Benedetto Croce s Theory of Science

Similar documents
Necessity in Kant; Subjective and Objective

REVIEW ARTICLE IDEAL EMBODIMENT: KANT S THEORY OF SENSIBILITY

Kant s Critique of Judgment

Conclusion. One way of characterizing the project Kant undertakes in the Critique of Pure Reason is by

1/8. Axioms of Intuition

The Senses at first let in particular Ideas. (Essay Concerning Human Understanding I.II.15)

INTERVIEW: ONTOFORMAT Classical Paradigms and Theoretical Foundations in Contemporary Research in Formal and Material Ontology.

The Strengths and Weaknesses of Frege's Critique of Locke By Tony Walton

KANT S THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE

Intersubjectivity and physical laws in post-kantian theory of knowledge: Natorp and Cassirer Scott Edgar October 2014.

KANT S TRANSCENDENTAL LOGIC

None DEREE COLLEGE SYLLABUS FOR: PH 4028 KANT AND GERMAN IDEALISM UK LEVEL 6 UK CREDITS: 15 US CREDITS: 3/0/3. (Updated SPRING 2016) PREREQUISITES:

Language and History in the Pragmatism of Giulio Preti

Philosophical Background to 19 th Century Modernism

ANALOGY, SCHEMATISM AND THE EXISTENCE OF GOD

A Copernican Revolution in IS: Using Kant's Critique of Pure Reason for Describing Epistemological Trends in IS

On The Search for a Perfect Language

UNIT SPECIFICATION FOR EXCHANGE AND STUDY ABROAD

The topic of this Majors Seminar is Relativism how to formulate it, and how to evaluate arguments for and against it.

1/6. The Anticipations of Perception

Bas C. van Fraassen, Scientific Representation: Paradoxes of Perspective, Oxford University Press, 2008.

Review of Krzysztof Brzechczyn, Idealization XIII: Modeling in History

Phenomenology Glossary

1/9. The B-Deduction

Logic and Philosophy of Science (LPS)

observation and conceptual interpretation

PAUL REDDING S CONTINENTAL IDEALISM (AND DELEUZE S CONTINUATION OF THE IDEALIST TRADITION) Sean Bowden

Imagination and Contingency: Overcoming the Problems of Kant s Transcendental Deduction

206 Metaphysics. Chapter 21. Universals

What do our appreciation of tonal music and tea roses, our acquisition of the concepts

GRADUATE SEMINARS

Philosophy Pathways Issue th December 2016

Sidestepping the holes of holism

Is Genetic Epistemology of Any Interest for Semiotics?

WHITEHEAD'S PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE AND METAPHYSICS

CONTENTS II. THE PURE OBJECT AND ITS INDIFFERENCE TO BEING

Scientific Philosophy

Kuhn s Notion of Scientific Progress. Christian Damböck Institute Vienna Circle University of Vienna

«Only the revival of Kant's transcendentalism can be an [possible] outlet for contemporary philosophy»

Poincaré s Aesthetics of Science

A Comprehensive Critical Study of Gadamer s Hermeneutics

that would join theoretical philosophy (metaphysics) and practical philosophy (ethics)?

The Shimer School Core Curriculum

Hypatia, Volume 21, Number 3, Summer 2006, pp (Review) DOI: /hyp For additional information about this article

A Letter from Louis Althusser on Gramsci s Thought

Kuhn Formalized. Christian Damböck Institute Vienna Circle University of Vienna

INTRODUCTION TO NONREPRESENTATION, THOMAS KUHN, AND LARRY LAUDAN

Pragmatism, Semiotic mind and Cognitivism

Kant, Peirce, Dewey: on the Supremacy of Practice over Theory

COURSE: PHILOSOPHY GRADE(S): NATIONAL STANDARDS: UNIT OBJECTIVES: Students will be able to: STATE STANDARDS:

AESTHETICS. Key Terms

KANT S THEORY OF SPACE AND THE NON-EUCLIDEAN GEOMETRIES

1/8. The Third Paralogism and the Transcendental Unity of Apperception

Ithaque : Revue de philosophie de l'université de Montréal

Categories and Schemata

INTRODUCTION. Cambridge University Press

Mapping Film Studies Thorsten Botz-Bornstein

Mind, Thinking and Creativity

Interpreting Kant's Critiques; Karl Ameriks; 2003

IMPORTANT QUOTATIONS

The Confluence of Aesthetics and Hermeneutics in Baumgarten, Meier, and Kant

INTERNATIONAL CONFERENCE ON ENGINEERING DESIGN ICED 05 MELBOURNE, AUGUST 15-18, 2005 GENERAL DESIGN THEORY AND GENETIC EPISTEMOLOGY

Quine s Two Dogmas of Empiricism. By Spencer Livingstone

A Study of the Bergsonian Notion of <Sensibility>

The aim of this paper is to explore Kant s notion of death with special attention paid to

Michael Friedman The Prolegomena and Natural Science

TEST BANK. Chapter 1 Historical Studies: Some Issues

KANTIAN CONCEPTUALISM

The Nature Of Order: An Essay On The Art Of Building And The Nature Of The Universe, Book 1 - The Phenomenon Of Life (Center For Environmental

1 Exceptions to this include Friedman 1992, 34-5 and Ferrari 2009, who allude to Cassirer s emphasis on

PH th Century Philosophy Ryerson University Department of Philosophy Mondays, 3-6pm Fall 2010

Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy

James SCOTT JOHNSTON, John Dewey s Earlier Logical Theory

The Teaching Method of Creative Education

Phenomenology and Non-Conceptual Content

Human Finitude and the Dialectics of Experience

What counts as a convincing scientific argument? Are the standards for such evaluation

Critical Theory. Mark Olssen University of Surrey. Social Research at Frankfurt-am Main in The term critical theory was originally

Biological Purposiveness and Analogical Reflection

Culture and Art Criticism

Modeling Scientific Revolutions: Gärdenfors and Levi on the Nature of Paradigm Shifts

124 Philosophy of Mathematics

Advanced English for Scholarly Writing

Ralph K. Hawkins Bethel College Mishawaka, Indiana

Social Mechanisms and Scientific Realism: Discussion of Mechanistic Explanation in Social Contexts Daniel Little, University of Michigan-Dearborn

Philosophy 405: Knowledge, Truth and Mathematics Spring Russell Marcus Hamilton College

KANT'S TRANSCENDENTAL DEDUCTION: AN ANALYTICAL-HISTORICAL COMMENTARY BY HENRY E. ALLISON

Università della Svizzera italiana. Faculty of Communication Sciences. Master of Arts in Philosophy 2017/18

Action, Criticism & Theory for Music Education

NATURE FROM WITHIN. Gustav Theodor Fechner and His Psychophysical. Michael Heidelberger. Translated by Cynthia Klohr. University of Pittsburgh Press

Introduction. Lior Rabi. José Ortega y Gasset is the most prominent Spanish philosopher in the 20 th century.

Self-Consciousness and Music in the Late Enlightenment

INTRODUCTION TO THE POLITICS OF SOCIAL THEORY

Jacek Surzyn University of Silesia Kant s Political Philosophy

The Power of Ideas: Milton Friedman s Empirical Methodology

Philosophy Department Expanded Course Descriptions Fall, 2007

Kant Prolegomena to any Future Metaphysics, Preface, excerpts 1 Critique of Pure Reason, excerpts 2 PHIL101 Prof. Oakes updated: 9/19/13 12:13 PM

THE LOGICAL FORM OF BIOLOGICAL OBJECTS

MAURICE MANDELBAUM HISTORY, MAN, & REASON A STUDY IN NINETEENTH-CENTURY THOUGHT THE JOHNS HOPKINS PRESS: BALTIMORE AND LONDON

The Debate on Research in the Arts

Transcription:

L&PS Logic and Philosophy of Science Vol. IX, No. 1, 2011, pp. 531-537 Benedetto Croce s Theory of Science Stefano Zappoli Università di Bergamo stefano.zappoli@unibg.it 1. Introduction 2. The Theory 3. The Context ABSTRACT. Benedetto Croce theorizes that natural sciences are defective sciences, because they always bump against facts that require to be intuitively and historically understood, and because they set up concepts which are anything but natural. These concepts can be used only in order to organize the empirical material; therefore they are mere schemes, or pseudo-concepts, or conceptual fictions. These fictions are of great help in simplifying the physical reality and in stating relations within it; they have an instrumental character like a sort of necessary functions and practical acts. Their main feature is the lack of universality; therefore they are just the opposite of pure concepts. Such logical theory does not involve a depreciation of natural sciences, which are rather viewed as a form of practical, economical knowing, like in the perspective of empiriocriticism (Avenarius, Mach) and conventionalism (Poincaré, Le Roy, Milhaud). But, unlike all these philosophers, Croce distinguishes clearly between pure sensation and intuition, on the one hand, and pure concept, on the other hand. And he founds real knowledge only on pure concepts. 1. Introduction 1909 Croce published a work named Logic as the science of the pure concept. This work has been charged since its appearance of having criticized science and reducing it as a false form of knowledge, namely as a knowledge based upon pseudo-concepts. The main authors of this critic were theorists The Author 2011. Published by L&PS Logic and Philosophy of Science http://www2.units.it/ ~episteme ISSN: 1826-1043

COGNOME E NOME PRIMO AUTORE, COGNOME E NOME SECONDO AUTORE like Federico Enriques and, after the Second World War, Ludovico Geymonat and his pupils, above all Giulio Giorello. A such seeming depreciation of science, combined with the cultural hegemony detained in Italy by Croce (and in general by the idealistic thought) had produced as sustained by the Geymonat s school a delayed circulation of modern scientific culture in Italy, in comparison with the rest of Europe and the world. My aim is to defend Croce on this point and thus demonstrate that when we rightly judge them Croce s views on natural science, considered as a specific form of knowledge, are analogous to the epistemological theories which circulated at the beginning of the 20 th Century within the fields of empiriocriticism and conventionalism. In the first part of this paper I will focus on Croce s theory of science itself, while in the second part I will deepen the context in which his theory developed, to clarify in which sense Croce s theory of science can be seen as analogous to those circulating in Europe between the end of the Eighteenth century and the beginning of the Nineteenth. 2. The Theory Can we relate Croce s thought with epistemology, or theory of science at all? Croce is not an epistemologist, nor did he dedicate a lot of pages to the philosophy of science. He s not a scientist, but not being a scientist should not be a sin, also by formulating a theory of science. The problem is: In which sense does Croce formulate a theory of science? At the beginning of the Nineteenth century Croce is a convinced enemy of positivism, i.e. enemy of a philosophy featuring the doctrine of a general philosophy which is above all particular sciences, namely the sciences of nature (physics, chemistry, biology, psychology). Within this so-called late positivism, which assumed the tacit scientific presupposition that the only reality is the material one, philosophy is conceived (i.e. in the first part, named The Unknowable of the First Principles [1862] of Herbert Spencer) as having the task to show how all science leads ultimately (like religion) to a belief in an Absolute that transcends human understanding. This attitude widely spread also in Italy at that time, above all among socialist circles, with whom Croce had sympathized in past years leads, in Croce s opinion, to a way of thinking featuring a metaphysical attitude enemy of criticism. 532

TITOLO DEL CONTRIBUTO The theoretical, i.e. the logical error of this doctrine is the presupposition that the only knowable reality is the material one. On the contrary, already in his first main philosophical work, i.e. the Aesthetic (1902), Croce writes that the only true science is the science of the spirit, and that the natural sciences are defective sciences, always bumping into facts which are intuitively and historically understood, and setting up concepts (unextended atom, ether or vibrating, vital force, unintuitable space) which are anything but natural. In 1904-5, in the first edition of his Logic, Croce repeats that natural disciplines cannot count as type or model of the true, solid and only science. In fact he writes the gnoseological theories they lately posed insist on the conventional character, handy, practical, economical of the constructions on which natural sciences work. These constructions are irrational as knowledge, but quite rational as practical facts (of the spirit). In the second edition of his Logic (1909) Croce articulates knowledge in two degrees. Knowledge is first knowledge of the individual, intuition that is also representation, and that is object of the aesthetic as a science. On a secondary step, knowledge is knowledge of the universal. Involved in this knowledge is not intuition, but thought, that is concept, pure concept, concrete universal: Logical knowledge is something beyond simple representation. The latter is individuality and multiplicity; the former the universality of individuality, the unity of multiplicity; the one is intuition, the other concept (Croce [1909], engl. transl., 8). The Logic is divided in two main sections. The first is dedicated to the definition of the pure concept, the individual judgment and the logical synthesis a priori. The second is devoted to philosophy, history, and natural and mathematical sciences. Croce aims to distinguish between pure concept, on the one hand, and empirical and abstract concepts, on the other: the first is the fundament of logic, the second ones are used by natural sciences to ordinate the empirical material and are simply schemes. Only the pure concept is real in itself. Empirical concepts, like abstract concepts, are pseudo-concepts, conceptual fictions, used by the sciences to simplify the physical reality in order to state relations in it, by quantifying reality stating natural laws, i.e. relations between natural facts. Material to knowledge is given by intuition. The beginning of knowledge is not perception: it is intuition, and sensations are consequences, not causes, of the intuition. They come after it, not before it. 533

COGNOME E NOME PRIMO AUTORE, COGNOME E NOME SECONDO AUTORE But what are these fictions, on which the knowledge of both natural and mathematical sciences is based? On the first hand, fictions are spiritual products, which aid and contribute to the life of the spirit. They are necessary functions. They are practical acts. They make easily available to memory a patrimony of acquired knowledge that once has been possessed. Conceptual fictions are instruments constructed for this purpose. By means of them armies of representations are evoked with a single word, or a single word approximately indicates what form of operation must be resorted to, in order that certain representations may be recovered (Croce [1909], engl. transl., 20-21). Croce distinguishes, then, between science in the proper form, that is logic or philosophy, and natural science. The first is based upon concepts, pure concepts, the second is based upon empirical concepts, on the one hand, and abstract concepts, on the other. Both of them are fictions. So, while a true and proper concept is universal in itself, ultrarepresentative and omnirepresentative at the same time, the main feature of fictions is precisely the lacking of this universality: [In] fictional concept or conceptual fictions either the content is furnished by a group of representations, even by a single representation, so that they are not ultrarepresentative [that is the case of empirical concepts ]; or there is no representable content, so that they are not omnirepresentative [that is the case of abstract concepts ]. Examples of the first type are afforded by the concepts of house, cat, rose; of the second, those of triangle, or of free motion. Once stated that the theory of conceptual fictions, namely pseudo-concepts, means by Croce not a depreciation of science as a form of knowledge, but only a theorization of it in the sense of a practical knowledge, or better of a practical act of knowledge, my final aim is to prove that this economical theory of science is not like someone once said an aping or mimicry of the similar theories of empiriocriticists and conventionalists, but has its own theoretical axis inside the philosophy, or simply the logic, of his author. To state that, we have to assume a genetical perspective 1 in considering the logical thought 1 Recently Michael Friedman has defined the conception of scientific knowledge by which the Marburg School adapting critical philosophy to the deep revolutionary changes affecting mathematics and the mathematical sciences» throughout the late nineteenth and early 534

TITOLO DEL CONTRIBUTO of Croce. That means, we have to investigate historically his theory, to find out which philosophical roots his theory of logical concept has. 3. The Context Croce attributes much importance to the logical thought of Kant. Elaborating a cue from Leibniz s New Essays on Human Understanding, printed in 1765, Kant began to rebuilt the Logic as a philosophical science. Against all empiricism an empiricism that, by Hume, ended in skepticism Kant strived to demonstrate that the exact science of nature is possible. The Critique of Pure Reason contains the Logic of physical and mathematical sciences, thought not more by an empiricist but by a philosopher, who overtook empiricism and recognized that the concepts of experience presuppose an human intellect that originally constructs them. But Kant confused the logical and philosophical a priori synthesis his major discovery with the a priori synthesis of the sciences, i.e. mathematics and physics, thus invalidating his profoundly romantic concept of the synthesis a priori through a classicist and intellectualist treatment of it: The synthesis is the palpitating reality which makes itself and knows itself in the making: the Kantian philosophy makes it rigid again in the concepts of the sciences; and it is a philosophy in which the sense of life, of imagination, of individuality, of history, is almost as completely absent as in the great systems of the Cartesian period (Croce [1909], engl. transl., 535-7). It was Hegel who established the new doctrine of the concept. The true concept for him is the idea, and the idea is the absolute unity of the concept and of its objectivity. It was Kuno Fischer who clearly distinguished the empirical concepts from the pure ones, and noted that those which are pure or philosophical are, in the spirit, the basis and presupposition of the others. The pure concepts do not represent phenomena, but connections and relations. twentieth centuries replaced Kant s original static or timeless version of the synthetic a priori, as an essentially developmental or genetic one (Friedman [2010], 178). 535

COGNOME E NOME PRIMO AUTORE, COGNOME E NOME SECONDO AUTORE In the last pages of the historical section of his Logic, Croce refers explicitly to the new theories emerging from the field of mathematics, physics and natural science themselves, theories that recognizes the practical or economic character of these sciences. Croce holds, for example, the empiriocriticism of Avenarius (1890) in high esteem, while considering science to be a simple description of the forms of experience (pure intuition or pure perception) for the purpose of simplifying it. Mach (1886) is considered the one who has developed and popularized these views, by reaching them as own conclusions departing from the study of mechanics 2. Within the Neo-Kantian field, Ernst Rickert, in his book on the Limits of concept formation in natural science (1896-1902), also, outgoing from other cultural assumptions, holds the concept resulting of the labour of the sciences to be nothing but a means to a scientific end. What about France? Here the same ideas are sustained by a group of thinkers variously called philosophers of contingency, of liberty, of intuition or of action. For Bergson the concepts of the natural sciences are symboles et etiquettes. Le Roy holds that scientific laws only become rigorous when they are changed into conventions. Moving from the theories of higher geometry, which revealed the practical character of mathematics, Poincaré and Milhaud affirms the conventional character of the mathematical and physical sciences (for more details see Brenner [2003]). But the limit of all these theories, Croce argues, is to put pure sensation and intuition instead of pure concept as the term that is distinct from the empirical and abstract concepts, as the knowledge that is not falsified by practical ends and discovered beneath labels and formulae (Croce [1909], engl. transl., 557-8). REFERENCES AVENARIUS, R. (1890): Kritik der reinen Erfahrung, Leipzig: Fues. BERGSON, H. (1903): Introduction à la Métaphysique, Revue de métaphysique et de morale, 11, 1-36. BRENNER, A. (2003): Les origines françaises de la philosophie des sciences, Paris: Presses Universitaires de France. 210. 2 Very interesting similarities to Croce s views are to be found in Husserl (1900), 192-536

TITOLO DEL CONTRIBUTO CROCE, B. (1902): Estetica come scienza dell espressione e linguistica generale, Milano: Sandron. Translated as Æsthetic as science of expression and general linguistic by D. Ainslie. London: Macmillan and Co., 1909. CROCE, B. (1909): Logica come scienza del concetto puro, Bari: Laterza. Translated as Logic as the science of the pure concept by D. Ainsle. London: Macmillan and Co., 1917. FISCHER, K. (1865): System der Logik und Metaphysik oder Wissenschaftslehre. Zweite völlig umgearbeitete Auflage, Heidelberg: Bassermann. FRIEDMAN, M. (2010): Ernst Cassirer and Thomas Kuhn: The Neo-Kantian Tradition in the History and Philosophy of Science, in Rudolf A. Makkreel and Sebastian Luft (eds.), Neo-Kantianism in Contemporary Philosophy (Bloomington: Indiana University Press). GIORELLO, G. (Ed.) (1977): L immagine della scienza, Milan: Mondadori. HUSSERL, E. (1900). Logische Untersuchungen. I, Prolegomena zur reinen Logik. Tübingen: Max Niemeyer Verlag, 1993 7. MACH, E. (1886): Beiträge zur Analyse der Empfindungen, Jena: Fischer. Translated as Contributions to the analysis of the sensations by C. M. Williams. Chicago: The Open Court, 1897. MILHAUD, G. (1898): Essai sur le conditions et les limites de la certitude logique, Paris: Alcan. POINCARÉ, H. (1904): La valeur de la science, Paris: Flammarion. RICKERT, H. (1902): Die Grenzen der naturwissenschaftlichen Begriffsbildung, Tübingen: Mohr. Translated as The limits of concept formation in natural science: a logical introduction to the historical sciences by G. Oakes. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1986. 537