Rehabilitating Social Philosophy s Normative Criteria

Similar documents
By Rahel Jaeggi Suhrkamp, 2014, pbk 20, ISBN , 451pp. by Hans Arentshorst

This is an electronic reprint of the original article. This reprint may differ from the original in pagination and typographic detail.

A Comprehensive Critical Study of Gadamer s Hermeneutics

HEGEL, ANALYTIC PHILOSOPHY AND THE RETURN OF METAPHYISCS Simon Lumsden

Critical Theory. Mark Olssen University of Surrey. Social Research at Frankfurt-am Main in The term critical theory was originally

NATURAL IMPURITIES IN SPIRIT? HEGELIANISM BETWEEN KANT AND HOBBES Heikki Ikäheimo

Introduction. Normative scepticism

Brandom s Reconstructive Rationality. Some Pragmatist Themes

The Meaning of Abstract and Concrete in Hegel and Marx

Necessity in Kant; Subjective and Objective

PH th Century Philosophy Ryerson University Department of Philosophy Mondays, 3-6pm Fall 2010

UNIT SPECIFICATION FOR EXCHANGE AND STUDY ABROAD

Metaphors we live by. Structural metaphors. Orientational metaphors. A personal summary

Kent Academic Repository

Review of Krzysztof Brzechczyn, Idealization XIII: Modeling in History

Lia Mela. Democritus University of Thrace. Keywords: modernity, reason, tradition, good, Frankfurt School, MacIntyre, Taylor

Philip Joseph Kain. Santa Clara University Scotts Valley, CA Santa Clara, CA fax

PHILOSOPHY. Grade: E D C B A. Mark range: The range and suitability of the work submitted

PAUL REDDING S CONTINENTAL IDEALISM (AND DELEUZE S CONTINUATION OF THE IDEALIST TRADITION) Sean Bowden

REVIEW ARTICLE IDEAL EMBODIMENT: KANT S THEORY OF SENSIBILITY

SUMMARY BOETHIUS AND THE PROBLEM OF UNIVERSALS

An Intense Defence of Gadamer s Significance for Aesthetics

Martin, Gottfried: Plato s doctrine of ideas [Platons Ideenlehre]. Berlin: Verlag Walter de Gruyter, 1973

This thesis is protected by copyright which belongs to the author.

The Free Will Which Wills the Free Will : On Marriage as a Paradigm of Freedom in Hegel s Philosophy of Right

Università della Svizzera italiana. Faculty of Communication Sciences. Master of Arts in Philosophy 2017/18

Ithaque : Revue de philosophie de l'université de Montréal

Review of David Woodruff Smith and Amie L. Thomasson, eds., Phenomenology and the Philosophy of Mind, 2005, Oxford University Press.

Hegel and Neurosis: Idealism, Phenomenology and Realism

HEGEL S CONCEPT OF ACTION

The Strengths and Weaknesses of Frege's Critique of Locke By Tony Walton

Krisis. Journal for contemporary philosophy

Having the World in View: Essays on Kant, Hegel, and Sellars

Sidestepping the holes of holism

Doctoral Thesis in Ancient Philosophy. The Problem of Categories: Plotinus as Synthesis of Plato and Aristotle

Integration, Ambivalence, and Mental Conflict

Idealism and Pragmatism: Transcendent Validity Claims in Habermas s Democratic Theory

Conclusion. One way of characterizing the project Kant undertakes in the Critique of Pure Reason is by

foucault s archaeology science and transformation David Webb

A Hegel-Marx Debate About the Relation of the Individual and Society

Department of Philosophy Florida State University

Manuel Bremer University Lecturer, Philosophy Department, University of Düsseldorf, Germany

PATOLOGIE SOCIALI PERCORSI NELLA TEORIA CRITICA CONTEMPORANEA

Dabney Townsend. Hume s Aesthetic Theory: Taste and Sentiment Timothy M. Costelloe Hume Studies Volume XXVIII, Number 1 (April, 2002)

observation and conceptual interpretation

Book Review. John Dewey s Philosophy of Spirit, with the 1897 Lecture on Hegel. Jeff Jackson. 130 Education and Culture 29 (1) (2013):

Current Issues in Pictorial Semiotics

Hans-Georg Gadamer, Truth and Method, 2d ed. transl. by Joel Weinsheimer and Donald G. Marshall (London : Sheed & Ward, 1989), pp [1960].

Principal version published in the University of Innsbruck Bulletin of 4 June 2012, Issue 31, No. 314

What Can Experimental Philosophy Do? David Chalmers

Naïve realism without disjunctivism about experience

M E M O. When the book is published, the University of Guelph will be acknowledged for their support (in the acknowledgements section of the book).

TRAGIC THOUGHTS AT THE END OF PHILOSOPHY

Truth and Method in Unification Thought: A Preparatory Analysis

ARISTOTLE AND THE UNITY CONDITION FOR SCIENTIFIC DEFINITIONS ALAN CODE [Discussion of DAVID CHARLES: ARISTOTLE ON MEANING AND ESSENCE]

SocioBrains THE INTEGRATED APPROACH TO THE STUDY OF ART

POST-KANTIAN AUTONOMIST AESTHETICS AS APPLIED ETHICS ETHICAL SUBSTRATUM OF PURIST LITERARY CRITICISM IN 20 TH CENTURY

Julie K. Ward. Ancient Philosophy 31 (2011) Mathesis Publications

Aristotle s Metaphysics

Review of "The Unexplained Intellect: Complexity, Time, and the Metaphysics of Embodied Thought"

The Aesthetic Within. Music and Philosophy as Autonomous Practice

Review of: The Rise and Fall of Structural Marxism: Althusser and His Influence by Ted Benton, Macmillan, 1984, 257 pages, by Lee Harvey

Sight and Sensibility: Evaluating Pictures Mind, Vol April 2008 Mind Association 2008

CAROL HUNTS University of Kansas

1/8. The Third Paralogism and the Transcendental Unity of Apperception

The topic of this Majors Seminar is Relativism how to formulate it, and how to evaluate arguments for and against it.

Philosophical Background to 19 th Century Modernism

Idealism and Pragmatism: "Transcendent" Validity Claims in Habermas's Democratic Theory

Mitchell ABOULAFIA, Transcendence. On selfdetermination

Charles Taylor s Langue/Parole and Alasdair MacIntyre s Networks of Giving and Receiving as a Foundation for a Positive Anti-Atomist Political Theory

Todd Hedrick

University of Huddersfield Repository

Freedom s Right. The Social Foundations of Democratic Life. Axel Honneth. polity. Translated by Joseph Ganahl

TROUBLING QUALITATIVE INQUIRY: ACCOUNTS AS DATA, AND AS PRODUCTS

Creative Actualization: A Meliorist Theory of Values

Please cite the published version in Human Studies, available at Springer via

Culture, Space and Time A Comparative Theory of Culture. Take-Aways

Critical Political Economy of Communication and the Problem of Method

Review of S. J. McGrath and Joseph Carew (eds.). Rethinking German Idealism, London: Palgrave Macmillan, pp.

Art, beauty and the Divine

The Social Constitution of the Body: Bodily Alienation and Bodily Integrity

CARE OF THE SELF IN THE GLOBAL ERA 1

The Human Intellect: Aristotle s Conception of Νοῦς in his De Anima. Caleb Cohoe

An Aristotelian Puzzle about Definition: Metaphysics VII.12 Alan Code

Bas C. van Fraassen, Scientific Representation: Paradoxes of Perspective, Oxford University Press, 2008.

Culture in Social Theory

Towards a Conflict Theory of Recognition: On the Constitution of Relations of Recognition in Conflict

Philosophy Pathways Issue th December 2016

Louis Althusser s Centrism

Perceptions and Hallucinations

Architecture as the Psyche of a Culture

Presented as part of the Colloquium Sponsored by the Lonergan Project at Marquette University on Lonergan s Philosophy and Theology

Herbert Marcuse s Review of John Dewey s Logic: The Theory of Inquiry 1

The Principle of Production and a Critique of Metaphysics: From the Perspective of Theory of Baudrillard

ENVIRONMENTAL EXPERIENCE: Beyond Aesthetic Subjectivism and Objectivism

Chapter 2: Karl Marx Test Bank

(Ulrich Schloesser/ Humboldt-Universität zu Berlin)

UNIVERSITY OF TORONTO INSTRUCTORSHIPS IN PHILOSOPHY CUPE Local 3902, Unit 1 SUMMER SESSION 2019

CRITICAL CONTEXTUAL EMPIRICISM AND ITS IMPLICATIONS

UNIT SPECIFICATION FOR EXCHANGE AND STUDY ABROAD

Transcription:

Rehabilitating Social Philosophy s Normative Criteria A Review of Rahel Jaeggi s Alienation, translated by Frederick Neuhouser and Alan E. Smith (New York: Columbia University Press, 2014), 267 pages. Loughlin Gleeson University of New South Wales Only recently translated from German into English some ten years after its initial publication, Rahel Jaeggi s Alienation aims to rehabilitate a key normative criterion within the tradition of social philosophy that has long been discredited, or at any rate underutilised. Jaeggi s aim, to be more precise, is to reestablish the critical concept of alienation [Entfremdung] in order to diagnose extant social pathologies or, in the terminology of the current issue, various modes of precarity that are either neglected by, or irreducible to, the prevailing Rawlsian account of (in-)justice. At the same time, Jaeggi is adamant that this diagnostic task or function cannot rely on any problematic essentialist claims for justificatory support à la Hegel and Marx. 1 Her approach is therefore neither strictly liberal nor universalist, but rather aims to mediate between these unsatisfying alternatives (48). Philament 22: Precarity philamentjournal.com 133

134 Philament 22: Precarity Alienation is divided into three discrete yet thematically linked parts. Part 1 sets out a historico-philosophical reconstruction of the critical concept of alienation. It begins with a preliminary definition of alienation as a relation of relationlessness [eine Beziehung der Beziehungslosigkeit] (22). That is to say, alienation does not designate a state or condition marked by the absence of a relation, but rather the presence of a normatively deficient relation to oneself, others, or the (social) world more generally. Jaeggi traces the origin of the concept of alienation back to the figures of Rousseau and Hegel. Whereas the former, in Jaeggi s view, identified systemic alienation in the form of the pathological dependence of subjects on false patterns of intersubjective recognition and morally vacuous social norms and institutions, the latter is said to have conceived of alienation in the exact opposite terms; namely, the cleavage between individual and society rather than in the individual s loss of self through society (28). From here, the evolution of the concept of alienation tracks two separate trajectories the socio-economic and existential instigated by Marx and Heidegger respectively. The Marxist trajectory links alienation to economic structures and conditions peculiar to capitalism, which systematically impede the ability of human beings to fully realise their species-essence [Gattungwesen] through non-alienated modes of production. By contrast, the Heideggerian trajectory concerns itself with various inauthentic phenomena that are, in a specific instance, by the deep-ontological detachment from one s innermost self. Leaving these conceptual and methodological differences to one side, Jaeggi devotes the remaining section of part 1 to an assessment of the concept of alienation in the light of the challenges posed by the two nominally unified camps of political liberalism and poststructuralism. To pose the challenges addressed in this section in the form of a question: has the dual descriptive-diagnostic appeal of alienation not been completely exhausted, since it is underpinned by certain objectivist and perfectionist premises that are irreconcilable with the historicist and value-pluralist tendencies of contemporary philosophical thought? While Jaeggi is intent on answering this question, she is also careful to avoid the pitfalls associated with Rawlsian and

Gleeson Rahel Jaeggi s Alienation 135 Foucauldian approaches (respectively, abstractness and an autonomy-denying conception of subjectivisation ). For this reason, Jaeggi posits that a modified conception of alienation, which is suitable to a contemporary readership, hinges on the ability of such a proposal to position itself midway between, as she puts it, ethical subjectivism and objectivism, between espousing from and espousing substantial moral conceptions of the good life, between abandoning the idea of autonomy and holding onto illusory conception of subjectivity (48). Key to this reconceptualisation is Jaeggi s establishment of an adequate evaluative criterion against which various alienated relations can be immanently criticised, one that makes no claim as to the fixed or immutable nature of the human life-form. 2 Jaeggi appeals here to the concept of appropriation [Aneignung], arguing that the conceptual inverse of alienation ought to be understood not in terms of freedom from external constraints (Hobbes), and still less in terms of eudaimonia (Aristotle). Appropriation should instead be understood as the positive capacity to establish practical relations to oneself, others, and society, such that one may take them to be one s own [sich zu Eigen zu machen] via a process of reflexive identification. As Jaeggi argues, The conception of appropriation refers to a way of establishing relations to oneself and to the world, a way of dealing with oneself and the world and of having oneself and the world at one s command [über sich verfügen können]. Alienation, as a disturbance in this relation, concerns the way these acts of relating to self and world are carried out, that is, whether processes of appropriation fail or are impeded. (51) According to this strictly formal definition, alienation implies an ethically deficient mode of praxis whereby subjects are unable not only to be reconciled with, but also actively transform aspects of themselves, others, and the social world. In consequence, indifference, reification, meaninglessness and even precarity are all species of alienation.

136 Philament 22: Precarity In contrast to the historico-philosophical orientation of part 1, part 2 concretely analyses the phenomenon of self-alienation [Selbstentfremdung] with reference to four case studies. For Jaeggi, the received view of self-alienation, which hypostatises the existence of a true, inner self that is unable to realise itself, amounts to nothing other than an antiquated, essentialist distortion. The alternative form of self-alienation that Jaeggi attempts to bring into view is defined as a condition in which one is unable in crucial respects to appropriate the life one is leading and in which one does not have oneself at one s command in what one does (61, emphasis in original). Under this categorial framework, Jaeggi looks first at the example of a young academic who, without directly intending it, settles down into the proverbial middle-class, suburban way of life a way of life to which he is nevertheless unable to relate to meaningfully as an instance of powerlessness. The second and third case studies, which involve an ambitious employee who attempts to affirm his place within his workplace, and a so-called giggling feminist whose self-image is belied by her own actions, serve to illuminate the phenomenon of self-alienation from the perspective of social roles and personal division respectively. Finally, indifference is embodied in the character of Perlmann, the protagonist in Pascal Mercier s novel Perlmann s Silence, inasmuch as his general mode of comportment as a linguistics professor is so saturated in apathy as to warrant the metaphorical description of him as permanently anesthetised. These examples of powerlessness, prescriptive roles, division, and brute indifference, all of which are instantiations of a broader phenomenon of self-alienation, do much more than simply bring the concept of alienation into sharp relief for the reader. For the light that these case studies shed on the psycho-social problems facing modern subjects is highly engaging and challenging, and evinces the kind of attention to everyday, practical situations too often missing from contemporary philosophy. In part 3, Jaeggi attempts to systematically explicate the model of subjectivity implied in her previous historico-philosophical and phenomenological analyses of alienation. Partaking of certain elements

Gleeson Rahel Jaeggi s Alienation 137 of German idealist (Hegelian) and existential philosophies, Jaeggi s so-called appropriative model of the self is distinguishable both from the traditional essentialist view of the subject and the post-modern take on subjectivity. The self, we read, is neither a fixed ontological structure endowed with universally applicable capacities and functions, nor a radically indeterminate entity comprised of a plurality of personality-forms whose realisation hinges on little more than free choice. Eschewing these two extremes, Jaeggi s conception of the self is simultaneously given and made through dynamic appropriative relations with oneself and others that are concretely embedded in the world (158, emphasis in original). The self therefore amounts, on this functionalist-expressivist model, to nothing other than a mode of doing that realises itself through those self-determined deeds or actions externalised within a shared social space. 3 Jaeggi s monograph concludes with the recognisable Hegelian thesis concerning the fundamentally social nature of human subjectivity. Developing an earlier train of thought, Jaeggi reaffirms that alienation can mean one of two very different things: either alienation from others and the social world (Hegel), or alienation by intersubjective-social conditions (Rousseau). A fierce proponent of the former camp, Jaeggi summarises her argument in these terms: My reconstruction of the concept of alienation has aimed to show that it is only by relating appropriatively to social practices that determine our lives and not by (to use Hegel s terms) abstractly negating them that an unaliented relation to self is possible (202). For Jaeggi, the flight or escape from those others by which one is necessarily determined is a mere illusion, as reflected in Hegel s concept of abstract freedom [abstrakte Freiheit]. Positively stated, then, other subjects and social-institutional structures or conditions assume the role of the essential determinants of human subjectivity insofar as both contribute to the actualisation of a non-alienated relation-to-self, itself understood somewhat inconsistently, it must be said in terms of the achievements of self-determination and self-realisation (204). On the whole, there can be little doubt that Alienation successfully realises its stated goal: to resurrect a central normative criterion

138 Philament 22: Precarity within the tradition of social philosophy. The great virtue of the monograph lies, in my view, in Jaeggi s consistent ability to chart a middle course between the two opposing stances she sets up between Rawlsian liberalism and its abstractness, on the one hand, and Hegelian and Marxist universalism and its putative ethical overburdening, on the other. With her modified conception of alienation, Jaeggi is therefore able to diagnose various distortions within the social field in a meaningful way, and therewith to maintain the viability of social philosophy as a specific discipline. 4 Having said this, questions remain over Alienation s exegetical and philosophical adequacy. One of the philosophical problems of Jaeggi s monograph is its failure to afford any systematic attention to the objective component of alienation. From part 2 onwards, the centrality of the subjective aspects of alienation are self-evident. While Jaeggi s treatment of self-alienation, appropriative subjectivity and other attendant concepts and phenomena are never positioned outside or beyond society, the fact that other subjects and social norms and institutions are addressed only ever passing seems to yield a truncated social-philosophical account, one that is lacking the requisite descriptive and normative depth. In view of Jaeggi s insistence that an ineliminable structural connection exists between self and society, one might have expected her monograph to say much more about alienated intersubjective and social relations and practices within contemporary societies, or at any rate the embeddedness of self-alienation within such relations and practices. 5 To this end, Alienation would appear to align much more with the Heideggerian, existential camp of alienation theories than with the Marxist, socio-economic camp, and future research would do well to redress this apparent one-sidedness. 6 One of the exegetical problems with Alienation is its all-too-common misrepresentation of Hegel s Realphilosophie and of his concept of freedom in particular. As recent scholarship attests, Hegel is increasingly being understood as a normative or evaluative essentialist of a broadly Aristotelian stripe, but not in the way, or for the problematic reasons, that Jaeggi outlines in Alienation. 7 In the Philosophy of Spirit,

Gleeson Rahel Jaeggi s Alienation 139 Hegel argues that concrete freedom [konkrete Freiheit], understood as the relational achievement of being-with-oneself-in-the-other [bei sich Selbstsein im Anderen], is the formal essence of spirit [Geist], or mutatis mutandis, of the human life-form. 8 Freedom so conceived applies not unlike Jaeggi s own model of appropriation, incidentally in a highly differentiated manner to all of those relations with others upon which human persons are necessarily dependent, including with internal and external nature, other persons, and historically conditioned social norms and institutions. Crucially, this reading is free of the kind of totalisation (unity, in Hegel, is always accompanied with difference), metaphysics (Geist qua God-like substance plays no role whatsoever in this reading), and substantialism (the actual content of concrete freedom is always necessarily historically and socially specific) commonly attributed to Hegel by Jaeggi, among others. It therefore arguably satisfies the very same theoretical criteria that Jaeggi seeks to introduce in Alienation; namely, normative or evaluative significance and formality. Though it will of course require further elaboration and justification, my own recommendation is that Hegelian concrete freedom assume ideally, alongside Jaeggi s own proposal of appropriation the role of an immanent evaluative criterion against which alienated relations in respect to various others can be criticised as defects [Mangle]. 9 The appeal to concrete freedom would also have the additional benefit of correcting a perceived flaw in Jaeggi s terminological-cum-philosophical formulation of the achieved state or condition of non-alienation, which, as I have intimated, seems to vacillate between the concepts of appropriation, self-determination, and self-realisation. If, as I am suggesting, Jaeggi s Hegel amounts to nothing more than a straw man, and her reluctance to embrace even weak versions of essentialism proves to be unfounded, then the Hegel identified above is as good an ally as any for contemporary social philosophers who, like Jaeggi, attempt to make good on their programmatic ambitions to normatively or evaluatively criticise extant social pathologies. 10

140 Philament 22: Precarity Notes 1. On the notion of social pathology and its programmatic function within social philosophy, see Axel Honneth, Pathologies of the Social: The Past and Present of Social Philosophy, in Disrespect: The Normative Foundations of Critical Theory (Cambridge: Polity Press, 2007), 3 49. 2. On the (left-)hegelian methodology of immanent critique, see Axel Honneth, Reconstructive Social Critique with a Genealogical Proviso: On the Frankfurt School, in Pathologies of Reason: On The Legacy of Critical Theory (New York: Columbia University Press, 2009), 43 53. 3. Here, Jaeggi comes very close to Robert Pippin s (post-kantian) Hegelian account of freedom as socially mediated rational self-determination. See Robert Pippin, Hegel s Practical Philosophy: Rational Agency as Ethical Life (New York: Cambridge University Press, 2008), 198 99. 4. Below I will argue against Jaeggi s misrepresentation of Hegel s universalism or evaluative essentialism. Most importantly of all, Hegelian essentialism, rather than being merely naturalistic pace Aristotle, is distinctly evaluative; in other words, it does not concern fixed or immutable natural potentials, but rather the ethicality of the distinctly spiritual [Gestig] phenomenon attributable to the human life-form. 5. So, too, one may well question the conspicuous absence of alienated relations to the natural world (as opposed to social world). 6. Axel Honneth has arguably made some progress in this direction with his recent work. See Axel Honneth, Freedom s Right: The Normative Foundations of Democratic Life, trans. Joseph Ganahl (Cambridge: Polity Press, 2014). 7. See Heikki Ikäheimo, Holism and Normative Essentialism in Hegel s Social Ontology, in Heikki Ikäheimo and Arto Laitinen (eds.) Recognition and Social Ontology (Leiden: Brill, 2011), 145 209; Allen Wood, Hegel s Ethical Thought (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1990), Robert Stern, Why Hegel Now (Again) and in What Form? (forthcoming). 8. As Hegel states: The formal essence of spirit is therefore freedom, the absolute negativity of the Notion as self-identity. G. W. F Hegel, The Philosophy of Mind, trans. W. Wallace and A. V. Miller (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2012), paragraph 382. 9. See my Contra Pippin: An Evaluative Essentialist and Holistic Reading of Hegelian Concrete Freedom (forthcoming in the Hegel-Jahrbuch). 10. See Heikki Ikäheimo, Ethical Perfectionism in Social Ontology A Hegelian Alternative (forthcoming in I That is We, We That is I Perspectives on Contemporary Hegel).