Trope Theory, Resemblance, and Russell's Regress

Similar documents
Tropes and the Semantics of Adjectives

Varieties of Nominalism Predicate Nominalism The Nature of Classes Class Membership Determines Type Testing For Adequacy

This paper is a near-exact replica of that which appeared in S. Laurence and C. Macdonald

Resemblance Nominalism: A Solution to the Problem of Universals. GONZALO RODRIGUEZ-PEREYRA. Oxford: Clarendon Press, Pp. xii, 238.

Naïve realism without disjunctivism about experience

Instantiation and Characterization: Problems in Lowe s Four-Category Ontology

Why Realists Need Tropes

Resemblance Nominalism: A Solution to the Problem of Universals

Reply to Stalnaker. Timothy Williamson. In Models and Reality, Robert Stalnaker responds to the tensions discerned in Modal Logic

What is Character? David Braun. University of Rochester. In "Demonstratives", David Kaplan argues that indexicals and other expressions have a

Bennett on Parts Twice Over

What do our appreciation of tonal music and tea roses, our acquisition of the concepts

Social Mechanisms and Scientific Realism: Discussion of Mechanistic Explanation in Social Contexts Daniel Little, University of Michigan-Dearborn

Truth and Tropes. by Keith Lehrer and Joseph Tolliver

Degree structure as trope structure: a trope-based analysis of positive and comparative adjectives

PURE REALISM: PLATONISM AS A SERIOUS CONTEMPORARY ALTERNATIVE. Keywords: pure realism, Platonism, metaphysics, natures

AESTHETIC SUPERVENIENCE VS AESTHETIC GROUNDING

On Meaning. language to establish several definitions. We then examine the theories of meaning

Scientific Philosophy

Intensional Relative Clauses and the Semantics of Variable Objects

Mind Association. Oxford University Press and Mind Association are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Mind.

Questions of Ontology

Perception and Mind-Dependence Lecture 3

Universals. Some Existence Arguments

On the Analogy between Cognitive Representation and Truth

1. What is Phenomenology?

Hume on Spatial Properties

Replies to the Critics

PLEASE SCROLL DOWN FOR ARTICLE

Bas C. van Fraassen, Scientific Representation: Paradoxes of Perspective, Oxford University Press, 2008.

On Recanati s Mental Files

What Can Experimental Philosophy Do? David Chalmers

Immanuel Kant, the author of the Copernican revolution in philosophy,

Substance, Nature, and Immanence Form in Aristotle s Constituent Ontology

WHITEHEAD'S PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE AND METAPHYSICS

From Brian Leiter and Michael Rosen (eds), The Oxford Handbook of Continental Philosophy (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2007), pp.

Watching Anna knit, it s clear that the scarf she s making and the yarn

CONTINGENCY AND TIME. Gal YEHEZKEL

WHAT IS WRONG WITH THE RELATIONAL THEORY OF CHANGE? Gonzalo Rodriguez-Pereyra Hertford College, Oxford

Ridgeview Publishing Company

IN DEFENSE OF ESSENTIALISM 1. L. A. Paul University of Arizona Australian National University/RSSS

A Notion of Logical Concept based on Plural Reference

7AAN2056: Philosophy of Mathematics Syllabus Academic year 2016/17

Comments on Dumont, Intension and Remission of Forms. Robert Pasnau

Types of perceptual content

Forms and Causality in the Phaedo. Michael Wiitala

Articulating Medieval Logic, by Terence Parsons. Oxford: Oxford University Press,

Working BO1 BUSINESS ONTOLOGY: OVERVIEW BUSINESS ONTOLOGY - SOME CORE CONCEPTS. B usiness Object R eference Ontology. Program. s i m p l i f y i n g

INTERNATIONAL CONFERENCE ON ENGINEERING DESIGN ICED 05 MELBOURNE, AUGUST 15-18, 2005 GENERAL DESIGN THEORY AND GENETIC EPISTEMOLOGY

6 Bodily Sensations as an Obstacle for Representationism

Chudnoff on the Awareness of Abstract Objects 1

COGNITION AND IDENTIFYING REFERENCE. Gary Rosenkrantz

I. INTRODUCING STORIES

Composition, Counterfactuals, Causation

Philosophy of Mind and Metaphysics Lecture III: Qualitative Change and the Doctrine of Temporal Parts

THE PROBLEM OF UNIVERSALS IN CONTEMPORARY PHILOSOPHY

A Puzzle about Hume s Theory of General Representation. According to Hume s theory of general representation, we represent generalities by

Mind Association. Oxford University Press and Mind Association are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Mind.

Simplicity, Its Failures And a Naturalistic Rescue?

SNP Best-set Typesetter Ltd. Article No.: 583 Delivery Date: 31 October 2005 Page Extent: 4 pp

A Note on Analysis and Circular Definitions

The Introduction of Universals

PHD THESIS SUMMARY: Phenomenology and economics PETR ŠPECIÁN

Verity Harte Plato on Parts and Wholes Clarendon Press, Oxford 2002

In Defense of the Contingently Nonconcrete

Hume Studies Volume XXIV, Number 1 (April, 1998)

Vagueness & Pragmatics

Instantiation in Trope Theory (A.R.J. Fisher, University of Manchester)

The red apple I am eating is sweet and juicy. LOCKE S EMPIRICAL THEORY OF COGNITION: THE THEORY OF IDEAS. Locke s way of ideas

A New Approach to the Paradox of Fiction Pete Faulconbridge

The ambiguity of definite descriptions

Are There Two Theories of Goodness in the Republic? A Response to Santas. Rachel Singpurwalla

The Nature of Time. Humberto R. Maturana. November 27, 1995.

All Roads Lead to Violations of Countable Additivity

STUDENTS EXPERIENCES OF EQUIVALENCE RELATIONS

PAUL REDDING S CONTINENTAL IDEALISM (AND DELEUZE S CONTINUATION OF THE IDEALIST TRADITION) Sean Bowden

Background to Gottlob Frege

A Higher-order, Dispositional Theory of Qualia. John O Dea. Abstract

Phenomenology and Non-Conceptual Content

Z.13: Substances and Universals

KINDS (NATURAL KINDS VS. HUMAN KINDS)

Properties and Resemblance Classes

A Confusion of the term Subjectivity in the philosophy of Mind *

Carlo Martini 2009_07_23. Summary of: Robert Sugden - Credible Worlds: the Status of Theoretical Models in Economics 1.

Kuhn Formalized. Christian Damböck Institute Vienna Circle University of Vienna

MONOTONE AMAZEMENT RICK NOUWEN

RESEMBLANCE IN DAVID HUME S TREATISE Ezio Di Nucci

HEGEL, ANALYTIC PHILOSOPHY AND THE RETURN OF METAPHYISCS Simon Lumsden

Chapter 9 Truth as Composite Correspondence

By Tetsushi Hirano. PHENOMENOLOGY at the University College of Dublin on June 21 st 2013)

Logic and Philosophy of Science (LPS)

Penultimate Draft- Final version forthcoming in Philosophical Psychology

Philosophy 405: Knowledge, Truth and Mathematics Spring Russell Marcus Hamilton College

The Epistemological Status of Theoretical Simplicity YINETH SANCHEZ

I n t r o d u c t i o n t o a n d C o m m e n t a r y o n J e n n i f e r H o r n s b y s Truth: The Identity Theory GILA SHER

Tolkien and Phenomenology: On the concepts of recovery and epoché

NINO B. COCCHIARELLA LOGIC AND ONTOLOGY

Riccardo Chiaradonna, Gabriele Galluzzo (eds.), Universals in Ancient Philosophy, Edizioni della Normale, 2013, pp. 546, 29.75, ISBN

Two Ways to Particularize a Property

The Constitution Theory of Intention-Dependent Objects and the Problem of Ontological Relativism

Transcription:

Trope Theory, Resemblance, and Russell's Regress Florian Boge 12.07.2012

Structure Introduction what are tropes? Nominalism about universals Bundle theory A refinement: nucleus theory Similarity relations A trope theoretical measure for relative resemblance The resemblance regress a fundamental problem for trope theory Is it vicious? Similarity as internal A cognitivist approach as a possible solution Perfect resemblance defined

What are tropes? Definition: Tropes are the particular properties (property instances) of a given concrete entity (cf. Campbell 1990, 18). They are abstract particulars. Relatons = polyadic tropes Qualitons = monadic tropes (cf. Bacon 2008, 2) An entity is called abstract (in this context) iff. it is a part of some other entity, which can only be separated in thought (cf. Rojek 2008, 361). Particulars (indviduals) = entities which only exist in one place at one time (interval) Spacio-temproal location as an important criterion for individuality according to trope theory: [O]ur abstract particulars are particulars because they have a local habitation, even if no name. They exist as individuals at unique placetimes. (Campbell 1990, 3)

What are tropes? Examples: The particular shape of a given chair Bill Clinton s eloquence This redness, in contrast to redness in general Supposed to provide an alternative to realism about universals Trope theory is a form of nominalism about universals Needs to explain our use of general terms Should be able to explain every day life s entities such as things, their appearance, their relations etc.

Nominalism about universals Nominalism about universals = attempt to provide an explanation of general terms (i.e. terms for types, properties, relations etc.) without appeal to universals Universals = entities that are multiply exemplified i.e. exist in more than one place at the same time Different kinds of nominalism: Predicate nominalism: different entities just fall under the same predicate (cf. Armstrong 1978,13) highly unsatisfactory Class nominalism: different entities are part of the same class; the predicate refers to the whole class Faces some great difficulties, e. g. coextension problem ( cordate and renate ), aggregate problem (aggregate of soldiers = aggregate of armies) Resemblance nominalism: different entities resemble each other and constitute resemblance classes (which are the denotation of a predicate) Most promising, but also has to face the coextension problem (cf. Schurz 1995, 100)

Nominalism about universals Trope theory as a form of resemblance nominalism which ipso facto solves some of the problems of classical similarity nominalism: No coextension problem; class of resembling F-tropes distinct (even disjunct) from the class of resembling G-tropes, even if all F- and G- tropes always occur in the same classical individuals Makes it easier to define relative resemblance of classical individuals (resemblance w.r.t. one property instead of overall resemblance) and degrees of resemblance in virtue of perfectly resembling tropes (definition will be given later)

Bundle theory Classical individuals = concrete entities we encounter in everyday life, things How can trope theory account for those? One classical, intuitive approach: substrata, bare particulars, that bear tropes Difficulties: Ontological extra (dispensable) Relation of bearing must be second order trope that needs explanation: how can tropeless substratum have the property (trope) of being a bearer? (Cf. Simons 1994, 567) Alternative: bundle theory Tropes (always -?) appear in bundles Tropes in a bundle are compresent Several tropes are compresent at a time (interval) iff. they occupy the same space at that time (interval) (cf. Russell 1948, 260) Can also be interpreted to introduce a cognitive dimension; several tropes are percieved as one complex

A refinement: nucleus theory Problem: how can bundle theory account for the distinction between essential and accidental properties (i.e. tropes)? Solution: There is a nucleus of tropes in every bundle, where any trope of the nucleus cannot exist without any of the other tropes (cf. Simons 1994, 567). One sided dependence of accidental tropes on the existence of the nucleus Phenomenological conception of essential and accidental (cf. Gallagher and Zahavi 2008, 27). Alternative interpretation: Some tropes are essentially compresent: basic tropes (tropes that constitute the basic physical entities). The tropes of several nuclei can be accidentally compresent (constitute bigger entities together) and create supervenient tropes; introduce degrees of compresence. Many Relatons may be defined in terms of compresence (degree of compresence, change in the degree of compresence ) Less anthropocentric

Similarity relations General properties are taken to be resemblance classes of tropes what is resemblance? Resemblance is a similarity relation. Technical definition: A similarity relation is a symmetric and reflexive relation: x y(sxy Syx) x(sxx) (cf. Bacon 2008, 4) Resemblance as the nominalistic pendant to qualitative identity (having the same property) Perfect resemblance is the highest degree of resemblance; it is, arguably, also transitive: x y z(rxy Ryz Rxz) Perfect resemblance, thus, is an equivalence relation, which induces a partition on a given Domain D. Relative resemblance of classical individuals can be modeled in terms of perfectly resembling basic tropes; a measure for resemblance in some respect can be defined. Compresence can logically be taken to be a similarity relation (similarity w.r.t. spacio-temporal location).

A trope theoretical measure for relative resemblance Motivation: [A]n orangeness trope might be like the color of a given tomato, which in turn was like a bunch of redness tropes. The tomato s color might be both an orangeness and a redness. Yet the orangeness trope might not be like any of the other redness tropes. I see no compelling reason to exclude such possibilities a priori. (Bacon 1995, 15) Argument for the non-transitivity of resemblance plausible? Can be resolved by introducing degrees of similarity (resemblance); take resemblance in general to be fuzzy: [A] similarity relation, S, is a fuzzy relation which is reflexive, symmetric, and transitive. Thus, let x, y be elements of a set X and s (x, y) denote the grade of membership of the ordered pair (x, y) in S. Then S is a similarity relation in X if and only if, for all x, y, z in X, s (x, x) = 1 (reflexivity), s (x, y) = s (y, x) (symmetry), and s (x, z) y ( s (x, y) s (y, z)) (transitivity), where and denote max and min, respectively. (Zadeh 1971, 177) We need y because is a real-valued function into the closed interval [0,1].

A trope theoretical measure for relative resemblance If we assume that the tropes of classical individuals supervene on the basic tropes, we can define the following measure for (relative) resemblance: Let x, y be variables for the elements of the set I of classical individuals and F any relation of relative resemblance on I (e.g. color resemblance). Further, let B be the set of basic tropes and t i, t j, with i, j IN, be variables for the elements of B. Let T(x) be the set of basic tropes compresent in x, i.e. t1,t2 T(x): Kt 1 t 2, where K is the relation of compresence on B. Let N = {<t i, t j > B F ² : t i T(x), t j T(y)} where B F B is the set of basic F-tropes (the set of basic tropes on which the relata of F e.g. color-tropes supervene). Let P be the relation of perfect resemblance on B F. Then: F (x, y) = {<t i, t j > P: t i T(x) B F and t j T(y) B F } / N Relates the idea of degrees of resemblance to trope theory Reduces the need for a general definition of resemblance to the need for a definition of perfect resemblance Bears some explanatory value for the question of how degrees of resemblance come into existence

The resemblance regress Resemblance relations must either consist relatons (particular resemblances; 2nd order tropes) or the universal of resemblance must be accepted. Problem: If we accept a universal at the basis of our ontology, trope theory does not give us a complete form of nominalism. However, if we take resemblances themselves to be individuals, the regress problem arises: Let r 1 be the particular resemblance between two tropes a and b and r 2 the particular resemblance between two tropes c and d Now, for the r 1 and r 2 both to be resemblances, there must be another, higher order trope r 1,2 which makes them both resemblances (since this is our criterion for membership in a resemblance class). Let, in general, r i,j be the resemblance between two resemblances r i and r j For any two r i,j and r k,n, we now need a r (i,j),(k,n) for them to be resemblances and so forth for any two higher order resemblances, ad infinitum.

Is it vicious? Some philosophers have argued, that there are virtuous regresses, e.g.: The truth regress (resulting from the substitution of the truth conditions of a true sentence into Tarskis T-scheme) The regress of successor numbers, resulting from the axioms of peano arithmetic (cf. Nolan 2001, 523-524) The regress of resemblances could be such a regress (cf. Campbell 1990, 35 ff.) Campbell: more formality and less substance on every level what does that even mean? Daly (1994, 256-257): applies to any regress. We need a better argument.

Resemblance as internal Some philosophers have argued that resemblance is an internal relation (cf. Armstrong 1989, pp. 43), i.e.: Given the existence two resembling entities (tropes) a and b, they must resemble one another (they resemble one another in every possible world, in which they exist). Tropes necessitate their resemblance Resemblance supervenes on tropes Question: Is resemblance ontologically reducible to the resembling entities? (cf. Armstrong 1989, 56) Problem: If r a,b is the resemblance of a and b and it is nothing besides a and b then it should hold that r a,b = a and r a,b = b. But then a = b. (cf. Schurz 1995, 102)

A cognitivist approach as a possible solution Prima facie it seems plausible to relativize resemblance to epistemic agents or cognitive systems. Resemblance then becomes a three-place relation: x,y(rxy SRxyS) where S $, $={x x is a cognitive system} and RxyS is the three-place predicate x resembles y for S. Plausible modification: x,y(rxy M R RxyM R ) where M R $ The resemblance of some a and b has to be understood as an associative impression that arises in (some set of) cognitive systems after percieving a and b. Two follow-up problems: a. In virtue of what are a and b associated by the set of cognitive systems? b. The regress still holds: associations would have to be analyzed as associations because we associate one association process with another one

A cognitivist approach as a possible solution To a.: To b.: It seems plausible to still conceive of resemblance as an internal relation in some sense. But now that means that for every possible world in which cognitive systems satisfy some conditions (the same ones as they supposedly do in our world), they automatically associate certain entities. Cognitive systems do so in virtue of the way a and b act on them. A nominalistic theory of causality is needed for this approach. If the regress actually occurred, that would mean an infinitely complex cognitive system, e.g. an infinitely complex brain (!) since associations could be interpreted as connections of stimulated neurons (cf. Bear, Connors, and Paradiso 2009, 372). This seems implausible. No brain or other finite cognitive system would ever associate associations ad infinitum. The regress hardly ever occurs because it is only a dispositional one, i.e.: if we were to reflect on the act of association, we would associate the particular acts of association with one another.

A cognitivist approach as a possible solution The regress always stops at some order of association and is (usually) replaced by an inductive generalization ( and so forth ). It is plausible to assume that an inductive generalization is a different kind of neuronal (or other material) process. There is no infinite regress, just a dispositional finite regress; this may be seen as an argument for the virtuousness of the regress of resemblances. Investment: A somewhat Kantian metaphysics A nominalistic theory of certain causal terms

Perfect resemblance defined Definition now has to involve: a. Relativization to (a) cognitive system(s) b. All possible worlds in which cognitive systems have the same perceptive and cognitive capabilities as they do in our world (no transcendent means of identification ) c. Action of the tropes on the system(s) at some place and time We could take perfect resemblance to mean that there would be no difference in a cognitive system (e.g. the cognition-relevant parts of a brain), if the space-time coordinates of two perfectly resembling tropes were swapped.

Perfect resemblance defined Let W be the set of all possible worlds, w 0 W our world (or some world that satisfies the same conditions for cognitive systems), W = {w n W all S w n satisfy the same conditions as all S w 0 }, where S $. Then our definition would have to look something like this: Two tropes a and b perfectly resemble one another iff in every possible world w 1 which is identical to some w 2 up to some point in time, t 2 t 1, except that in w 1 a acts on some S $ in t 1, s 1 and b acts on (the same) S in t 2, s 2, whereas in w 2 b acts on S in t 1, s 1 and a acts on S in t 2, s 2, the states of S in w 1 and w 2 until, and immediately after t 2 are identical (where s 1 s 2 ).

Perfect resemblance defined This leaves us with the following questions: 1. How should possible worlds be understood nominalistically? 2. What does identical mean in this context? 3. What would a nominalistic theory of causality (and dispositions) look like? Formalist apporach to questions 1 and 2 (possible worlds as something like sets of propositions, identity as numerical identity); 3 is an open end

References Armstrong, D. M. 1978. Nominalsim and Realism: Universals and Scientific Realism Volume I. London: Cambridge University Press. Armstrong, D. M. 1989. Universals: An Opinionated Introduction. Boulder: Westview Press. Bacon, John. 1995. Universals and property instances: The alphabet of being. Cambridge: Blackwell. Bacon, John. 2008. Tropes, in: Metaphysics Research Lab, CSLI [eds.], Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Online-URL: http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/tropes/ (Stand: 09.06.2011). Bear, Mark, Connors, Barry and Paradiso, Michael. 2009. Neurowissenschaften. Heidelberg: Spektrum. Campbell, Keith. 1990. Abstract Particulars. Oxford: Blackwell Publishing. Daly, Chris. 1994. Tropes, in: Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, New Series, Vol. 94, 253-261. Gallagher, Shaun und Zahavi, Dan. 2008. The Phenomenological Mind: An Introduction to Philosophy of Mind and Cognitive Science. London: Routledge.

References Nolan, Daniel. 2001. What is wrong with infinite regresses?, in: Metaphilosophy, Vol. 32, No. 5, 523-538. Rojek, Pawel. 2008. Three Trope Theories, in: Axiomathes, Vol. 18, No. 3, 359-377. Russell, Bertrand. 2009 [1948]. Human Knowledge: Its Scope and Limits. Taylor & Francis. Schurz, Gerhard. 1995. Ein quantenmechanisches Argument für die Existenz konkreter Universalien, in: Brandl, J., Hieke, A. und Simons, P. [eds.]: Metaphysik. Neue Zugänge zu alten Fragen. Sankt Augustin: Academia Verlag. Simons, Peter. 1994. Particulars in Particular Clothing: Three Trope Theories of Substance, in: Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, Vol. 54, No. 3, 553-575.

Thank you for your time and attention!