Appraising the Ordinary Tension in Everyday Aesthetics

Similar documents
Perception and Mind-Dependence Lecture 3

that would join theoretical philosophy (metaphysics) and practical philosophy (ethics)?

Summit Public Schools Summit, New Jersey Grade Level 1 / Content Area: Visual Arts

A Comprehensive Critical Study of Gadamer s Hermeneutics

observation and conceptual interpretation

What is the Object of Thinking Differently?

Aristotle on the Human Good

Guide to the Republic as it sets up Plato s discussion of education in the Allegory of the Cave.

VARIETIES OF CONTEMPORARY AESTHETICS

What s Really Disgusting

ENVIRONMENTAL EXPERIENCE: Beyond Aesthetic Subjectivism and Objectivism

Edward Winters. Aesthetics and Architecture. London: Continuum, 2007, 179 pp. ISBN

The Spell of the Sensuous Chapter Summaries 1-4 Breakthrough Intensive 2016/2017

What do our appreciation of tonal music and tea roses, our acquisition of the concepts

Rethinking the Aesthetic Experience: Kant s Subjective Universality

The Doctrine of the Mean

Misc Fiction Irony Point of view Plot time place social environment

Grade 8 Fine Arts Guidelines: Dance

Reply to Stalnaker. Timothy Williamson. In Models and Reality, Robert Stalnaker responds to the tensions discerned in Modal Logic

Heideggerian Ontology: A Philosophic Base for Arts and Humanties Education

Nicomachean Ethics. p. 1. Aristotle. Translated by W. D. Ross. Book II. Moral Virtue (excerpts)

An Intense Defence of Gadamer s Significance for Aesthetics

PROGRAMME SPECIFICATION FOR M.ST. IN FILM AESTHETICS. 1. Awarding institution/body University of Oxford. 2. Teaching institution University of Oxford

SUMMARY BOETHIUS AND THE PROBLEM OF UNIVERSALS

Kant: Notes on the Critique of Judgment

Summit Public Schools Summit, New Jersey Grade Level 3/ Content Area: Visual Arts

The Strengths and Weaknesses of Frege's Critique of Locke By Tony Walton

Episode 28: Stand On Your Head. I m Emily P. Freeman and welcome to The Next Right Thing. You re listening to episode 28.

Thinking Broadly COPYRIGHTED MATERIAL. Concepts. Sources Activities Origins Influences Issues. Roles Form Function Experiences Voice

Sight and Sensibility: Evaluating Pictures Mind, Vol April 2008 Mind Association 2008

PHI 3240: Philosophy of Art

A Happy Ending: Happiness in the Nicomachean Ethics and Consolation of Philosophy. Wesley Spears

Dawn M. Phillips The real challenge for an aesthetics of photography

Locke and Berkeley. Lecture 2: Primary and Secondary Qualities

Zooming in and zooming out

1/10. Berkeley on Abstraction

Communication Studies Publication details, including instructions for authors and subscription information:


Kant Prolegomena to any Future Metaphysics, Preface, excerpts 1 Critique of Pure Reason, excerpts 2 PHIL101 Prof. Oakes updated: 9/19/13 12:13 PM

LÍNGUA INGLESA How Poetry Can Change Lives by John Burnside

Towards a Phenomenology of Development

Immanuel Kant Critique of Pure Reason

Resemblance Nominalism: A Solution to the Problem of Universals. GONZALO RODRIGUEZ-PEREYRA. Oxford: Clarendon Press, Pp. xii, 238.

The Art of Time Travel: A Bigger Picture

The Cognitive Nature of Metonymy and Its Implications for English Vocabulary Teaching

Life Areas Test & Bagua Map

Review of David Woodruff Smith and Amie L. Thomasson, eds., Phenomenology and the Philosophy of Mind, 2005, Oxford University Press.

Rashid Johnson on David Hammons, Andy Goldsworthy, and His Own Anxiety of Movement

ON GESTURAL MEANING IN ACTS OF EXPRESSION

6 The Analysis of Culture

Philosophy of Science: The Pragmatic Alternative April 2017 Center for Philosophy of Science University of Pittsburgh ABSTRACTS

On Recanati s Mental Files

Examination papers and Examiners reports E040. Victorians. Examination paper

HERMENEUTIC PHILOSOPHY AND DATA COLLECTION: A PRACTICAL FRAMEWORK

Why is there the need for explanation? objects and their realities Dr Kristina Niedderer Falmouth College of Arts, England

PHL 317K 1 Fall 2017 Overview of Weeks 1 5

A DEFENCE OF AN INSTITUTIONAL ANALYSIS OF ART ELIZABETH HEMSLEY UNIVERSITY OF EDINBURGH

Object Oriented Learning in Art Museums Patterson Williams Roundtable Reports, Vol. 7, No. 2 (1982),

International Journal of Advancements in Research & Technology, Volume 4, Issue 11, November ISSN

Critical Spatial Practice Jane Rendell

Reflections on a sofa-bed : functional beauty and looking fit

Aesthetics of the Everyday Mondays, Päärakennus, sali 4

Logic, Truth and Inquiry (Book Review)

Art and Morality. Sebastian Nye LECTURE 2. Autonomism and Ethicism

Student Learning Assessment for ART 100 Katie Frank

Doctoral Thesis in Ancient Philosophy. The Problem of Categories: Plotinus as Synthesis of Plato and Aristotle

Early Modern Philosophy Locke and Berkeley. Lecture 2: Primary and Secondary Qualities

SURVEYS FOR REFLECTIVE PRACTICE

Action, Criticism & Theory for Music Education

foucault s archaeology science and transformation David Webb

Why Pleasure Gains Fifth Rank: Against the Anti-Hedonist Interpretation of the Philebus 1

1/8. The Third Paralogism and the Transcendental Unity of Apperception

The Nature of Rhetorical Criticism

AESTHETICS. Key Terms

The Nature of Art. Introduction: Art in our lives

Tradition and the Individual Poem: An Inquiry into Anthologies (review)

SYSTEM-PURPOSE METHOD: THEORETICAL AND PRACTICAL ASPECTS Ramil Dursunov PhD in Law University of Fribourg, Faculty of Law ABSTRACT INTRODUCTION

FINE ART. Transition Pack. Course Guide and Summer Work. Exam Board: AQA Course Title: Fine Art Course Code:

Are There Two Theories of Goodness in the Republic? A Response to Santas. Rachel Singpurwalla

The poetry of space Creating quality space Poetic buildings are all based on a set of basic principles and design tools. Foremost among these are:

Bring it On: The Gift of Conflict

A Brief Guide to Writing SOCIAL THEORY

KINDS (NATURAL KINDS VS. HUMAN KINDS)

Benchmark A: Perform and describe dances from various cultures and historical periods with emphasis on cultures addressed in social studies.

Defining the profession: placing plain language in the field of communication.

CONRAD AND IMPRESSIONISM JOHN G. PETERS

Visual Arts Curriculum Framework

Action, Criticism & Theory for Music Education

Relational Needs Assessment Tool

According to Maxwell s second law of thermodynamics, the entropy in a system will increase (it will lose energy) unless new energy is put in.

MANOR ROAD PRIMARY SCHOOL

In this essay, I criticise the arguments made in Dickie's article The Myth of the Aesthetic

The Mind's Movement: An Essay on Expression

Capstone Courses

Truth and Tropes. by Keith Lehrer and Joseph Tolliver

Music Policy. Introduction

Realism and Representation: The Case of Rembrandt s

Berkeley s idealism. Jeff Speaks phil October 30, 2018

Q2: Do you think creativity is something of genetic or environmental, or both? Q3: One can learn to be creative or not? How?

A Study of the Bergsonian Notion of <Sensibility>

Transcription:

Appraising the Ordinary Tension in Everyday Aesthetics Jane Forsey * Department of Philosophy, University of Winnipeg Abstract. The recent movement of Everyday Aesthetics seeks to theorize our responses to ordinary things and daily activities. But a tension arises in such attempts: can we appreciate the ordinary as ordinary without first making it extraordinary or unusual? Tom Leddy, in his new work The Extraordinary in the Ordinary argues that we cannot. This paper will contrast his approach with the dissenting position of Arto Haapala, and argue that aesthetic experiences and appraisals can indeed reveal themselves within quotidian contexts. In 2005, Tom Leddy made the following remark about the nascent field of Everyday Aesthetics: It would seem that we need to make some sort of distinction between the aesthetics of everyday life ordinarily experienced and the aesthetics of ordinary life extraordinarily experienced. However, any attempt to increase the aesthetic intensity of our everyday lifeexperiences will tend to push those experiences in the direction of the extraordinary. One can only conclude that there is a tension within the very concept of the aesthetics of everyday life. 1 This tension cuts to the heart of what the movement seeks to achieve. Everyday Aesthetics has sought to open up a new domain of inquiry within the discipline, in part by focusing on objects and activities that have generally been neglected by traditional aesthetic theory: sofas, knives, and coffee-pots on the one hand, and cooking, walking to work or going to a ballgame on the other. But more than expanding the range of objects * Email: j.forsey@uwinnipeg.ca 1 Leddy, 2005, p. 18. 237

and activities fit for our aesthetic attention, some philosophers in this area have argued that our aesthetic experiences of the everyday cannot be theorized along the same lines as our experiences of the fine arts, or the beauty and sublimity of nature. The quotidian aspects of our lives, while meriting aesthetic appraisal, also require that we rethink how we respond to ordinary things. The tension, as Leddy saw, is that appreciating a sofa or ballgame, or subjecting it to our theoretical gaze, seems to lift it from the realm of the ordinary to that of the unusual or striking. That is, to make such a thing worthy of our aesthetic attention is at the same time to make it somehow extraordinary, or rob it of the very everydayness the movement seeks to focus on. When Leddy published his work The Extraordinary in the Ordinary last year, I hoped for a resolution to this tension, but I was disappointed. For, instead of trying to solve the problem, Leddy merely conceded the game, claiming that it is not possible to approach the ordinariness of the ordinary without making it extraordinary, without approaching it, therefore, in an art-like way. 2 I disagree. While thus far attempts to capture the peculiarly aesthetic nature of our daily lives have not been overly successful, I do not think that it is in principle an impossible undertaking. I will contrast Leddy s approach with that of Arto Haapala to illustrate the difficulty the movement faces, before providing a suggestion of my own. Leddy s central claim is that the ordinary qua ordinary is uninteresting or boring and only becomes aesthetic when transformed to become akin to a work of art. 3 He affects this transformation through the notion of aura which explains how quotidian objects come to merit our attention. Aura is not an aesthetic property per se but an experience of an object as having the quality of heightened significance in which it seems to extend beyond itself. 4 Aura is a phenomenological characteristic of an object as experienced, in a particularly vivid way. When we ascribe aesthetic properties to a thing when we appraise it we are describing our experience as having an aura for us. His various characterizations of aura include that we need to experience an object as (i) being somehow greater than itself; (ii) as having a surrounding glow ; and (iii) as seeming more real and alive. 2 Leddy, 2012, p.121. 3 Leddy, 2012, p.112. 4 Leddy, 2012, pp.116-7. 238

This experience is attended with pleasure; requires imaginative perception ; and what he calls an aesthetic attitude or a sensing in a certain way. Specifically, aura is what aesthetic properties have in common, and what accounts for an object being seen to possess them. 5 For us to make an aesthetic appraisal of an ordinary chair, for instance, we must first experience that chair as being different from, and having greater significance than, the other objects in the room (including the other chairs). Only then can we apply predicates such as graceful or delicate to it, and be said to have had an aesthetic experience of it, due to its transformation into a nominal work of art. Glenn Parsons, in a paper delivered to the American Society for Aesthetics annual general meeting in St. Louis, understands Leddy s theory in terms of metaphor: to perceive an object imaginatively, with aesthetic attitude, is just to perceive it metaphorically. 6 Its heightened significance for us is thus of a particular kind. Read this way, Leddy s account shares some of the characteristics of Danto s theory of fine art, from The Transfiguration of the Commonplace. But Leddy s goal is broader than Danto s, in that he wishes aura to describe aesthetic experience at large, including that of everyday things. And it is here that weaknesses arise. First, if we grant that aura transforms the ordinary, the aesthetic will not be its only kind. For instance, everything that my partner has ever received as a gift has a glow of untouchability about it such that it can never be thrown away, no matter how old, chipped, torn, or stained it might become. If I suggest that this coffee mug with the broken handle should go, I m invariably met with the cry but it was a gift! I call this the aura of sentimentality and while it raises the mug to a status somehow greater than itself, it has nothing to do with the aesthetic merit of the mug in question. My partner may even agree with my assessment that it is old, broken and tacky but he values it nonetheless. Similarly, my friend who returns every year to the same mosquito-ridden holiday cottage with the lumpy sofa, leaky windows and smell of mildew, does so admittedly because his family has always spent the summers there. (I would call this the aura of nostalgia). But if there are various auras that objects can have, 5 Leddy, 2012, pp.128-135. 6 Parsons paper was presented as part of a panel on Leddy s book. St. Louis, October 25, 2012. 239

we need a way of distinguishing between them, to isolate the one that is aesthetic, both to ourselves and to others. Of course the auras of sentimentality and nostalgia are highly personal: there is no arguing about the sentimental value of a mug with the person who feels that sentiment. But an aesthetic aura would be equally subjective: the object must be lifted for me from the realm of the ordinary, and have heightened significance again for me when I appraise it. Because my experience constitutes the aesthetic object in question, any appraisal of it will be equally mine, and therefore not open to reasoned debate with others. The difference between a mug of sentimental value and one of aesthetic value will rest only on my say so. Yet our experiences, to be aesthetic, must be in principle shareable and communicable, whatever theory one subscribes to. They must have some objective, or objectifiable aspect to make them appropriately aesthetic. Leddy s notion of aura, at least regarding the everyday, instead leads us to an acute relativism, if not to dissolving what we mean by aesthetic pleasure and experience altogether. Certainly no one would disagree that some quotidian objects such as chairs or china vases have come to be seen as extraordinary, and have been exhibited in museums alongside works of art, to be appraised in a similar art-like manner. But the difference between that chair in the museum and the one in my living room is that the former is publicly acknowledged to be an apt object of our attention, and the latter is one only because I have made it so. Further, an emphasis on aura means that the object itself becomes of secondary interest: we do not appraise its qualities directly, but those qualities as seen through the veneer of its particular significance for us. What we are responding to, it appears, is the significance created, and the object is merely a vehicle for its delivery, in the way that an ordinary thing can become transformed within a metaphorical expression to have heightened significance. And while such a theory may work for our experiences of fine art, as Danto has argued, it is less successful for the ordinary chairs and coffee-pots that are part of our quotidian lives, in large part because these objects do not themselves lay claim to carrying any content or meaning that needs to be interpreted in the way that a metaphor or work of fine art can be. Even that museum chair, while being extraordinary enough to be displayed and appreciated, does not thereby become a 240

metaphor for something else: what we attend to in our aesthetic appreciation of it are the qualities that it actually possesses which in principle we can describe to, and discuss with, someone else. Taken together, Leddy s conditions for the aesthetic experience of the everyday effect their goal only by omitting the one thing that drew these theorists attention in the first place: its very everydayness, its familiarity and embeddedness in the context of our daily lives. Chris Dowling has called this a weak formulation of the aesthetics of daily life, where the concept of the aesthetic understood in terms of the value of fine art is merely extended to include quotidian objects and activities. 7 But it does this only by removing them from their contexts, and by first making them strange or unusual. I would like to contrast Leddy s approach with what Dowling calls a strong formulation of Everyday Aesthetics, which denies that an art-centred aesthetic can accommodate the stuff of our daily lives. Such strong versions are driven by the suggestion that despite the instrumental and functional nature of much of our everyday interactions, aesthetic experiences and appraisals can reveal themselves within these quotidian contexts. But they do so in ways not bound by the conventions and limitations that colour discussions of fine art. 8 Dowling argues that the strong version has not yet been successful in its aims and I agree but I am sympathetic to its overarching goal of bringing into focus the aesthetic texture of our ordinary lives qua ordinary, as a distinct but important facet of human experience. Let me turn to the work of Arto Haapala in this regard. Haapala is critical of what he calls the aesthetic model of strangeness, where a work of art is a paradigmatic example of a phenomenon that is supposed to stand out from the stream of the everyday. 9 Like Leddy s notion of aura, strangeness is not a property of objects per se but a phenomenological characteristic of our interactions with them: a work of fine art hung by the mantle can become familiar over the passage of time, just as a nominally mundane object such as a phone booth can become strange when, for instance, we are travelling in a foreign country. Unlike Leddy, though, Haapala seeks to theorize the everyday as an aesthetic of the fa- 7 Dowling, 2010, p.241. 8 Dowling, 2010, pp. 233, 241. 9 Haapala, 2005, p.41. 241

miliar and uncover the aesthetic relevance of the everyday as it is lived. His discussion of the strange stems from Heidegger s analysis of a tool, such as a hammer, which, when functioning properly, we pay no attention to. Only when the tool malfunctions do we notice it, and it comes to be seen as striking or unusual. When it works well it disappears into its function, as background, or as a thing we use to achieve our everyday purposes and in this role it becomes familiar. 10 The challenge for Haapala is how to make the familiar of aesthetic import without also making it strange. While he acknowledges the difficulty more explicitly than other theorists of the everyday, his proposal falls short of a solution. Again adopting a notion from Heidegger, Haapala s account ties familiarity to the process of home-building or settling down and making a place our own. Home-building is a way of forging a sense of belonging to an environment whereby we create attachments to our surroundings. Here the familiar can be contrasted with the strange, not in Leddy s sense of the boring versus the striking, but instead as that to which we belong, compared to being in a state of homelessness and alienation (or, in the case of the hammer, a state of disrepair). However, while Haapala speaks to the import of the everyday, he has trouble explaining how these experiences are specifically aesthetic ones. His account provides a negative characterization, an aesthetic of what he calls the lacking, or the quiet fascination of the absence of the visual, auditory and other demands from the surroundings. The everyday provides pleasure through a comforting stability that makes us feel homey and in control, not because things are taken out of context but instead because of their utterly ordinary familiarity for us, which gives us a sense of home. 11 But there are many pleasures of home that we would not regard as particularly aesthetic: a hot bath or cozy seat by the fire also provide comfort and security in the way he intimates, and these feelings accompany a large number of our bodily or sensuous enjoyments. But physical pleasures are not aesthetic ones, even if we value them. Haapala s proposal seems to reduce the aesthetic to a kind of quiet satisfaction we feel when we arrive 10 Haapala 2005, p. 49. 11 Haapala, 2005, pp. 50-52. 242

home and find things as they ought to be a gentle sense that all is right with the world, safe and predictable. Here we seem to concede the aesthetic to an ethical-existential idea of place that provides us with a sense of meaning and identity. And in so doing, what Haapala calls our attention to is, ironically, that which commands no attention at all. From this impasse between the unusual and striking on the one hand, and the familiar and safe on the other, there is a solution that allows us to focus on the particularly aesthetic elements of the everyday without either exoticizing those experiences, or subsuming them within some larger normative framework. My recent work 12 has focused particularly on designed objects rather than everyday experiences but I think it can provide a model for both because the two are intertwined. We can agree with Leddy and Haapala that the ordinary things we use tend to disappear into the background of our instrumental goals and concerns. But it is not only when they break down that they come to our attention: we also notice things when they work extremely well, when they perform their functions with an ease or grace that calls for our appreciation. That some things are better than the norm does not make them strange, or remove them from the everyday any more than it makes them honorary works of art: they remain the chairs and coffee-pots that we use everyday. It is simply that at times some of them come to demand our aesthetic as opposed to practical or ethical (or sentimental) attention. The factors involved in our aesthetic appreciation of the everyday run a line between the extremes of Leddy s and Haapala s theories. For one thing, to merit my approbation, a given coffee-pot, for instance, must perform its function, and do so very well. Were it to make bad coffee, or fail altogether, it would indeed become strange but not in a meritorious way. Fulfilling its function is a minimal requirement for a designed object to be a candidate for aesthetic appraisal. More than this, to appraise the coffee-pot I must be a coffee drinker. For those who do not drink coffee, or have never made it, the pot will be a mystifying artefact. But this means that a certain amount of culturally and historically specific knowledge is required for me to make this judgement: the coffee-pot must be part of my everyday life and activities. This speaks to Haapala s notion 12 Forsey, 2013 243

of home-building in that the coffee-pot must be familiar, but its aesthetic merit does not reside merely in its place as part of my home: it stands out as exemplary because of its functional excellence. Standing out, however, does not mean that the pot acquires the patina of a special aura: its aesthetic value does not prescind from its nature as a coffee maker that I use everyday. What I suggest for an aesthetics of the ordinary qua ordinary is thus the following: 1. Pace Leddy, we attend to the actual qualities of the object in question, and in doing so, we are appraising something that is in principle shareable, and our judgements can thus be communicated to others (we can argue about the merits of my coffee-pot in a way that we cannot about, say, its sentimental value). 2. These qualities are integral to the object as it is used in our daily activities. Again pace Leddy, we need not lift it out of the realm of the everyday to thereby transform it into a nominal work of art to give it our attention. Instead, it is only by being an integral part of our specific lives that it comes to our notice. And this notice requires that we actively use it rather than merely admire it: an aesthetics of the ordinary combines objects with our daily interactions with them. 3. Being embedded in the familiar does not mean that a thing becomes mere background, however. Pace Haapala, we can notice and appraise an object when it works particularly well, and this makes it stand out from other coffee-pots we have used. But to appraise it aesthetically, we still need to be knowledgeable users and consumers of the thing in question. In doing so, we are not merely enjoying the sensuous pleasure of a cup of coffee. If we focus on these factors as contributing to an object s beauty: functional excellence, contextually specific knowledge, actual qualities of the thing in question, its quotidian use, and the in-principle communicability of our judgements with others, then we have the makings of an aesthetic of the ordinary as it is ordinarily experienced. We need neither raise it to 244

the status of artwork with special significance, nor lower it to the level of mere familiar background to do so. It need have neither metaphorical nor existential meaning for us. When we appreciate the everyday, we do so because it is part of our lives but an object can become aesthetically pleasing by being very good, while still remaining very much an everyday thing. And this, I think is the kernel of what the movement of Everyday Aesthetics is striving for: a way of acknowledging the particularly aesthetic texture of our daily lives and concerns. References Dowling, C. (2010). The Aesthetics of Daily Life British Journal of Aesthetics, 50: 225-242. Forsey, J. (2013). The Aesthetics of Design. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Haapala, A. (2005). On the Aesthetics of the Everyday: Familiarity, Strangeness and the Meaning of Place in Andrew Light and Jonathan Smith eds. The Aesthetics of Everyday Life New York: Columbia University Press. Leddy, T. (2005). The Nature of Everyday Aesthetics in Andrew Light and Jonathan Smith, eds. The Aesthetics of Everyday Life New York: Columbia University Press. (2012) The Extraordinary in the Ordinary: The Aesthetics of Everyday Life Toronto: Broadview Press. 245