, 714-725. Inbar, Y., Pizarro, D.A., Knobe, J., & Bloom, P. (2009) Disgust sensitivity predicts intuitive disapproval of gays. Emotion, 9, 435-439. Moll, J., de Oliveira-Souza, R., Moll, F. T., Ignacio, F. A., Bramati, I. E., Caparelli- Daquer, E. M., & Eslinger, P. J. (2005). The moral affiliations of disgust: A functional MRI study. Cognitive and Behavioral Neurology, 18, 68-78. Nichols, S. 2004. Sentimental Rules: On the Natural Foundations of Moral Judgment. New York: Oxford University Press. Royzman, E. B., Leeman, R. F. & Baron, J. (2009). Unsentimental ethics: Toward a content-specific account of the moral-conventional distinction. Cognition, 112, 159 274. Rozin, P., Lowery, L., Imada, S., & Haidt, J. (1999). The CAD triad hypothesis: A

mapping between three moral emotions (contempt, anger, disgust) and three moral codes (community, autonomy, divinity). Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 76(4), 574-586. Rozin, P., Markwith, M., & Stoess, C. (1997). Moralization and becoming a vegetarian, Psychological Science, 8(2), 67-73. Schwarz, N., & Clore, G. L. (1988). How do I feel about it? The informative function of affective states. In K. Fiedler & J. Forgas (Eds.), Affect, cognition and social behavior (pp. 44-62). Toronto, Canada: Hogrefe. Wheatley, T., & Haidt, J. (2005). Hypnotic disgust makes moral judgments more severe. Psychological Science, 16, 780 784.