Action, Criticism & Theory for Music Education

Similar documents
Review of David Woodruff Smith and Amie L. Thomasson, eds., Phenomenology and the Philosophy of Mind, 2005, Oxford University Press.

Conclusion. One way of characterizing the project Kant undertakes in the Critique of Pure Reason is by

observation and conceptual interpretation

Action, Criticism & Theory for Music Education

Phenomenology and Non-Conceptual Content

The Polish Peasant in Europe and America. W. I. Thomas and Florian Znaniecki

Kęstas Kirtiklis Vilnius University Not by Communication Alone: The Importance of Epistemology in the Field of Communication Theory.

Action, Criticism & Theory for Music Education

1/9. The B-Deduction

James SCOTT JOHNSTON, John Dewey s Earlier Logical Theory

1/8. Axioms of Intuition

REVIEW ARTICLE IDEAL EMBODIMENT: KANT S THEORY OF SENSIBILITY

Creative Actualization: A Meliorist Theory of Values

ARISTOTLE AND THE UNITY CONDITION FOR SCIENTIFIC DEFINITIONS ALAN CODE [Discussion of DAVID CHARLES: ARISTOTLE ON MEANING AND ESSENCE]

Book Review. John Dewey s Philosophy of Spirit, with the 1897 Lecture on Hegel. Jeff Jackson. 130 Education and Culture 29 (1) (2013):

Philosophy of Science: The Pragmatic Alternative April 2017 Center for Philosophy of Science University of Pittsburgh ABSTRACTS

PH 8122: Topics in Philosophy: Phenomenology and the Problem of Passivity Fall 2013 Thursdays, 6-9 p.m, 440 JORG

Action, Criticism & Theory for Music Education

Action, Criticism & Theory for Music Education

PDF hosted at the Radboud Repository of the Radboud University Nijmegen

The Observer Story: Heinz von Foerster s Heritage. Siegfried J. Schmidt 1. Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2011

ENVIRONMENTAL EXPERIENCE: Beyond Aesthetic Subjectivism and Objectivism

Truth and Method in Unification Thought: A Preparatory Analysis

Categories and Schemata

Introduction SABINE FLACH, DANIEL MARGULIES, AND JAN SÖFFNER

Habit, Semeiotic Naturalism, and Unity among the Sciences Aaron Wilson

Ithaque : Revue de philosophie de l'université de Montréal

Nature's Perspectives

Logic and Philosophy of Science (LPS)

On The Search for a Perfect Language

Ralph K. Hawkins Bethel College Mishawaka, Indiana

Philosophical Background to 19 th Century Modernism

The topic of this Majors Seminar is Relativism how to formulate it, and how to evaluate arguments for and against it.

Unravelling the Dance: an exploration of dance s underdeveloped relationship

INTRODUCTION TO NONREPRESENTATION, THOMAS KUHN, AND LARRY LAUDAN

The Question of Equilibrium in Human Action and the Everyday Paradox of Rationality

TROUBLING QUALITATIVE INQUIRY: ACCOUNTS AS DATA, AND AS PRODUCTS

1/8. The Third Paralogism and the Transcendental Unity of Apperception

6AANB th Century Continental Philosophy. Basic information. Module description. Assessment methods and deadlines. Syllabus Academic year 2016/17

What counts as a convincing scientific argument? Are the standards for such evaluation

M E M O. When the book is published, the University of Guelph will be acknowledged for their support (in the acknowledgements section of the book).

Mixed Methods: In Search of a Paradigm

Qualitative Design and Measurement Objectives 1. Describe five approaches to questions posed in qualitative research 2. Describe the relationship betw

The Human Intellect: Aristotle s Conception of Νοῦς in his De Anima. Caleb Cohoe

Philip Kitcher and Gillian Barker, Philosophy of Science: A New Introduction, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2014, pp. 192

What Can Experimental Philosophy Do? David Chalmers

The Teaching Method of Creative Education

By Rahel Jaeggi Suhrkamp, 2014, pbk 20, ISBN , 451pp. by Hans Arentshorst

Natika Newton, Foundations of Understanding. (John Benjamins, 1996). 210 pages, $34.95.

Wilson, Tony: Understanding Media Users: From Theory to Practice. Wiley-Blackwell (2009). ISBN , pp. 219

PAUL REDDING S CONTINENTAL IDEALISM (AND DELEUZE S CONTINUATION OF THE IDEALIST TRADITION) Sean Bowden

The Shimer School Core Curriculum

TRAGIC THOUGHTS AT THE END OF PHILOSOPHY

Communication Studies Publication details, including instructions for authors and subscription information:

Interpretive and Critical Research Traditions

Mitchell ABOULAFIA, Transcendence. On selfdetermination

Rethinking the Aesthetic Experience: Kant s Subjective Universality

Penultimate Draft- Final version forthcoming in Philosophical Psychology

Action, Criticism & Theory for Music Education

Moral Judgment and Emotions

Curriculum Vitae: MARIA TALERO. Department of Philosophy University of Colorado at Denver

What is (an) emotion?

UNIT SPECIFICATION FOR EXCHANGE AND STUDY ABROAD

Are There Two Theories of Goodness in the Republic? A Response to Santas. Rachel Singpurwalla

Writing an Honors Preface

BOOK REVIEWS. Celebrating Don Ihde

Jacek Surzyn University of Silesia Kant s Political Philosophy

THE RELATIONS BETWEEN ETHICS AND ECONOMICS: A COMPARATIVE ANALYSIS BETWEEN AYRES AND WEBER S PERSPECTIVES. By Nuria Toledano and Crispen Karanda

SUMMARY BOETHIUS AND THE PROBLEM OF UNIVERSALS

Immanuel Kant Critique of Pure Reason

In his essay "Of the Standard of Taste," Hume describes an apparent conflict between two

CHAPTER TWO. A brief explanation of the Berger and Luckmann s theory that will be used in this thesis.

KINDS (NATURAL KINDS VS. HUMAN KINDS)

RESPONSE AND REJOINDER

ANALYSIS OF THE PREVAILING VIEWS REGARDING THE NATURE OF THEORY- CHANGE IN THE FIELD OF SCIENCE

Action, Criticism & Theory for Music Education

Practical Intuition and Rhetorical Example. Paul Schollmeier

Big Questions in Philosophy. What Is Relativism? Paul O Grady 22 nd Jan 2019

Literary Theory and Criticism

Ideological and Political Education Under the Perspective of Receptive Aesthetics Jie Zhang, Weifang Zhong

PHD THESIS SUMMARY: Phenomenology and economics PETR ŠPECIÁN

Emerging Questions: Fernando F. Segovia and the Challenges of Cultural Interpretation

Towards a Methodology of Artistic Research. Nov 22nd

introduction: why surface architecture?

What is woman s voice?: Focusing on singularity and conceptual rigor

Incommensurability and Partial Reference

Merleau-Ponty s Transcendental Project

On the Analogy between Cognitive Representation and Truth

Zhu Xi's Reading of the Analects: Canon, Commentary, and the Classical Tradition (review)

1/6. The Anticipations of Perception

High School Photography 1 Curriculum Essentials Document

TERMS & CONCEPTS. The Critical Analytic Vocabulary of the English Language A GLOSSARY OF CRITICAL THINKING

The Mind's Movement: An Essay on Expression

Plan. 0 Introduction and why philosophy? 0 An old paradigm of personhood in dementia 0 A new paradigm 0 Consequences

A Hybrid Theory of Metaphor

Action Theory for Creativity and Process

The Debate on Research in the Arts

SocioBrains THE INTEGRATED APPROACH TO THE STUDY OF ART

Necessity in Kant; Subjective and Objective

Meaning, Being and Expression: A Phenomenological Justification for Interdisciplinary Scholarship

Transcription:

Action, Criticism & Theory for Music Education The refereed journal of the Volume 9, No. 1 January 2010 Wayne Bowman Editor Electronic Article Shusterman, Merleau-Ponty, and Dewey: The Role of Pragmatism in the Conversation of Embodiment J. Scott Jordan J. Scott Jordan 2010 All rights reserved. ISSN 1545-4517 The content of this article is the sole responsibility of the author. The ACT Journal and the Mayday Group are not liable for any legal actions that may arise involving the article's content, including, but not limited to, copyright infringement. For further information, please point your Web Browser to http://act.maydaygroup.org

Action, Criticism, and Theory for Music Education Electronic Article 68 Shusterman, Merleau-Ponty, and Dewey: The Role of Pragmatism in the Conversation of Embodiment J. Scott Jordan Director, The Institute for Prospective Cognition Department of Psychology, Illinois State University Richard Shusterman advises us that the 20 th century scholarly community has not just ignored the value that can come to one s life as a function of paying close attention to the body and its immediate sensual qualities, it has trained us to eschew its character-enhancing sensual natures in favor of more lofty, intellectual pursuits. Given that the Western scholarly tradition has conceptualized individual and cultural development in terms of rationalism, it comes as no surprise to find evidence of such an approach to the body in 20 th century scholarship. But while Shusterman believes such pursuits have led us astray, one can also ask if the issues at stake for Shusterman are the same as those of the scholars he critiques. Specifically, Shusterman s pragmatic approach to body sensuality is clearly intertwined with the practices of developing body awareness often referred to in his work. From this perspective he projects a position on embodiment that asserts a practical philosophy committed to enhancing one s quality of life though enhanced soma awareness. From this practical vantage point Shusterman s arguments work: if this was the objective, he has achieved it with honors. There is the possibility however, that one might confuse this practical success for philosophical success, in general. For while one cannot deny that the scholars critiqued by Shusterman did in fact make practical claims about the nature of human living and the most effective means to address it, it is not clear that, in the end, their scholarly efforts were intended to be solely or primarily practical. Shusterman asserts that Merleau-Ponty, for example, rightly claimed that a philosophy of experience should begin with the primordial intentionality of the pre-reflective body: Merleau-Ponty s notion of bodily intentionality defies philosophical tradition by granting the body a kind of subjectivity instead of treating it as mere object or mechanism (60). Shusterman also points out that in his zeal to establish the ontological primacy of lived experience via the body, Merleau-Ponty implicitly eschewed the utilization of higher-level

Action, Criticism, and Theory for Music Education Electronic Article 69 representations of the body. Shusterman challenges this division in Merleau-Ponty s position by making a case for the practical utility of higher-level somatic awareness, In advocating the unreflective lived body and its motor schema in opposition to the conceptual representations of scientific explanation, Merleau-Ponty creates a polarization of lived experience versus abstract representations that neglects the deployment of a fruitful third option what could be called lived somaesthetic reflection, that, concrete but representational and reflective body consciousness (63). While from a pragmatic perspective, Shusterman s arguments work, it is not clear Merleau-Ponty would have actually disagreed. One could argue that Merleau-Ponty s agenda was ontological, not practical. From this perspective, there is no real philosophical point of dissent between Merleau-Ponty and Shusterman. The former is in search of a fundamental, ontological explanation of experience, and the latter, a practical, informed view of the body that allows one to work toward better somatic awareness. The fact that both describe their positions as philosophical does not, in and of itself, necessarily reveal a conflict. One could argue that Merleau-Ponty proposes a philosophy of experience, and Shusterman, a philosophy of somatic practice. One way to clarify the difference between the two is to examine the criteria for truth in both philosophies. In Merleau-Ponty s search for a bodily-based explanation of experience, the truthfulness of a given argument derives from its universality its ability to apply in all cases in non-contradictory fashion. The truthfulness of Shusterman s somatic philosophy derives not from its universality but from its ability to help individuals enhance and refine their own somatic sense. Merleau-Ponty s commitment to a fixed, universal phenomenological ontology based on primordial perception thus provides further reason for dismissing the value of explicit somatic consciousness. Being more concerned with individual differences and contingencies, with future-looking change and reconstruction, with pluralities of practice that can be used by individuals and groups for improving on primary experience, pragmatism is more receptive to reflective somatic consciousness and its disciplinary uses for philosophy (66). This difference in truth criteria in ontological versus practical philosophy constitutes the bedrock of the distinction between scientific and practical truth made by Michael Oakeshott (1962) in his classic essay, The Role of Poetry in the Conversation of Mankind. In this essay, Oakeshott makes the case that different modes of experience (e.g., scientific, daily practice, history, and poetry) entail different truth criteria. In the scientific mode, truth is determined in terms of convergence toward universality, the highest form of which is

Action, Criticism, and Theory for Music Education Electronic Article 70 mathematics. In daily practice, truth is not based on universality and convergence but rather on the degree to which the practices by which members of a group organize and manage their desires is applied to the group members in non-contradictory ways. As a result, statements regarding whether or not a given practice or behavior is correct are not based on the practice s degree of variation from a universal, context-independent system of moral absolutes. Rather, the rightness and or goodness of behavior derives from its degree of variation from systems of behavioral expectations that emerge within groups as they work to sustain various forms of social organization. Oakeshott distinguished the truth criteria at work in the modes of science and practice in order to save a space, as it were, for the modes of practice, history, and poetry in the conversation of civilized culture. That is, for him, culture was a conversation among voices (i.e., modes), in which facts appear only to be resolved once more into the possibilities from which they were made; certainties are shown to be combustible, not by being brought in contact with other certainties or with doubts, but by being kindled by the presence of ideas of another order; approximations are revealed between notions normally remote from one another. Thoughts of different species take wing and play round one another, responding to each other s movements and provoking one another to fresh exertions (198). Saving such a space was important to Oakeshott because he believed the philosophical naturalism at the core of the scientific mode was dominating the cultural conversation regarding truth. As a result, the truth criteria of daily practice (i.e., politics) came to be dominated by the truth criteria of science, and the truth status of political debate came to be based on assertions regarding the right and correct way to run a society, as if there existed a universal, culture-independent system of axioms against which one could measure a political system s deviation from correctness. By distinguishing different forms of truth criteria, Oakeshott created a conceptual framework that allowed each mode to be its own arbiter. In short, while science cannot tell us the right way to live, politics cannot tell us the ontological truth about reality. Oakeshott s framework proves relevant to the present task because it is consistent with the assertion that ontology and practice are not of the same kind, and utilizing the truth criteria for one mode as the truth criteria for the other constitutes a category mistake. Many of Shusterman s critiques of Merleau-Ponty are based on the assertion that his ontological approach to the body implicitly prevents readers from examining the practical value of paying

Action, Criticism, and Theory for Music Education Electronic Article 71 attention to body consciousness. While this may be true, it does not lead to the conclusion that what Merleau-Ponty had to say about the body was wrong. He was speaking ontologically, not practically. I am not claiming that Shusterman has committed a category mistake. Rather, I wish to draw attention to the possibility that Merleau-Ponty would not deny the practical value of enhanced soma awareness. Thus, what really seems to be at stake for Shusterman is not the ontological status of the body but rather the type of philosophy we should apply to it. As a result, Shusterman s critique of Merleau-Ponty comes across as a debate about ontology versus pragmatism. Perhaps this explains Shusterman s affinity for Dewey s pragmatism. Having begun his philosophical career as an idealist, Dewey later turned away from metaphysics and attempted to move philosophy toward a more scientifically-informed, practically-oriented philosophical agenda. This coupling of naturalism and practicality allowed him to retain his idealist belief in the existence of purpose and value in experience while simultaneously asserting the scientific method as a means of perpetually enhancing such value. Gardner (2007) however, questions Dewey s belief in the ability of naturalism to provide sound footing for value: Dewey s claim is that it is in the very nature of experience to form ever higher unities, which, simply in virtue of being unities, possess value, in the strongest sense. Yet the ground of this tendency to unity and value is, on Dewey s account, baldly Darwinian biological functions take the place of the idealists a priori metaphysics. Dewey talks as if it is in no surprise to discover in nature the very same kind of purposiveness that we claim for human activity. We think, however, that he ought to be surprised at this fact, if it is one. This is why the generation of American naturalists to which Dewey belongs, and for whom Dewey was the leading figure, looks to us now a mere phase in the development of Anglophone naturalism, in which the naturalistic impulse had announced but not yet clarified itself (p. 29). Gardner further argues that since Dewey s time, naturalism has moved to a point from which it now argues there is nothing in the world of natural facts from which to build value (i.e., goodness): By the time we get to Freud let alone Quine, naturalism is conceived as resting exclusively on theoretical reason and as immune to non-theoretical attack it is assumed that nothing could be shown regarding the axiological implications of naturalism that would give us reason to reconsider our commitment to it: we have ceased to think that naturalism is essential for the realization of our interest in value, and do not believe that it would be an option for us to reject naturalism even if it were to prove thoroughly inimical to our value-interests (24).

Action, Criticism, and Theory for Music Education Electronic Article 72 This relates to Shusterman s critique of Merleau-Ponty, for since the critique seems to reduce to the relative merits of ontology and practice, one might claim Shusterman is recapitulating in the field of embodiment philosophy Dewey s efforts to move philosophy, in general, away from metaphysics. That is, Shusterman seems to be saying that if we are going to talk about the body philosophically, it is better to do so pragmatically versus ontologically. One might deny this and assert that he is only making the smaller claim that there is room enough in embodiment philosophy for those of both ontological and pragmatic bents. If this were the case however, there would be no real tension between Merleau-Ponty and Shusterman. Tension is only introduced if Shusterman is taken as advancing the stronger claim that the pragmatic position is the better position that it is more worthwhile for embodiment philosophers to focus on practice more than ontology. While such a position is rather Dewey-esque in its flair, it is not clear that the time is right for proposing the higher value of pragmatism. For while Dewey implicitly believed in naturalism s ability to make us better, due to his early idealism, current naturalism, as described above, entails no such commitment to value. Thus, modern pragmatism has a decision to make about value. One option is to perpetuate Dewey s enthusiasm for naturalism (i.e., the scientific method) as a means of increasing the value in reality. To ally itself with naturalism however, such a position would have to find a way to ground its use of value in its naturalism a project most modern naturalists have even abandoned. Without such grounding, modern pragmatism might avoid ontology altogether and make its case for value by invoking Oakeshott s distinction between ontological and practical truth criteria. The value judgment that the pragmatic approach is the better approach (versus ontology) could then be based on the assertion that people want to live more satisfactory lives, and the pragmatic approach is the more useful way to get there. Having secured its status as better via the truth criteria of practice however (i.e., the realm of human desire), the pragmatic approach to the body will not have defeated ontology. Rather, as Oakeshott hoped, it will have found its voice in the current conversation on embodiment.

Action, Criticism, and Theory for Music Education Electronic Article 73 References Gardner, S. (2007). The Limits of Naturalism and the Metaphysics of German Idealism. German Idealism: Contemporary Perspectives, ed. by E. Hammer. Abingdon, UK: Routledge, 19 49. Oakeshott, M. (1962). The Voice of Poetry in the Conversation of Mankind. Rationalism in Politics and Other Essays. London: Methuen, 197 247. About the Author J. Scott Jordan studied cognitive psychology and the neurophysiological basis of perception at Northern Illinois University in Dekalb, Illinois. He received his PhD in psychology in 1991. His research focus is directed toward volition and its relationship to consciousness. His dissertation addressed the relationship between voluntary eye-movements and spatial perception. In 1992 he was awarded an Alexander von Humboldt Post-doctoral Fellowship and spent a year in Prof. Dr. Hans Kornhuber s neurophysiology lab at the University of Ulm studying the relationship between event-related brain potentials and memory and attention. In 1998-1999 he spent a year at the Max Planck Institute for Psychological Research studying the relationship between action planning and spatial perception, and in 2006, he spent a semester as a Scholar-in-Residence at the Center for Interdisciplinary Research at the University of Bielefeld working in a research group entitled, Embodied Communication in Humans and Machines. He is currently a professor in the Department of Psychology at Illinois State University in Normal, Illinois where he recently founded the Institute for Prospective Cognition (http://my.ilstu.edu/~jsjorda/institute_for_prospective_cognition.html).