Priscila Lena Farias* and João Queiroz On Peirce s diagrammatic models for ten classes of signs

Similar documents
Daniella Aguiar and Joao Queiroz Semiosis and intersemiotic translation

Author Query Form. Iconic semiosis and representational efficiency in the London Underground Diagram

44 Iconicity in Peircean situated cognitive Semiotics

Semiotic modelling of biological processes: semiotic systems João Queiroz a,b,c & Charbel El-Hani a,b

Intersemiotic translation: The Peircean basis

Symposium on Semiotics and Mathematics with the Special Theme 'Peirce, the Mathematician', June 11 13

Chapter 7 C. S. Peirce and Intersemiotic Translation

Referências. ANDERSON, Michael & ARMEN, Cris Diagrammatic reasoning and color. In: The. The Diagrammatic Reasoning Site [originalmente

Peircean concept of sign. How many concepts of normative sign are needed. How to clarify the meaning of the Peircean concept of sign?

A new aspect of sign and its implications for the Theory of Communication

Anne Freadman, The Machinery of Talk: Charles Peirce and the Sign Hypothesis (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 2004), pp. xxxviii, 310.

PEIRCE ON PRACTICAL REASONING

Kalevi Kull 1. [...] and since knowledge is habit [...]. (1906, CP 4.531) 4

Diagrams, Iconicity, and Abductive Discovery

Peirce s Theory of Signs 1

SYNTHESE LIBRARY STUDIES IN EPISTEMOLOGY, LOGrC, METHODOLOGY, AND PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE. Managing Editor: Editors:

Terminology. - Semantics: Relation between signs and the things to which they refer; their denotata, or meaning

Keywords: semiotic; pragmatism; space; embodiment; habit, social practice.

C. S. Peirce s formal science of signs provides an analytic framework

The semiotics of models

Peirce and Semiotic an Introduction

EUROPEAN JOURNAL OF PRAGMATISM AND AMERICAN PHILOSOPHY. The History of Reception of Charles S. Peirce in Greece 1

SEMIOTICS AND INDEXING: AN ANALYSIS OF THE SUBJECT INDEXING PROCESS JENS-ERIK MAI. u.washington.edu

Sign Processes and the Sheets of Semeiosis (S S )

Community of Inquiry and Inquiry- based learning

Biosemiotics: To Know, What Life Knows. Kalevi Kull 1. Whether biology has studied what organisms know?

A Semiotic Rosetta Stone: Developing a Designercentric Meta-language of Pragmatic Semiotics

Semiosis as an Emergent Process

C. S. Peirce s Evolutionary Sign: an Analysis of Depth and Complexity within Peircean Sign Types and Peircean Evolution Theory.

Semiotics and the Philosophy of Language UMBERTO ECO INDIANA. University Press. Bloomington & Indianapolis

5 ETCS One Week PhD- course in

Transduction and Meaning Making Issues Within Multimodal Messages

Monday August 25. Göran Sonesson: Phenomenological semiotics.

Sets, Symbols and Pictures: A Reflection on Euler Diagrams in Leonhard Euler s Tercentenary (2007)

Semiotics of Terminology: A Semiotic Knowledge Profile

MISSING FUNDAMENTAL STRATUM OF THE CURRENT FORMS OF THE REPRESENTATION OF CONCEPTS IN CONSTRUCTION

Ontology as Meta-Theory: A Perspective

The Tools at Hand: Making Theory More Relevant to Graphic Design

Semiotic-Cognitive Theory of Learning

Pre-conference workshop with Lars Elleström (Linneaus University) Daniella Aguiar & João Queiroz (orgs.)

Peirce s Final Account of Signs and The Philosophy of Language ALBERT ATKIN

Introduction: Umberto Eco s interpretative semiotics: Interpretation, encyclopedia, translation

Inquiry and the Fourth Grade of Clearness

Embodied Experience and the Semiosis of Abductive Reasoning. Donna E. West State University of New York at Cortland

Instructions to the Authors

Cultural heritage and multidimensional representations of buildings Schrøder, Anne Lise

Undercutting the Realism-Irrealism Debate: John Dewey and the Neo-Pragmatists

Dicisigns. Frederik Stjernfelt. Synthese An International Journal for Epistemology, Methodology and Philosophy of Science

Space, Time, and Interpretation

CHAPTER SIX. Habitation, structure, meaning

Moving Pictures of Thought II: Graphs, Games, and Pragmaticism s Proofs

Current Issues in Pictorial Semiotics

SYNTHESE LIBRARY VOLUME 329 STUDIES IN EPISTEMOLOGY, LOGIC, METHODOLOGY, AND PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE

Science as a Form of Life and Cross-disciplinarity: Mariano Artigas and Charles S. Peirce

GESTALT CONFIGURATIONS IN GEOMETRY LEARNING

Lecture (0) Introduction

Interactions between Semiotic Modes in Multimodal Texts. Martin Siefkes, University of Bremen

META-COGNITIVE UNITY IN INDIRECT PROOFS

Back to Basics: Appreciating Appreciative Inquiry as Not Normal Science

In Pursuit of Objectivity. Chiara Ambrosio Department of Science and Technology Studies University College London

Bent Sørensen and Torkild Leo Thellefsen

Pragmatism and Idealism

Operational and Optimal Iconicity in Peirce s Diagrammatology

Is Genetic Epistemology of Any Interest for Semiotics?

Narrative Dimensions of Philosophy

The Sign and Its Alterity

THE PROBLEM OF NOVELTY IN C.S. PEIRCE'S AND A.N. WHITEHEAD'S THOUGHT

STYLE GUIDELINES. Dear Afterimage Contributor,

Metaphor in Discourse

SYNTHESE LIBRARY STUDIES IN EPISTEMOLOGY, LOGIC, METHODOLOGY, AND PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE. JAAKKO HINTIKKA, Boston University

RAFAEL BOMBELLI S ALGEBRA (1572) AND A NEW MATHEMATICAL OBJECT : A SEMIOTIC ANALYSIS

The Phenomenological Road to Cognitive Semiotics

common available Go to the provided as Word Files Only Use off. Length Generally for a book comprised a. Include book

Aalborg Universitet. Signs of Meta-understanding Schrøder, Anne Lise. Published in: ScanGIS Publication date: 2005

PEIRCE, SEBEOK, AND THE SEMIOTIC REFORMATION ON CONTEMPORARY COMMUNICATIONS

PHI6500: seminar times to be arranged early in the course. Short Essay deadline: Thursday 29th November (Thursday week 10)

Postdisciplinary Studies in Discourse

Profile of requirements for Master Theses

Pragmaticism among the pragmatists: a brief history and future prospects 1

Habits and Interpretation: defending the pragmatist

A Critical Examination of the Philosophy of Charles S. Peirce: A Defence of the Claim that his Pragmatism is Founded on his Theory of Categories

AU-6407 B.Lib.Inf.Sc. (First Semester) Examination 2014 Knowledge Organization Paper : Second. Prepared by Dr. Bhaskar Mukherjee

Problems of Information Semiotics

Film sound: Applying Peircean semiotics to create theory grounded in practice

GUIDELINES FOR PREPARATION OF THESIS AND SYNOPSIS

Charles S. Peirce s Philosophy of Signs

Haecceities: Essentialism, Identity, and Abstraction

AUTHORS: TANIA LUCIA CORREA VALENTE UNIVERSIDADE TECNOLÓGICA FEDERAL DO PARANÁ

Journal of Nonlocality Round Table Series Colloquium #4

Methodeutic and the order of inquiry. Bergman, Mats

STYLE-BRANDING, AESTHETIC DESIGN DNA

Leo Murray Adapting Peircean semiotics to sound theory and practice

Thinking of or Thinking Through Diagrams? The Case of Conceptual Graphs.

English 10-Persuasive Research Paper

Postprint.

Neglected Aspects of Peirce s Writings: Contributions to Ethics and Humanism

The Collected Papers Of Albert Einstein Volume 13 English The Berlin Years Writings Correspondence January 1922 March 1923 German Edition

GUIDELINES FOR FULL PAPER SUBMISSION for the NAXOS th International Conference on Sustainable Solid Waste Management

Form, Program, and Metaphor in the Music of Berlioz

The Pennsylvania State University. The Graduate School. College of the Liberal Arts THE SLOW PERCOLATION OF FORMS: CHARLES PEIRCE S WRITINGS ON PLATO

Transcription:

Semiotica 2014; 202: 657 671 Priscila Lena Farias* and João Queiroz On Peirce s diagrammatic models for ten classes of signs Abstract: The classifications of signs are among the most important topics of Peirce s theory of signs. The 10 classes of signs were developed from 1903 and represent an important refinement of the fundamental division of signs into icons, indexes, and symbols. In this paper we present two diagrammatic models for 10 classes, proposed by Peirce, and an interpretation of the reasoning behind their development, based on the analysis of preparatory versions of these models. Keywords: classification of signs, 10 classes of signs, diagrams, C. S. Peirce, 1903 Syllabus, Lady Welby DOI 10.1515/sem-2014-0038 1 Introduction Sign-mediated processes show a remarkable variety. In an attempt to advance in the modeling of semiotic processes, Peirce proposed several classifications, with different degrees of refinement and several relationships to one another. In fact, the classifications of signs are among the most important topics of Peirce s Speculative Grammar. The 10 classes of signs were specially developed from 1903 and represent a major refinement of the best known division of signs into icons, indexes, and symbols. 1 In order to more accurately describe complex semiotic 1 For an introduction to Peirce s extended classifications of signs, see Savan (1988); Liszka (1996); Parker (1998); Freadman (2004); Houser (2010); Atkin (2010). On the classes and its compositions, see Weiss and Burks (1945); Lieb (1977); Sanders (1970); Muller (1994). On the theoretical aspects involved in this issue, see Savan (1977); Tursman (1987); Short (2007). On its genealogy, see Freadman (2001, 2004). On its structural organization, see Marty (1982); Jappy (1989); Balat (1990); Houser (1991); Merrell (1996); Serson (1997); Farias and Queiroz (2000, 2003, 2004); Hoffman (2001). On the modeling of biosemiotic phenomena, see Queiroz (2012a, 2012b). *Corresponding author: Priscila Farias: University of São Paulo. E-mail: prifarias@usp.br João Queiroz: Federal University of Juiz de Fora. E-mail: queirozj@pq.cnpq.br

658 Priscila Lena Farias and João Queiroz phenomena, Peirce developed several classifications of signs (10, 28, and 66 classes), based on different trichotomies (see EP 2: 289 299 and 478 491). The consequence is an enormous accuracy of the relations observed within semiosis. An examination of Peirce s manuscripts, from 1903 to 1908, reveals that he devoted considerable attention to research and development of visual models for the 10 classes of signs, a fact that should not be considered surprising, given his association of diagrammatic reasoning with abductive inference and creativity (see Paavola 2011, Stjernfelt 2007). In previous works, we argued that there is a common pattern in the arrangement of the diagrams designed by Peirce for 3-trichotomic classes (Farias and Queiroz 2003), and showed that this pattern could serve as a basis for a dynamic diagram for such classes. This has lead to the development of a computer program able to build equivalent diagrams for any n-trichotomic classification of signs (Farias and Queiroz 2004), which serves as a tool for the investigation of C. S. Peirce s theory of signs. An example of the use of such tool is the visualization of the different kinds of iconic classes that occur within the 66 classes of signs, depending on the ordering of the trichotomies, and their possible relation with the hypoicons described by Peirce (Farias and Queiroz 2006). Here we present, in more detail than in previous works, the two diagrams designed by Peirce for the 10 classes. One of them refers to the division described for the first time in his Syllabus, in 1903 (MS 540: 17, CP 2.264, EP 2: 296). The other diagram appears in drafts of a letter to Victoria Welby, written in December 1908 (L 463: 146, CP 8.376, EP 2: 491). In addition to the models published in the Collected Papers and The Essential Peirce, we present a series of sketches for these diagrams, found in several manuscripts, from which we might infer Peirce s underlying diagrammatic reasoning (in the sense discussed by Stjernfelt 2000) regarding the relations of affinity and hierarchical dependence between the classes of signs. 2 The Syllabus diagram In his 1903 Syllabus (EP 2: 296), Peirce introduces the 3-trichotomic 10 classes of signs. After describing the classes, he presents a diagram where they appear in 10 squares arranged in a triangular structure (Figure 1), and makes the following comment: The affinities of the ten classes are exhibited by arranging their designations in the triangular table here shown, which has heavy boundaries between adjacent squares that are appropriated to classes alike in only one respect. All other adjacent squares pertain to classes

Peirce s models for ten classes of signs 659 Fig. 1: Diagram found in Peirce s manuscript (MS 540: 17) for his 1903 Syllabus. alike in two respects. Squares not adjacent pertain to classes alike in one respect only, except that each of the three squares of the vertices of the triangle pertains to a class differing in all three respects from the classes to which the squares along the opposite side of the triangle are appropriated. The lightly printed designations are superfluous. (CP 2.264) This diagram, which we will from now on refer to as the Syllabus diagram, was reproduced (Figure 2) in the Collected Papers (CP 2.264) and in the second volume of The Essential Peirce (EP 2: 296). The Roman figures were added to the diagram by the editors of the Collected Papers for easy reference to the 10 classes, and were omitted by the editors of The Essential Peirce. In other pages of the manuscript MS 540 (MS 540: 27, 28 and 29, Figures 3, 4, and 5), and also in one of the pages of the manuscript MS 799 (MS 799: 2, Figure 6), we can find drafts for this diagram. In the drafts found in manuscript MS 540 (Figures 3, 4, and 5), we observe Peirce s effort to visually organize the classes in a way that would reflect the relations of similarity among their internal structures, expressed through trichotomic modalities (e.g., iconic classes, or classes of sinsigns). The sketches are clear attempts to get to the final arrangement shown in the Syllabus diagram, where

660 Priscila Lena Farias and João Queiroz Fig. 2: A diagram for 10 classes reproduced in accordance to the Syllabus model as seen on CP 2.264. The reproduction found in the second volume of the The Essential Peirce (EP 2: 296) omits the Roman numerals. Peirce finally seems to be satisfied with the relative position of the classes, as he states in the passage quoted above (CP 2.264). The diagram found in MS 540: 29 (Figure 5) is the first of this series. There are four tentative models in this page. The most complete arrangement is one shown in the lower left corner of figure 5, where the class of qualisigns (111) is placed in the apex of a triangle supported on one side. Figure 7 shows the same structure, with the classes expressed in Arabic and Roman numerals, following the same convention adopted by the editors of the Collected Papers for the Syllabus diagram. In manuscript MS 540: 28 (Figure 4) we can find, in the upper right corner, a list of pairs of trichotomic aspects of the classes (e.g., rhematic iconic, rhematic legisign ) followed by Arabic and Roman figures (used only for the number 10, represented as X), indicating the classes that have such aspects. The convention adopted for this notation is identical to the one adopted by the editors of the Collected Papers: numbering follows the order of presentation of the classes in the Syllabus. The only difference is the adoption of Arabic instead of Roman figures. On the left, and below this list, we find two triangular arrangements for the classes. The arrangement on the left seems to have been based in the numerical order of the classes. The largest arrangement, below, seems to be yet another

Peirce s models for ten classes of signs 661 Fig. 3: A draft for the Syllabus diagram found in manuscript MS 540: 27. attempt to organize the classes according to their internal composition. It should be noted that, in the latter, the position of classes I, II, III, and V is identical to the one that appears in the sketch in the following page (MS 540: 28, Figures 5 and 7). The relative position of classes is also similar to the one found in the Syllabus diagram, except for the position of classes VI (321) and X (333), which is reversed (in order to compare them, just rotate the Syllabus diagram counterclockwise, positioning class 111 in the upper vertex). The sketches found in MS 540: 27 (figure 3) and MS 799: 2 (Figure 6) seem to be the last in the series that leads to the Syllabus diagram. In both, the positions of the classes are marked by squares. In both cases, the relative position of classes IV (222) and VI (321) is inverted, revealing the difficulty of positioning class VI, the only one that combines aspects of thirdness, secondness, and firtsness, among the others. Indeed, this is the only difference with respect to the position of the classes, between the Syllabus diagram, where it is placed in the

662 Priscila Lena Farias and João Queiroz Fig. 4: A draft for the Syllabus diagram found in manuscript MS 540: 28. center of the triangular diagram, and the draft found in manuscript MS 799: 2 (figure 6), where it is placed at the bottom. The diagram in manuscript 540 MS: 27 (Figure 3), by contrast, must be rotated 180 degrees and mirrored so that the position of classes coincides with those found in the Syllabus diagram. Some adjustments, made by Peirce, to the final version of the Syllabus diagram include the differentiation in the thickness of the lines between the classes and the weight of the letters used to write their names. In the final version (MS 540: 17, figure 1), the lines dividing the cells for classes II and VI, IX and VI, and VII and III, are thicker, indicating that, unlike other bordering classes, they have only one aspect in common (II and VI, for example, are rhemes). The variation in the weight of the letters used in the description of the classes seems to have aimed to the simplification of their names terms that are not necessary for describing and differentiating the classes, and therefore can be omitted, are lighter.

Peirce s models for ten classes of signs 663 Fig. 5: A draft for the Syllabus diagram found in manuscript MS 540: 29. 3 The Welby diagram In the draft of a letter to Lady Welby, dated 24 28 December 1908 (L 463: 132 146, CP 8342 76, EP 2: 483 491), Peirce drew a second diagram for the 10 classes of signs. The diagram, reproduced in Figure 8 (L 463: 146), appears in the post scriptum of this draft, where the main theme of conversation is the ten trichotomies. Just below the diagram, Peirce makes the following comment: The number above to the left describes the Object of the Sign. That above to the right describes its Interpretant. That below describes the Sign itself. 1 signifies the Possible Modality, that of an Idea. 2 signifies the Actual Modality, that of an Occurrence. 3 signifies the Necessary Modality, that of a Habit. (L 463: 146; EP 2: 491) This diagram, which we will refer to as the Welby diagram (Figure 9), was reproduced in the Collected Papers (CP 8.376) and in the second volume of The Essential Peirce (EP 2: 491).

664 Priscila Lena Farias and João Queiroz Fig. 6: A draft for the Syllabus diagram found in manuscript MS 799: 2. Fig. 7: Underlying structure for 10 classes found in an early version the Syllabus diagram, in manuscript MS 540: 29 (Figure 5). There are other versions of the Welby diagram among Peirce s manuscripts. Some of them, found in a manuscript dated 27 December 1908 (MS 399D: 627, Figure 10), appear to be preparatory notes for this diagram, which was finally

Peirce s models for ten classes of signs 665 Fig. 8: A diagram for 10 classes drawn by Peirce in the draft of a letter to Lady Welby dated 24 28 December 1908 (L 463: 146). Fig. 9: The Welby diagram (L 463: 146, figure 8), as reproduced in the Collected Papers and in the second volume of The Essential Peirce (CP 8376, EP 2: 491). rendered, most probably, with the help of a ruler or a similar instrument (Figure 8). What is more crucial here is the position of the numbers that identify each class. In the sketch found in the lower part of the paper, the position of the classes and the figures used to identify them are identical to those found in the Welby diagram.

666 Priscila Lena Farias and João Queiroz Fig. 10: Preparatory notes for the Welby diagram found in a manuscript dated 27 December 1908 (MS 399D: 627). A drawing very similar to the Welby diagram appears in manuscript L 463: 155 (Figure 11). 2 This drawing seems to have been done by overlaying the diagram 2 This one seems to be another of the many drafts to the letter that was finally posted. The latter is, most possibly, the one dated 23 December 1908, and contains no diagram (Hardwick 1977 80 85; EP 2: 478 481).

Peirce s models for ten classes of signs 667 Fig. 11: A diagram for classes found in 10 L 463: 155. It seems to have been drawn by overlaying the Welby diagram (L 463: 146, Figure 8) found in manuscript L 463: 146 (Figure 8) with a new sheet of paper, and copying parts of it. It consists of 10 triangles, which contain 10 classes, and has no empty cells, as the ones in the Welby diagram. Peirce makes the following comments on this diagram:... the three divisions according to the Modality of Being of the Sign itself, of its Object, and of its Interpretant cannot make 27 classes of Signs but only Ten; namely, appropriating a little triangular space with a vertex down to the description of each class, and denoting by 1 Possible 2 Actual 3 Necessitant Modality, I write one of these numbers in each of the three corners of the triangular space. The lower corner to characterize the Mode of Being of the Sign Itself. The left hand upper corner to characterize the Mode of Being of its Object. The right hand upper corner to characterize the Mode of Being of its Interpretant. Then the Ten resulting classes of signs will be those shown in the Scheme below. (L 463: 155) On the side of the diagram, Peirce includes the following comment: An Abstractive can only be Descriptive not Designative nor Copulative while a Copulative can only be Collective, not Abstractive nor Concretive (L 463: 155). The terms used by Peirce in this excerpt refer to the trichotomic modalities of Od ([nature of the] dynamic object) and Oi ([nature of the] immediate object). The statement is peculiar, since these trichotomies only become part of the classifications of signs once Peirce describes the division into 28 classes. Furthermore,

668 Priscila Lena Farias and João Queiroz although these diagrams are structurally very similar to the Syllabus diagram, there are important differences relatively to the classes represented in their cells. If we consider that the reading sequence of the figures that represent the classes in the Welby diagram is (i) top left, (ii) bottom, and (iii) upper right corner, this would correspond, in terms of order of determination, to say that the Object determines the Sign, which determines the Interpretant. This seems to contradict what we observe in the Syllabus diagram, where the Sign determines its relation to the Object, which determines its relation to the Interpretant. However, we must remember that, in the Welby diagram, what we are calling Object is described as the mode of being of [the Sign s] Object (and not the relationship of the Sign with its Object), and, similarly, that what we are calling Interpretant is described as the mode of being of [the Sign s] Interpretant. The implication of this is that Peirce seems to be showing us here, with this diagram, is that the mode of being of the Sign s Object (immediate or dynamic) determines the mode of being of the Sign, which determines the the mode of being of its Interpretant (immediate, dynamic or final). This is not the order of determination that generates the 10 classes of signs described in the Syllabus, but is also not in contradiction with it. This is the basic structure of the order of determination which gives rise to another classification, the 28 classes of signs. This is, in fact, the number of triangular cells with vertex down in the Welby diagram, although only ten of them are occupied by classes, expressed in Arabic numbers. 4 Conclusion Peirce devoted great attention to the development of models for visually representing ten classes of signs. The diagrams are important because they graphically express relations of affinity and of hierarchical dependence between the classes. We presented here the intermediate steps taken by Peirce to obtain diagrammatic models for ten classes of signs. The development of the ten classes described in the Syllabus was carefully investigated by several authors (e.g., Houser 1991; Freadman 1996, 2001, 2004), but Peirce s diagrammatic experiments related to this classification were never considered. The 10 classes of signs form a system of cross-relations (see Freadman 1996: 150) designed by a precise arrangement of 3-trichotomic divisions. The main problem presented in any attempt to diagrammatically render this system is related to the development of a model whose structure of regular intervals would reflect the structural regularity that distinguishes the classes. However, although the structure of the Welby and the Syllabus diagrams are very similar, and although both are diagrams for 10 classes, and share similar

Peirce s models for ten classes of signs 669 structures, the classes shown in the two models are clearly not the same. While the Syllabus diagram shows us the ten 3-trichotomic classes described in Peirce s course outline in 1903, the Welby diagram, developed in December 1908 shows us a subset of the division of signs into 28 classes, represented by 3 of their 6-trichotomic aspects. Despite such differences, experiments with visual models have undoubtedly been at the core of Peirce s musings about the classification of signs, indicating the importance of the manipulation of external diagrammatic resources to the exploration of new ideas in the domain of Speculative Grammar. Acknowledgments: The authors would like to acknowledge the support received, in the form of research grants, from São Paulo Research Foundation (FAPESP) and Minas Gerais Research Foundation (FAPEMIG). References Atkin, Albert. 2010. Peirce s theory of signs. In Edward N. Zalta (ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/peirce-semiotics (accessed 14 June 2014). Balat, Michel. 1990. Type, Trace, Ton, le ton peircien. Semiosis 57 58. 81 87. Farias, Priscila & João Queiroz. 2000. Notes for a dynamic diagram of Charles Peirce s classifications of signs. Semiotica 131(1/2). 19 44. Farias, Priscila & João Queiroz. 2003. On diagrams for Peirce s 10, 28, and 66 classes of signs. Semiotica 147(1/4). 165 184. Farias, Priscila & João Queiroz. 2004. 10cubes and 3N3: Using interactive diagrams to investigate Charles Peirce s classifications of signs. Semiotica 151(1/4). 41 63. Farias, Priscila & João Queiroz. 2006. Images, diagrams, and metaphors: Hypoicons in the context of Peirce s sixty-six-fold classification of signs. Semiotica 162(1/4). 287 307. Freadman, Anne. 1996. Peirce s second classification of signs. In Vincent M. Colapietro & Thomas M. Olshewsky (eds.), Peirce s doctrine of signs: Theory, applications, and connections, 143 159. Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter. Freadman, Anne. 2001. The classifications of signs (II): 1903. In João Queiroz & Ricardo Gudwin (eds.), Digital encyclopedia of C. S. Peirce. http://www.digitalpeirce.fee.unicamp.br (accessed 14 June 2014). http://www.commens.org/encyclopedia/article/freadman-anneclassifications-signs-ii-1903 (accessed July 9, 2014). Freadman, Anne. 2004. The machinery of talk: Charles Peirce and the sign hypothesis. Stanford: Stanford University Press. Hardwick, Charles (ed.). 1977. Semiotics and significs: The correspondence between Charles S. Peirce and Victoria Welby. Bloomington & London: Indiana University Press. Houser, Nathan. 1991. A Peircean classification of models. In: Myrdene Anderson & Floyd Merrell (eds.), On semiotic modeling, 431 439. Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter. Houser, Nathan. 2010. Peirce, phenomenology, and semiotics. In Paul Cobley (ed.), The Routledge companion to semiotics, 89 100. London & New York: Routledge.

670 Priscila Lena Farias and João Queiroz Jappy, Antony. 1989. Peirce s sixty-six signs revisited. In Gérard Deledalle (ed.), Semiotics and pragmatics, 143 153. Amsterdam: John Benjamins. Lieb, Irwin C. 1977. Appendix B. In C. S. Hardwick (ed.), Semiotics and significs: The correspondence between Charles S. Peirce and Victoria Lady Welby, 161 166. Bloomington: Indiana University Press. Liszka, James. 1996. A general introduction to the semeiotic of Charles S. Peirce. Bloomington: Indiana University Press. Marty, Robert. 1982. C. S. Peirce s phaneroscopy and semiotics. Semiotica 41(1/4). 169 181. Merrell, Floyd. 1996. Signs grow: Semiosis and life processes. Toronto: University of Toronto Press. Müller, Ralf. 1994. On the principles of construction and the order of Peirce s trichotomies of signs. Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 30(1). 135 153. Paavola, Sami. 2011. Diagrams, iconicity, and abductive discovery. Semiotica 186(1/4). 297 314. Parker, Kelly. 1998. The continuity of Peirce s thought. Nashville: Vanderbilt University. Peirce, Charles S. 1931 1966. The collected papers of Charles S. Peirce, 8 vols., C. Hartshorne, P. Weiss & A. W. Burks (eds.). Cambridge: Harvard University Press. [Reference to Peirce s papers will be designated CP followed by volume and paragraph number.] Peirce, Charles S. 1967. Manuscripts in the Houghton Library of Harvard University, as identified by Richard Robin, Annotated catalogue of the Papers of Charles S. Peirce. Amherst: University of Massachusetts Press. [Reference to Peirce s manuscripts will be designated MS or L.] Peirce, Charles Sanders. 1998. Essential Peirce: Selected philosophical writings, vol. 2 (1893 1913), Peirce Edition Project (eds.). Bloomington: Indiana University Press. [Reference to vol. 2 of Essential Peirce will be designated EP 2.] Queiroz, João. 2012a. Dicent symbols in non-human semiotic processes. Biosemiotics 5. 1 11. Queiroz, João. 2012b. Peirce s ten classes of signs: Modeling biosemiotic processes and systems. In Timo Maran, Kati Lindström, Riin Magnus & Morten Tønnessen (eds.), Semiotics in the wild: Essays in honour of Kalevi Kull on the occasion of his sixtieth birthday, 55 62. Tartu: Tartu University Press. Sanders, Gary. 1970. Peirce sixty-six signs? Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 6(1). 3 16. Savan, David. 1976. An introduction to C. S. Peirce s semiotics part 1. Toronto: Semiotic Circle. Serson, Breno. 1997. On Peirce s pure grammar as a general theory of cognition: From the thought-sign of 1868 to the semeiotic theory of assertion. Semiotica 113(1/2). 107 157. Short, Thomas. 2007. Peirce s theory of signs. Cambridge University Press. Stjernfelt, Frederik. 2000. Diagrams as centerpiece in a Peircean epistemology. Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 36(3). 357 392. Stjernfelt, Frederik. 2007. Diagrammatology: An investigation on the borderlines of phenomenology, ontology, and semiotics. Berlin: Springer. Tursman, Richard. 1987. Peirce s theory of scientific discovery: A system of logic conceived as semiotics. Indiana University Press. Weiss, Paul & Arthur Burks. 1945. Peirce s sixty-six signs. Journal of Philosophy 42. 383 388.

Peirce s models for ten classes of signs 671 Bionotes Priscila Farias (b. 1964) is a professor at University of São Paulo <prifarias@ usp.br>. Her research interests include design, semiotics, and typography. Her publications include Letters and cities: Reading the urban environment with the help of perception theories (2009); Architectonic epigraphs: details that tell a bigger story (2012); and São Paulo City epigraphic archive: Construction steps and procedures (2013). João Queiroz (b. 1963) is an associate professor at Federal University of Juiz de Fora <queirozj@pq.cnpq.br>. His research interests include biosemiotics, Peirce s philosophy, cognitive science, and intermediality and intersemiotic translation. His publications include Information and semiosis in living systems: A semiotic approach (with C. Emmeche & C. El-Hani, 2010); Advances in modeling adaptive and cognitive systems (with A. Loula, 2010); and Modeling intersemiotic translation: Notes toward a peircean approach (with D. Aguiar, 2010).