Between Cabbages and Kings: Speaking Across Forms of Life Marcus Morgan, Cambridge University

Similar documents
Philip Kitcher and Gillian Barker, Philosophy of Science: A New Introduction, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2014, pp. 192

INTRODUCTION TO NONREPRESENTATION, THOMAS KUHN, AND LARRY LAUDAN

TROUBLING QUALITATIVE INQUIRY: ACCOUNTS AS DATA, AND AS PRODUCTS

What counts as a convincing scientific argument? Are the standards for such evaluation

An Intense Defence of Gadamer s Significance for Aesthetics

The topic of this Majors Seminar is Relativism how to formulate it, and how to evaluate arguments for and against it.

CRITIQUE OF PARSONS AND MERTON

Hypatia, Volume 21, Number 3, Summer 2006, pp (Review) DOI: /hyp For additional information about this article

Holliday Postmodernism

What Can Experimental Philosophy Do? David Chalmers

What is the Object of Thinking Differently?

PHILOSOPHY OF SOCIAL SCIENCE INTS 4522 Spring Jack Donnelly and Martin Rhodes -

These are some notes to give you some idea of the content of the lecture they are not exhaustive, nor always accurate! So read the referenced work.

Truth and Method in Unification Thought: A Preparatory Analysis

POST-KANTIAN AUTONOMIST AESTHETICS AS APPLIED ETHICS ETHICAL SUBSTRATUM OF PURIST LITERARY CRITICISM IN 20 TH CENTURY

Normative and Positive Economics

KEY ISSUES IN SOCIOLOGICAL THEORY Dept. of Sociology and Social Anthropology, CEU Autumn 2017

Action, Criticism & Theory for Music Education

VALUES AND VALUING [Adapted from Carl Mitcham, ed., Encyclopedia of Science, Technology, and Ethics (New York: Macmillan Reference, 2005).

Jacek Surzyn University of Silesia Kant s Political Philosophy

Social Mechanisms and Scientific Realism: Discussion of Mechanistic Explanation in Social Contexts Daniel Little, University of Michigan-Dearborn

Any attempt to revitalize the relationship between rhetoric and ethics is challenged

Bas C. van Fraassen, Scientific Representation: Paradoxes of Perspective, Oxford University Press, 2008.

Introduction to The Handbook of Economic Methodology

Lecture 3 Kuhn s Methodology

Ithaque : Revue de philosophie de l'université de Montréal

Postmodernism. thus one must review the central tenants of Enlightenment philosophy

observation and conceptual interpretation

CRITICAL CONTEXTUAL EMPIRICISM AND ITS IMPLICATIONS

Four Characteristic Research Paradigms

Are There Two Theories of Goodness in the Republic? A Response to Santas. Rachel Singpurwalla

Beauty, Work, Self. How Fashion Models Experience their Aesthetic Labor S.M. Holla

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at

Necessity in Kant; Subjective and Objective

Back to Basics: Appreciating Appreciative Inquiry as Not Normal Science

The Observer Story: Heinz von Foerster s Heritage. Siegfried J. Schmidt 1. Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2011

The Polish Peasant in Europe and America. W. I. Thomas and Florian Znaniecki

ARCHITECTURE AND EDUCATION: THE QUESTION OF EXPERTISE AND THE CHALLENGE OF ART

Introduction and Overview

Situated actions. Plans are represetitntiom of nction. Plans are representations of action

Published in: International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 29(2) (2015):

Visual Argumentation in Commercials: the Tulip Test 1


REFERENCES. 2004), that much of the recent literature in institutional theory adopts a realist position, pos-

FOUNDATIONS OF ACADEMIC WRITING. Graduate Research School Writing Seminar 5 th February Dr Michael Azariadis

Mixed Methods: In Search of a Paradigm

Edward Winters. Aesthetics and Architecture. London: Continuum, 2007, 179 pp. ISBN

The Shimer School Core Curriculum

Architecture is epistemologically

THE RELATIONS BETWEEN ETHICS AND ECONOMICS: A COMPARATIVE ANALYSIS BETWEEN AYRES AND WEBER S PERSPECTIVES. By Nuria Toledano and Crispen Karanda

FORUM: QUALITATIVE SOCIAL RESEARCH SOZIALFORSCHUNG

Introduction: Mills today

Brandom s Reconstructive Rationality. Some Pragmatist Themes

Why Intermediality if at all?

(as methodology) are not always distinguished by Steward: he says,

Conceptual Change, Relativism, and Rationality

Science and Values: Holism and Radical Environmental Activism

Mitchell ABOULAFIA, Transcendence. On selfdetermination

In retrospect: The Structure of Scientific Revolutions

HEGEL, ANALYTIC PHILOSOPHY AND THE RETURN OF METAPHYISCS Simon Lumsden

Post-positivism. Nick J Fox

Dabney Townsend. Hume s Aesthetic Theory: Taste and Sentiment Timothy M. Costelloe Hume Studies Volume XXVIII, Number 1 (April, 2002)

Guide to the Republic as it sets up Plato s discussion of education in the Allegory of the Cave.

PHI 3240: Philosophy of Art

Humanities Learning Outcomes

t< k '" a.-j w~lp4t..

Penultimate draft of a review which will appear in History and Philosophy of. $ ISBN: (hardback); ISBN:

Sidestepping the holes of holism

Moral Judgment and Emotions

Qualitative Design and Measurement Objectives 1. Describe five approaches to questions posed in qualitative research 2. Describe the relationship betw

Rorty, Dewey, and Incommensurability

WHAT S LEFT OF HUMAN NATURE? A POST-ESSENTIALIST, PLURALIST AND INTERACTIVE ACCOUNT OF A CONTESTED CONCEPT. Maria Kronfeldner

Vinod Lakshmipathy Phil 591- Hermeneutics Prof. Theodore Kisiel

COURSE SYLLABUS. 1. Information about the programme

Conclusion. One way of characterizing the project Kant undertakes in the Critique of Pure Reason is by

Notes on Gadamer, The Relevance of the Beautiful

Candlin, Fiona (2000) Practice-based doctorates and questions of academic legitimacy. International Journal of Art and Design Education 19 (1):

This is an electronic reprint of the original article. This reprint may differ from the original in pagination and typographic detail.

10/24/2016 RESEARCH METHODOLOGY Lecture 4: Research Paradigms Paradigm is E- mail Mobile

Caught in the Middle. Philosophy of Science Between the Historical Turn and Formal Philosophy as Illustrated by the Program of Kuhn Sneedified

ENVIRONMENTAL EXPERIENCE: Beyond Aesthetic Subjectivism and Objectivism

SUMMARY BOETHIUS AND THE PROBLEM OF UNIVERSALS

Introduction Theorising is used in this book to indicate the activity of trying to reach adequate conceptual terms for understanding media structures

[My method is] a science that studies the life of signs within society I shall call it semiology from the Greek semeion signs (Saussure)

scholars have imagined and dealt with religious people s imaginings and dealings

The Senses at first let in particular Ideas. (Essay Concerning Human Understanding I.II.15)

Interculturalism and Aesthetics: The Deconstruction of an Euro centric Myth. Research Paper. Susanne Schwinghammer-Kogler

Intention and Interpretation

Abstract of Graff: Taking Cover in Coverage. Graff, Gerald. "Taking Cover in Coverage." The Norton Anthology of Theory and

that would join theoretical philosophy (metaphysics) and practical philosophy (ethics)?

The Postmodern as a Presence

The Strengths and Weaknesses of Frege's Critique of Locke By Tony Walton

Critical Spatial Practice Jane Rendell

Media as practice. a brief exchange. Nick Couldry and Mark Hobart. Published as Chapter 3. Theorising Media and Practice

Challenging the View That Science is Value Free

A Comprehensive Critical Study of Gadamer s Hermeneutics

Uniting the Two Torn Halves High Culture and Popular Culture

foucault s archaeology science and transformation David Webb

Sociological theories: the tradition and current notions pt II

Tamar Sovran Scientific work 1. The study of meaning My work focuses on the study of meaning and meaning relations. I am interested in the duality of

Transcription:

Between Cabbages and Kings: Speaking Across Forms of Life Marcus Morgan, Cambridge University I would like to thank Leandro Rodriguez Medina for his generous and unexpected comments 1 on my article. 2 It s always a privilege to have someone read one s work carefully, and his review has served the added welcome end of drawing my attention to the Social Epistemology Review and Reply Collective. I am happy to learn that this initiative itself embodies a feature of knowledge production I tried to highlight in my article: its perennially evolving nature as a conversation amongst a community of enquirers. Imagination and Social Science In order to avoid the risk of agreeing too much, the majority of my response here will focus upon Rodriguez Medina s more critical comments, mainly in relation to the canon, and the possibility of dialogue across potentially incommensurable forms of life. First, however, a brief note of strong agreement. Rodriguez Medina raises the centrality of imagination to quality social science. With this, I really couldn t agree more. I am proud to practise a discipline whose unofficial manifesto to potential new recruits is so often Mills s classic The Sociological Imagination. 3 Mills chose the title for his book carefully, and expressed his unease with the term social science, since, as he wrote, the word science has acquired great prestige and rather imprecise meaning and he did not feel any need to kidnap the prestige or to make the meaning even less precise by using it as a philosophical metaphor. 4 Foregrounding the importance of imagination is not merely useful as a proselytising tool, it also allows for a reflexive awareness of the subjectivity that inevitably goes into creating sociological knowledge, combined with a recognition that such knowledge is none the poorer for that fact. The creative impulse that drove the founding of institutionalised sociology in the nineteenth century no doubt derived from its dream of science. However, to maintain its scientific credentials these days, we must either expand the notion of science beyond the capacity for language to maintain a usefully stable connotative function (the looser German term Wissenschaft might pose fewer problems), or else commit ourselves to the uneasy claim that the majority of activity carried out under the banner of sociology is in fact not really sociology at all. To insist upon their inherent connection, it seems that one of the terms science or sociology has to give. In many ways this debate has in fact long been settled, and I doubt any social scientist (even an economist) would nowadays feel comfortable locating him or herself in the unlikely image that Hobbes painted in the Leviathan, wherein the social sciences were to constitute a sub-branch of physics. This is not to say that the natural sciences do not provide a potentially useful model for disciplines like sociology, for certain ends they surely do and to deny the central role of systematic empiricism within the social sciences would be foolish. However, social scientific knowledge can in no simplistic 1 Rodriguez Medina 2016. 2 Morgan 2016a. 3 C. Wright Mills 1959. 4 Ibid., 18n2. 24

way be understood as determined by empiricism. All sorts of non-empirical and a priori inputs go into shaping empirical perceptions of the world, and there can be no theory-independent observational language with which to describe that world. Empiricism usually involves seeing as rather than simply seeing that, 5 and this holds true for the natural sciences too, even if under conditions of normal science such non-empirical inputs are typically well concealed by their taken-for-granted nature. The model provided by natural science has also been revealed by historians, ethnographers, and philosophers of science not to be the singular unified approach that it was once presumed to be, and nor is it the only model on offer. Such things as literature, history, social activism, art, linguistics, even punk 6 have all proven their utility as inspirations for studying society effectively and imaginatively. Much of my defence of sociology as a specifically humanistic discipline elsewhere 7 is intended to reassert its debts to, and resonances with, the collection of disciplines usually grouped together under the humanities, as much as its connections with the empirical sciences. Rodriguez Medina suggests that acknowledging that notions of knowledge verification need to be situated in forms of life implies the need for reform in sociological education: the very idea of the canon, which still informs many, if not all, textbooks in the disciplines tends to overestimate some forms of life at the expense of others. 8 This is certainly true, though as long as we insist on certain conditions of knowledge production, I m not sure I see the continuing presence of a canon as necessarily pernicious. This is firstly for fairly mundane and functional reasons, such as the practical purposes that a canon serves in providing an historical anchor and organising discourse in an otherwise relatively amorphous and intellectually promiscuous discipline. Sociology is a broad and internally-dissenting church indeed, but its admirable openness is won at the risk of a potential loss of intellectual coherence. Being able to refer to Durkheim or Simmel, or figures who are slowly being pushed from the margins to the centre of the canon such as Du Bois or Martineau, allows for the otherwise highly unlikely feat that a sociologist researching the effects of economic liberalisation on homelessness might engage in a meaningful sociological conversation with one researching the social life of test-tubes. Paradoxically, limiting the number of books or authors we take as sacred can encourage a greater degree of open engagement across the discipline and provoke encounters that otherwise might not occur. The fewer the number of canonical bridges linking the various research sites, the more likely meetings are to take place on such crossings. These encounters, and the conversations that spring from them, may themselves form the basis for canon reform. Beyond these functional purposes of the canon, there are also normally good, albeit debatable, inherent reasons why certain works become sacralised. Such works typically contain a higher-than-usual degree of intrinsic intellectual merit, if one is 5 Norwood Russell Hanson 1958. 6 David Beer 2014. 7 Morgan 2016b, Ch. 4. 8 Rodriguez Medina 2016, op. cit., 68. 25

able to talk of such a thing in a sociology of knowledge context. How to identify and measure this merit is of course contentious territory. One potential identifier is that really good books (the few that deserve to be considered for canonical status) are almost always productive grist for the hermeneutic mill, and classics ought only justly become such if they are capable of sparking original and useful re-readings and reinterpretations in the present. The best texts seem to share this capacity for provoking fresh ideas in each new generation of readers. Once they cease to do this (unless they are to continue to serve as what Kuhn calls exemplars ), I agree that they should indeed make way for others. This is not to say that the insularity of a canon and barriers to access are not dangers, nor to deny as the recent movements around decolonising education have made clear that questions about the content of the canon are always political questions too, and especially so since they hold effects on how neophytes are to be socialised and therefore how the discipline is likely to reproduce itself. The insistence on certain conditions of knowledge production that I referred to above must certainly include mechanisms for open contestability in terms of which works are to be included and, when the time is right, excluded from the canon. This is a matter on which bright, well-read, and often politicised students are frequently one step ahead of overworked faculty, who are themselves invested in avoiding the extra labour that inevitably comes with periodically revising curricula. On Indigenous Knowledge Quoting from Harding s new book, 9 Rodriguez Medina raises the question of indigenous knowledge, and what I understand to be the issue of the demand for reincorporating the excluded and the peripheral, and questioning the universality of the conceptual apparatus developed in the core. In terms of sociology, not only was much of the classical canon constituted in reference to the oriental or colonial other, 10 but so too was the very conception of modernity that it took as its primary object of study. 11 I am therefore in agreement that other ways of knowing (historically, as well as culturally) ought to be put in conversation with our own accounts of knowledge, and the humanities and social sciences seem to me to have led the way in achieving this. Another interesting and related question is how European and North American thought has been transformed in the process of its reception in other areas of the world, a field Rodriguez Medina has himself contributed to, 12 and which I am currently exploring through the case of Black Consciousness in South Africa. However, it should also be remembered that attacks on the idea of the sociological canon have not only come from those at work in upsetting claims to epistemic universality and pushing for a reconsideration of the place of the marginal within the centre. Critique of the value of a sociological canon has also come from the centre itself, in the form of sociologists concerned with defending a more strictly scientific conception of the discipline. This was especially so in post-war America, when it was suggested that the history of social thought must not get muddled up with the primary 9 Sandra Harding 2015. 10 Craig Calhoun 1996. 11 Gurminder Bhambra 2007. 12 Rodriguez Medina 2014. 26

task of building a unified systemic body of sociological theory. Past sociological insight, in this critique, was relevant to present research concerns only to the extent that its claims had been empirically verified, and so could be incorporated into contemporary social models. After all, wrote Merton, schools of medicine do not confuse the history of medicine with current medical practice, nor do departments of biology identify the history of biology with the viable theory now employed in guiding and interpreting biological research. 13 Merton s choice of analogues is telling, and it should hopefully be clear that my own views diverge from these, and again, mainly because I see characteristics usually associated with the humanities and in particular the claim that there is never simply a single use for knowledge and therefore never a single way of judging it as central to sociological knowledge development. On a slightly different issue, but again taking his impulse from Harding, Rodriguez Medina writes that Perhaps one of the few shortcomings of Morgan s text is a lack of reflection about the possible dialogue between forms of life, between different truths, between epistemic communities whose knowledge has actually affected their way of relating to the world he does not seem to be sensitive to situations, in practical everyday life, in which those who use truth in one way have to communicate with those who use it in a different or contradictory way. 14 This issue of communicating across different forms of life comes to the fore most prominently with the intensification of globalisation processes, and it takes on normative stakes since value judgements infuse epistemic communities and often define their borders. In addition, epistemic communities hardly ever possess explicit and formally developed propositional accounts of the particular theory of truth they subscribe to. For both of these reasons, the debate around the philosophy of the social sciences is pushed towards a debate around ethnocentrism (and on a more speculative reading, anthropocentrism too). This is also an area where my own views depart radically from the complacent ethnocentrism (or anti-anti-ethnocentrism ) of Rorty. 15 On this matter I think Geertz was right in both an epistemological and a moral sense to warn against the attractions of deafness to the appeal of other values and of a relax-and-enjoy-it approach to one s imprisonment in one s own cultural tradition. 16 He was also correct in drawing our attention to the problematic assumption of consensus within communities. As he put it, foreignness does not start at the water s edge, but at the skin s, 17 and although Geertz grants Wittgenstein the benefit of the doubt, it was in part on this point about the internal coherence, isolation, and stability of communities on which Gellner famously took issue with Wittgenstein and his devotees. 18 13 Robert K. Merton 1949, 4. 14 Rodriguez Medina 2016, op. cit., 69. 15 Richard Rorty 1991, 203-210. 16 Clifford Geertz 1986, 257. 17 Geertz 1986, op. cit., 261. 18 Ernest Gellner 1959. 27

In this way, Geertz s, as opposed to Rorty s interpretation of forms of life seems far more adequate to me (whether or not it is in fact a more accurate reflection of what Wittgenstein himself actually meant). Rather than taking the notion that thought and judgement are located in a form of life as meaning that the limits of my world are the limits of my language, Geertz instead reminds us that what Wittgenstein in fact said was that, the limits of my language are the limits of my world, which implies not that the reach of our minds, of what we say, think, appreciate, and judge, is trapped within the borders of our society, our country, our class, or our time, but that the reach of our minds, the range of signs we can manage somehow to interpret, is what defines the intellectual, emotional, and moral space within which we live. 19 On this reading, ground is cleared not only for communication, but also for learning, and indeed doing so from forms of knowledge we might impulsively find absurd or repugnant. Rather than recoiling from such knowledge, what Gadamer termed a fusion of horizons is instead placed back on the agenda. Cultural diversity, including alternative notions of truth, is understood in Bernard Williams s phrase as providing not merely alternatives to us, but also potential alternatives for us. 20 Even where communities are not imbricated, they are seen as at least having windows in Geertz s vision, and humans are understood as capable of translation, interpretation, and of defining the terrain reason must cross if its modest rewards are to be reached and realised. 21 Conclusion Whilst not wishing to abandon the term, Harding s new book draws out the irony and confusion that stems from the fact that appeals to the epistemic norm of objectivity so often lack the thing they claim themselves to have. Values, she stresses, are at the centre of most of what we do, in science as elsewhere, and there is no ultimate way of surgically excising them from our activity. In many ways her appeal to the notion of strong objectivity from below is in fact congruent with two arguments I have supported elsewhere. These are, firstly, that the kinds of truths generated by the social sciences tend to exhibit characteristics of what James Clifford called partial truths, 22 in the sense of being both committed and incomplete. 23 This partiality again in both senses of the term derives from our simultaneously limited and privileged location within the world, as well as our interests, which in the process of developing more adequate research methodologies Harding and others have called a standpoint. Secondly, that the production of social knowledge ought never be separated from the development of grounded forms of social hope, aimed ultimately towards the 19 Geertz 1986, op. cit., 263. 20 Geertz 1986, op. cit., 260. 21 Geertz 1986, op. cit., 270. 22 James Clifford 1986. 23 Morgan 2016b, op. cit. 28

contestable ends of social justice, and especially so since the social sciences are performative in their effects. 24 Admittedly, as Rodriguez Medina correctly points out, these are somewhat grand pursuits, especially once foundationalism has been abandoned, much easier to give lip service to than consistently follow. They might also, however, be conceived as pragmatic orientation devices, and I am sure Medina would agree that the promise of sociology is better served by faltering towards valuable goals, than by consistently meeting less worthy ones. Contact details: mm2014@cam.ac.uk References Beer, David. Punk Sociology. London: Palgrave Macmillan, 2014. Bhambra, Gurminder. Rethinking Modernity: Postcolonialism and the Sociological Imagination. London: Palgrave Macmillan, 2007. Calhoun, Craig. Whose Classics? Which Readings?: Interpretation and Cultural Difference in the Canonization of Sociological Theory. In Social Theory and Sociology: The Classics and Beyond, edited by Stephen P. Turner, 70-96. Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell, 1996. Clifford, James. Partial Truths. In Writing Culture: The Poetics and Politics of Ethnography, edited by James Clifford and George E. Marcus, 1-26. London: University of California Press, 1986. Geertz, Clifford. The Uses of Diversity. In The Tanner Lecture on Human Values Delivered at the University of Michigan Nov 8 th, 1985, 251-275. Cambridge University Press and University of Utah Press, 1986. Gellner, Ernest. Words & Things. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1959. Hanson, Norwood Russell. Patterns of Discovery. An Inquiry Into the Conceptual Foundations of Science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1958. Harding, Sandra. Objectivity and Diversity. Another Logic of Scientific Research. Chicago and London: University of Chicago Press, 2015. Merton, Robert K. On the History and Systematics of Sociological Theory. In Social Theory and Social Structure, edited by Robert K. Merton, 1-39. New York: The Free Press, 1949. Mills, C. Wright. The Sociological Imagination. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1959. Morgan, Marcus. Humanising Sociological Knowledge. Social Epistemology (2016a). doi: 10.1080/02691728.2015.1119911. Morgan, Marcus. Pragmatic Humanism: On the Nature and Value of Sociological Knowledge. Abingdon, Oxon: Routledge, 2016b. Morgan, Marcus. The Responsibility for Social Hope. Thesis Eleven (2016c). doi: 10.1177/0725513616647574. Rodriguez Medina, Leandro. The Circulation of European Knowledge: Niklas Luhmann in the Hispanic Americas. London: Palgrave Macmillan, 2014. Rodriguez Medina, Leandro. From Humanising to Politicizing Sociological Knowledge. Social Epistemology Review and Reply Collective 5, no. 4 (2016): 67-70. Rorty, Richard. On Ethnocentrism, in Objectivity, Relativism, and Truth: Philosophical Papers. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991, 203-10. 24 Marcus Morgan 2016c. 29