On Meaning. language to establish several definitions. We then examine the theories of meaning

Similar documents
The Language Revolution Russell Marcus Fall Class #7 Final Thoughts on Frege on Sense and Reference

Mind Association. Oxford University Press and Mind Association are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Mind.

Quine s Two Dogmas of Empiricism. By Spencer Livingstone

In Defense of the Contingently Nonconcrete

Vagueness & Pragmatics

PLEASE SCROLL DOWN FOR ARTICLE

Types of perceptual content

Replies to the Critics

The Language Revolution Russell Marcus Fall 2015

The Philosophy of Language. Frege s Sense/Reference Distinction

Frege: Two Kinds of Meaning

The Prenective View of propositional content

What is Character? David Braun. University of Rochester. In "Demonstratives", David Kaplan argues that indexicals and other expressions have a

Singular Propositions, Abstract Constituents, and Propositional Attitudes

Scientific Philosophy

The Embedding Problem for Non-Cognitivism; Introduction to Cognitivism; Motivational Externalism

CONTINGENCY AND TIME. Gal YEHEZKEL

Background to Gottlob Frege

Bas C. van Fraassen, Scientific Representation: Paradoxes of Perspective, Oxford University Press, 2008.

LOGICO-SEMANTIC ASPECTS OF TRUTHFULNESS

Society for the Study of Symbolic Interaction SSSI/ASA 2002 Conference, Chicago

The identity theory of truth and the realm of reference: where Dodd goes wrong

winter but it rained often during the summer

Two-Dimensional Semantics the Basics

Partial and Paraconsistent Approaches to Future Contingents in Tense Logic

A Note on Analysis and Circular Definitions

Nissim Francez: Proof-theoretic Semantics College Publications, London, 2015, xx+415 pages

A difficulty in the foundation of Analytic Philosophy

For every sentences A and B, there is a sentence: A B,

QUESTIONS AND LOGICAL ANALYSIS OF NATURAL LANGUAGE: THE CASE OF TRANSPARENT INTENSIONAL LOGIC MICHAL PELIŠ

MONOTONE AMAZEMENT RICK NOUWEN

Sidestepping the holes of holism

COGNITION AND IDENTIFYING REFERENCE. Gary Rosenkrantz

Conclusion. One way of characterizing the project Kant undertakes in the Critique of Pure Reason is by

The Strengths and Weaknesses of Frege's Critique of Locke By Tony Walton

Social Mechanisms and Scientific Realism: Discussion of Mechanistic Explanation in Social Contexts Daniel Little, University of Michigan-Dearborn

The Reference Book, by John Hawthorne and David Manley. Oxford: Oxford University Press 2012, 280 pages. ISBN

Intensional Relative Clauses and the Semantics of Variable Objects

Reply to Stalnaker. Timothy Williamson. In Models and Reality, Robert Stalnaker responds to the tensions discerned in Modal Logic

Frege on Ideal Language, Multiple Analyses, and Identity

Self-reference. Sereny's presentation in "Godel, Tarski, Church, and the Liar,"' although the main idea is

By Tetsushi Hirano. PHENOMENOLOGY at the University College of Dublin on June 21 st 2013)

AN INSIGHT INTO CONTEMPORARY THEORY OF METAPHOR

PHL 317K 1 Fall 2017 Overview of Weeks 1 5

REFERENTS AND FIXING REFERENCE 1

1 The structure of this exercise

138 Great Problems in Philosophy and Physics - Solved? Chapter 11. Meaning. This chapter on the web informationphilosopher.com/knowledge/meaning

On The Search for a Perfect Language

The Semantics of Metaphor in the Game Theoretic Semantics. with at Least Two Coordination Equilibria

RETURNING TO OUR SENSES

Abstract Several accounts of the nature of fiction have been proposed that draw on speech act

Heideggerian Ontology: A Philosophic Base for Arts and Humanties Education

Perceptual Demonstrative Thought: A Property-Dependent Theory

Lecture 7. Scope and Anaphora. October 27, 2008 Hana Filip 1

Comparatives, Indices, and Scope

Natika Newton, Foundations of Understanding. (John Benjamins, 1996). 210 pages, $34.95.

Rhetorical Questions and Scales

Glossary alliteration allusion analogy anaphora anecdote annotation antecedent antimetabole antithesis aphorism appositive archaic diction argument

Articulating Medieval Logic, by Terence Parsons. Oxford: Oxford University Press,

CHAPTER 2 THEORETICAL FRAMEWORK

The Cognitive Nature of Metonymy and Its Implications for English Vocabulary Teaching

The ambiguity of definite descriptions

Resemblance Nominalism: A Solution to the Problem of Universals. GONZALO RODRIGUEZ-PEREYRA. Oxford: Clarendon Press, Pp. xii, 238.

Peircean concept of sign. How many concepts of normative sign are needed. How to clarify the meaning of the Peircean concept of sign?

XI*-INTENSIONAL AND INTENTIONAL OBJECTS By Roger Scruton

Philosophy 405: Knowledge, Truth and Mathematics Spring Russell Marcus Hamilton College

1. Introduction. Truth is a pretense. This bald statement might inspire incredulous stares, but my aim here is to deflect

1 Objects and Logic. 1. Abstract objects

Reviewed by Max Kölbel, ICREA at Universitat de Barcelona

Some Observations on François Recanati s Mental Files

MORAL CONTEXTUALISM AND MORAL RELATIVISM

PRIOR ON THE LOGIC AND THE METAPHYSICS OF TIME

Manuel Bremer University Lecturer, Philosophy Department, University of Düsseldorf, Germany

Objective Interpretation and the Metaphysics of Meaning

Incommensurability and Partial Reference

THE PROPOSITIONAL CHALLENGE TO AESTHETICS

A Notion of Logical Concept based on Plural Reference

Georgia Performance Standards for Second Grade

Resemblance Nominalism: A Solution to the Problem of Universals

The Application of Stylistics in British and American Literature Teaching. XU Li-mei, QU Lin-lin. Changchun University, Changchun, China

Non-Reducibility with Knowledge wh: Experimental Investigations

Logic and Philosophy of Science (LPS)

Pragmatics - The Contribution of Context to Meaning

Formalizing Irony with Doxastic Logic

Peirce's Remarkable Rules of Inference

RELATIVISM ABOUT TRUTH AND PERSPECTIVE-NEUTRAL PROPOSITIONS

Encyclopedia of Cognitive Science

GOTTLOB FREGE: SOME FORMS OF INFLUENCE

Imperatives are existential modals; Deriving the must-reading as an Implicature. Despina Oikonomou (MIT)

Tropes and the Semantics of Adjectives

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

SAINSBURY ON THINKING ABOUT AN OBJECT

Review of Epistemic Modality

TERMS & CONCEPTS. The Critical Analytic Vocabulary of the English Language A GLOSSARY OF CRITICAL THINKING

Meaning 1. Semantics is concerned with the literal meaning of sentences of a language.

Language Paper 1 Knowledge Organiser

THE USE OF METAPHOR IN INVICTUS FILM

Representation and Discourse Analysis

A New Approach to the Paradox of Fiction Pete Faulconbridge

Perception and Mind-Dependence Lecture 3

Transcription:

Aaron Tuor Philosophy of Language March 17, 2014 On Meaning The general aim of this paper is to evaluate theories of linguistic meaning in terms of their success in accounting for definitions of meaning derived from common usage. To this end we first examine the use of the terms meaning and nonsense in ordinary language to establish several definitions. We then examine the theories of meaning provided by Frege, and Russell. We shall argue that both Russell s and Frege s theories have limitations in capturing the full range of application of meaning. Finally we offer suggestions to extend a theory of meaning to encompass a greater range of expressions to which we attribute meaning. For the purposes of this paper, we define a linguistic phrase (LP) as an uttered word, adjective phrase, noun phrase, verb phrase, sentence, or clause. Further, we assume the following intuitive principle of substitution: *) If two LPs α and β have the same meaning, then a more complex LP containing either α or β as a constituent will mean the same thing when one constituent LP is substituted in place of the other. have: Consulting OED for examples of usage, and the lexicographer s definitions we Meaning: a. The significance, purpose, underlying truth, etc, of something. The symbol is so graceful that one is quite eager to know its meaning. b. The significance, import; implication. It makes you begin to question the meaning of everything you believe. Nonsense: d. That which is not sense; absurd or meaningless words or ideas. I am writing nonsense, but it is because no sense within my mind will answer the purpose.

c. Foolish or extravagant conduct; silliness, misbehavior. Haven t you done with your nonsense yet. The lexicographers have blended together several ideas in some definitions above which we will tease apart in the construction of our own definitions. While it is not the English idiom to be able to substitute not nonsense for every occurrence of meaning, from the examples above it seems we can do pretty well at expressing the range of concepts captured by nonsense by negating the definitions of meaning we ve developed below. Definitions are cast in adjectival form, so as not to presuppose any ontological commitments. To avoid stilted unnatural language, I will however not be consistent in the adjectival usage throughout the paper. M1) A meaningful LP is one which has significance. M2) A meaningful LP is one which has underlying truth (a truth value). M3) A meaningful LP is one which has a purpose. N1) A nonsense LP is on which is not significant. N2) A nonsense LP is one which has no underlying truth (no truth value). N3) A nonsense LP is one which has no purpose. The easiest way to begin the discussion of meaning is to discuss theories of proper names. As names are not things which can be true or false we are left to consider M1 and M3. What is the purpose of a name? What is its significance? It seems intuitive to say that the purpose of a name is to refer to something; that names are significant in virtue of their referring to something. So upon this analysis, M1 and M3 may be collapsed into a single definition. There are however problems with this view. For one thing there are names which don t seem to refer to any actual object, like Pegasus, or Captain Kirk. If we accept this analysis then Pegasus and Captain Kirk are nonsense names as they have no purpose and no significance. One can argue that they have both. Another objection is that if two names refer to the same object and their significance is due solely

to what they refer then by (*), sentences (1) and (2) below should have the same significance. (1) The Morning Star is The Evening Star. (2) The Morning Star is the Morning Star. But (1) seems to say that the thing called The Morning Star is the same as the thing called The Evening Star which is an informative statement, whereas (2) expresses the empty tautology that the thing called The Morning Star is the same as the thing called The Morning Star. Frege offers a solution to this quandary in his analysis of meaning. For Frege the meaning of a LP consists of two parts: a referent and a sense. A referent is, as we have discussed above in the case of proper names, something which a LP refers to, whereas a sense is the way in which a referent is determined by a LP. So, for Frege some names, those to which there corresponds an actual thing present in the world, have referents, and other names, those to which there does not correspond an actual thing present in the world, do not. Names of both types however have senses which may be thought of as some sort of cognitive description for which there might be some fitting object in the world. For instance, of the four names so far mentioned their senses may be listed: The Morning Star: The brightest star in the morning sky. The Evening Star: The brightest star in the evening sky. Pegasus: The winged divine stallion foaled by the Gorgon Medusa. James Tiberius Kirk: The person born on March 22, 2233, in Riverside, Iowa, by his parents, George and Winona Kirk. The solution to the two points elaborated for our quandary is that fictional names have sense but no reference, and pairs of names like The Morning Star and The Evening Star have different senses but the same referents.

While the above solution seems plausible there is something strange about attributing meaning to isolated names. To simply say Barack Obama to another person leaves open the question of whether the utterance satisfies (M1), or (M3). In other words, it is arguable that if the utterance Barack Obama is not embedded in a sentence or elliptical construction (as in a response to a question or a prompt) then the utterance has no significance, no truth value, and no purpose. So, there is motivation to explore the role that constituent elements of sentences such as names play in the composition of meaning in larger phrases and sentences. Frege s conceptions of sense and reference apply not only to constituent elements of sentences like names but to entire sentences as well. In Frege s theory, the sense of a declarative sentence is a proposition, and the reference of a declarative sentence is a truth value. So, roughly speaking, a sentence has M1 meaning due to its sense, and M2 meaning due to its truth value. For Frege the meaning of a declarative sentence is derived from its constituent elements. So the senses of constituent elements in a sentence combine to give the sense of its associated proposition. If some constituent element of a sentence fails to refer, then the sentence as a whole fails to have a referent, i.e., has no truth value. Frege is equally happy to call both (3) and (4) below N2 nonsensical: 3) The present king of France is bald. 4) Pegasus is the winged divine stallion foaled by Medusa. The analysis that the failure of reference of constituent terms entails the failure of reference of an entire sentence has a possible objection. Considering this analysis correct, if (3) is embedded in a belief ascription sentence as in (5) below, then as (3) has no reference (no truth value), it stands to reason from Frege s composition principle that (5) has no truth value. But (5) is a sentence that is determinately true or false.

(5) Barack Obama believes that the king of France is bald. Frege has a good response to such an objection. Frege regards (6) below as a true statement, because even though The king of France fails to refer, quotation marks around a phrase shift its referent to its sense, which seems reasonable when we consider the difference in meaning of (6) and (7). (6) The present king of France fails to refer. (7) The present king of France fails to refer. In much the same way, sentences embedded in subordinate clauses have their referents shifted to the sense of the sentence. So, (5) describes Barack Obama believing a proposition, not a truth value. Russell argued against Frege s theory from the observation that rather than being nonsense (3) is clearly false. One might respond that if Russell is simply appealing to intuition this is an unconvincing attack as one can equally well respond to (3) by saying either, That s not true, or That s nonsense. This objection is not itself convincing as it is unclear if the intuitively acceptable That s nonsense, response is related to the negation of M2 or to some other of our definitions of meaningful. While Russell s example may seem trivial, there are sentences that are more troubling for Frege s theory. In theoretical sciences, statements like (8) below are often made about things which turn out not to exist. (8) If the firmament exists and the earth is the center of the universe then the stars in the outer sphere are equidistant from the center of the earth. Frege s theory judges (8) as nonsense, but (8) is determinately true. In any case we can avoid appealing to intuition about nonsense by instead appealing to the semantic principle

of bivalence which states that every declarative sentence expressing a true proposition is either true or false. Russell elaborated a theory upholding the principle of bivalence in cases where LPs, according to Frege s theory, fail to have truth values. In general the theory holds that expressions like, a man, the king of France, and every person, which he calls denoting phrases, have no meaning in themselves, but every proposition which contains them has a meaning. Rather than performing some function of reference, denoting phrases contribute to the description of a variable which is a constituent of a proposition. For instance below, if x is a variable, C(x) is a proposition in (i), and C(x) = x walks, in (ii) we have: (i) C(a king) means C(x) and x rules is not always false. (ii) A king walks. means x walks and x rules is not always false. (i) C(all kings) means If x rules then C(x) is always true. (ii) All kings walk means If x rules then x walks is always true. (i) C(no kings) means C(x) and x rules is always false. (ii) No kings walk means x walks and x rules is always false. Propositions containing denoting phrases which use the definite article the are more complex as they involve an existence and a uniqueness claim. So, according to Russell, (3) means: (7) At present, it is not always false of x that x rules France and x is bald and if y rules France then y = x is always true. Or in the more familiar language of predicate logic: (8) At present, (There exists an x such that) (x rules France and x is bald and (for every y) (if y rules France then y = x)). So, denoting phrases are not analyzable outside the context of a sentence. (3) is false under this analysis as there is no entity which satisfies the existence claim implied

by the definite description. As well we can happily employ sentences like (8) in the pursuit of developing theoretical sciences without being concerned that we are making use of nonsense. Under this theory the sentence is the basic bearer of meaning and wellformed sentences cannot be N2 nonsense. In fact the only way a sentence can be nonsense is if it is not well-formed. Russell admits that phrases below the sentence level have no meaning so we can assume that in his theory, considering our analysis of nonsense as the negation of one or another definition of meaning, that the utterance of such phrases in isolation is nonsense. This fits with our earlier intuition. Russell s theory ensures the meaningfulness of scientific discourse, but it has some troubling things to say about fictional discourse. The meaning it attributes to fictional sentences like (4) is that they are false. As conscientious adults this is of course something we wish to be understood by the children we regale with such tales. However, we would like a theory of meaning to be able to say something about fictional discourse beyond its inherent falsity. By Frege s theory, fictional discourse is N2 nonsense. While we have seen ample reason to disregard this conclusion, his motivation for this pronouncement stems from a penetrating insight. When people engage in fictional discourse truth values aren t something they are generally concerned with. In Fregean terms, people are concerned with the sense of the LPs in fictional discourse rather than the referents. Frege envisions fictional discourse as conjuring entertaining thoughts which need have no bearing on reality. So, fictional discourse has M1 meaning but fails to have M2 meaning. Frege s conclusion that fictional discourse is nonsense, and Russell s conclusion that fictional discourse is false, while different, stem from a shared presupposition: M2

meaning is the primary concern of a theory of meaning. Frege calls fiction nonsense, giving no weight to fact that the purpose of fiction is different than the purpose of scientific discourse. Russell calls fiction false by the same error. However, there is reason to think that M3 meaning is a more general notion for a theory of linguistic meaning to be concerned with. The difference in the purpose of fictional discourse explains how it can be significant while having little or no concern for truth values. Also, differences in purpose can account for the attribution of meaning to non-declarative utterances such as exclamatory and imperative utterances. As Austin notes, the meaning of even some simple declarative sentences does not depend on their truth values. Take for instance LPs such as (9) I thee wed, or (10) I bet you twenty dollars, which we ll label as unconventionally declarative, or UD. Reasonable responses to ordinary declarative utterances in most circumstances include saying That s true, and That s false. However, it seems absurd in any circumstances to respond to (9) or (10) as either true or false, although there are circumstances in which we might reasonably respond, That s nonsense. Now when we say That s nonsense in response to this type of phrase, we don t mean that the statement has no truth value. What we mean is there is no significance in uttering such a comment given the purpose it is customarily intended for. Given these concerns one might propose something along the lines of the theory sketched below. I) To say a LP is to perform an action. II) There are different types of LPs which have different conventionally determined purposes. III) A type χ LP is meaningful if and only if fits the conventionally determined purpose of making such an LP.

To elaborate, first we evaluate the case of declarative sentences uttered with the purpose of expressing facts. Here we can say that sentences with no truth values do not fit the purpose of expressing facts, and are hence meaningless if you intend to express a fact. This theory offers the satisfying and intuitive conclusion that political speeches are often filled with nonsense as they contain many sentences which are too vague or ambiguous to have a determinate truth value. The work of Frege and Russell still serves for a finer analysis of the meanings of ordinary declarative sentences. However, in the case of fictional and other types of sentences, where the attribution of truth values is an ancillary concern, there is a great deal of work to be done in determining what finer metric of meaning to use in place of M2. The work of cultural anthropologists, speech act theorists, and philosophers of fiction would be invaluable in the development of such a theory. A concern for this theory is that fictional sentences and UD statements ostensibly have different conventionally determined purposes than declarative sentences which are uttered to report facts, yet they show no distinguishing syntactic features. In order for this theory to work one must explain how to determine the type of a LP beyond its syntactic features. Developing a theory of meaning based on the purpose of an utterance is a move towards generalizing theories of meaning to wider ranges of discourse. However, the presented list of definitions for meaning derived from common usage is not exhaustive. The definitions below seem just as plausible as the others listed. (M*) A meaningful LP is understandable. (N*) A nonsense LP is not understandable. These definitions raise some interesting questions about meaning. For instance there are lots of ways we can fail to understand a LP, ranging from ignorance of vocabulary,

improper syntax, ambiguity, vagueness, complicated phrasing, the representation of a complex concept with a single symbol, to paradox. Is it possible to refine this list to a small number of primitive phenomena which bear on the understanding of language? Also, (M*) is the relevant definition for many uses of meaning with relative terms such as more and less. In how many dimensions is it possible to be more or less meaningful? A fully developed theory of meaning should provide answers these questions as well. References Austin, J.L. Performative Utterances (1961). The Philosophy of Language. 5 th Ed. A.P. Martinich. New York: Oxford University Press. 2008. 136-145. Print. Frege, Gottlob. On Sense and Nominatum (1892). The Philosophy of Language. 5 th Ed. A.P. Martinich. New York: Oxford University Press. 2008. 217-229. Print. Quine, W.V. Two dogmas of empiricism (1951). The Philosophy of Language. 5 th Ed. A.P. Martinich. New York: Oxford University Press. 2008. 63-76. Print. Russell, Bertrand. On Denoting (1905). The Philosophy of Language. 5 th Ed. A.P. Martinich. New York: Oxford University Press. 2008. 230-238. Print. Russell, Bertrand. Descriptions (1919). The Philosophy of Language. 5 th Ed. A.P. Martinich. New York: Oxford University Press. 2008. 239-235. Print. Speaks, Jeff, Theories of Meaning. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2011 Edition). Edward N. Zalta (ed.). URL = http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2011/entries/meaning/. Second Edition, 1989 meaning, n.2 The Oxford English Dictionary. 2nd ed. 1989. OED Online. Oxford University Press. 30 April 2007. URL = http://dictionary.oed.com/. nonsense, n. and adj. The Oxford English Dictionary. 2nd ed. 1989. OED Online. Oxford University Press. 30 April 2007. URL = http://dictionary.oed.com/.