Cazeaux, C. (2011). Introduction to Immanuel Kant, in C. Cazeaux (ed.), The Continental Aesthetics Reader, 2nd edition, Abingdon: Routledge, 3 9.

Similar documents
None DEREE COLLEGE SYLLABUS FOR: PH 4028 KANT AND GERMAN IDEALISM UK LEVEL 6 UK CREDITS: 15 US CREDITS: 3/0/3. (Updated SPRING 2016) PREREQUISITES:

ANALOGY, SCHEMATISM AND THE EXISTENCE OF GOD

Kant: Notes on the Critique of Judgment

that would join theoretical philosophy (metaphysics) and practical philosophy (ethics)?

Conclusion. One way of characterizing the project Kant undertakes in the Critique of Pure Reason is by

Kant s Critique of Judgment

Kant and metaphor in contemporary aesthetics Clive Cazeaux

Kant's Aesthetics and Teleology

index 417 Fricke, Christel, 365, 372, 375,

What do our appreciation of tonal music and tea roses, our acquisition of the concepts

Immanuel Kant s Theory of Knowledge: Exploring the Relation between Sensibility and Understanding Wendell Allan Marinay

HEGEL, ANALYTIC PHILOSOPHY AND THE RETURN OF METAPHYISCS Simon Lumsden

Necessity in Kant; Subjective and Objective

KANT S TRANSCENDENTAL LOGIC

Syllabus Fall 2017! PHIL721 Advanced Seminar in Philosophy:! Kant s Critique of Judgment!

Philosophical Background to 19 th Century Modernism

Immanuel Kant, the author of the Copernican revolution in philosophy,

Rethinking the Aesthetic Experience: Kant s Subjective Universality

1/8. The Third Paralogism and the Transcendental Unity of Apperception

REVIEW ARTICLE IDEAL EMBODIMENT: KANT S THEORY OF SENSIBILITY

The Senses at first let in particular Ideas. (Essay Concerning Human Understanding I.II.15)

Human Finitude and the Dialectics of Experience

1/10. The A-Deduction

What is the Object of Thinking Differently?

Jacek Surzyn University of Silesia Kant s Political Philosophy

From Individuality to Universality: The Role of Aesthetic Education in Kant

1/9. The B-Deduction

Subjective Universality in Kant s Aesthetics Wilson

Aesthetics and Cognition in Kant s Critical Philosophy

UNIT SPECIFICATION FOR EXCHANGE AND STUDY ABROAD

Categories and Schemata

1/6. The Anticipations of Perception

Notes on Gadamer, The Relevance of the Beautiful

The Pure Concepts of the Understanding and Synthetic A Priori Cognition: the Problem of Metaphysics in the Critique of Pure Reason and a Solution

Philosophy Pathways Issue th December 2016

BASIC ISSUES IN AESTHETIC

Immanuel Kant Critique of Pure Reason

AESTHETICS. Key Terms

The aim of this paper is to explore Kant s notion of death with special attention paid to

Imagination and Contingency: Overcoming the Problems of Kant s Transcendental Deduction

A Comprehensive Critical Study of Gadamer s Hermeneutics

Kant Prolegomena to any Future Metaphysics, Preface, excerpts 1 Critique of Pure Reason, excerpts 2 PHIL101 Prof. Oakes updated: 9/19/13 12:13 PM

Philosophy of Science: The Pragmatic Alternative April 2017 Center for Philosophy of Science University of Pittsburgh ABSTRACTS

INTRODUCTION. Cambridge University Press

UNIT SPECIFICATION FOR EXCHANGE AND STUDY ABROAD

Having the World in View: Essays on Kant, Hegel, and Sellars

Edward Winters. Aesthetics and Architecture. London: Continuum, 2007, 179 pp. ISBN

observation and conceptual interpretation

IMPORTANT QUOTATIONS

The Second Copernican Turn of Kant s Philosophy 1

Making Modal Distinctions: Kant on the possible, the actual, and the intuitive understanding.

1/8. Axioms of Intuition

THE CRITIQUE OF JUDGEMENT PART 1: CRITIQUE OF AESTHETIC JUDGEMENT

4 Unity in Variety: Theoretical, Practical and Aesthetic Reason in Kant

Bas C. van Fraassen, Scientific Representation: Paradoxes of Perspective, Oxford University Press, 2008.

Theory of Aesthetics and Teleology

The Aesthetic Idea and the Unity of Cognitive Faculties in Kant's Aesthetics

6AANA034 Aesthetics Syllabus Academic year 2016/17. Module description. Assessment methods and deadlines

KANT S SUBJECTIVE DEDUCTION

Brandom s Reconstructive Rationality. Some Pragmatist Themes

Kant and the Problem of Experience

Dabney Townsend. Hume s Aesthetic Theory: Taste and Sentiment Timothy M. Costelloe Hume Studies Volume XXVIII, Number 1 (April, 2002)

genesis in kant notes

Architecture as the Psyche of a Culture

THESIS MIND AND WORLD IN KANT S THEORY OF SENSATION. Submitted by. Jessica Murski. Department of Philosophy

Undercutting the Realism-Irrealism Debate: John Dewey and the Neo-Pragmatists

Copyright Nikolaos Bogiatzis 1. Athenaeum Fragment 116. Romantic poetry is a progressive, universal poetry. Its aim isn t merely to reunite all the

The Role of Imagination in Kant's Theory of Reflective Judgment. Johannes Haag

6AANB021 Kant s Moral Philosophy 2014/15

PAUL REDDING S CONTINENTAL IDEALISM (AND DELEUZE S CONTINUATION OF THE IDEALIST TRADITION) Sean Bowden

Kant on Unity in Experience

Truth and Method in Unification Thought: A Preparatory Analysis

Hypatia, Volume 21, Number 3, Summer 2006, pp (Review) DOI: /hyp For additional information about this article

KANT S THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE

PH 360 CROSS-CULTURAL PHILOSOPHY IES Abroad Vienna

foucault s archaeology science and transformation David Webb

Georg W. F. Hegel ( ) Responding to Kant

Heideggerian Ontology: A Philosophic Base for Arts and Humanties Education

By Rahel Jaeggi Suhrkamp, 2014, pbk 20, ISBN , 451pp. by Hans Arentshorst

A Copernican Revolution in IS: Using Kant's Critique of Pure Reason for Describing Epistemological Trends in IS

206 Metaphysics. Chapter 21. Universals

The Unfolding of Intellectual Conversion

A RE-INTERPRETATION OF ARTISTIC MODERNISM WITH EMPHASIS ON KANT AND NEWMAN DANNY SHORKEND

WHITEHEAD'S PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE AND METAPHYSICS

PHI 3240: Philosophy of Art

Kant and the Problem of Experience. Hannah Ginsborg. As most of its readers are aware, the Critique of Pure Reason is

Chapter Two. Absolute Identity: Hegel s Critique of Reflection

Practical Intuition and Rhetorical Example. Paul Schollmeier

Practical Action First Critique Foundations *

By Tetsushi Hirano. PHENOMENOLOGY at the University College of Dublin on June 21 st 2013)

SAMPLE COURSE OUTLINE PHILOSOPHY AND ETHICS GENERAL YEAR 12

INHIBITED SYNTHESIS. A Philosophy Thesis by Robin Fahy

1/9. Descartes on Simple Ideas (2)

The Case for Absolute Spontaneity in Kant s Critique of Pure Reason. La defensa de la espontaneidad absoluta en la Crítica de la razón pura de Kant

What Can Experimental Philosophy Do? David Chalmers

INTRODUCTION TO THE POLITICS OF SOCIAL THEORY

Unit 2. WoK 1 - Perception

In his essay "Of the Standard of Taste," Hume describes an apparent conflict between two

Verity Harte Plato on Parts and Wholes Clarendon Press, Oxford 2002

The Chinese University of Hong Kong Department of Philosophy. PHIL 2050 History of Western Philosophy II Course Outline

Transcription:

Cazeaux, C. (2011). Introduction to Immanuel Kant, in C. Cazeaux (ed.), The Continental Aesthetics Reader, 2nd edition, Abingdon: Routledge, 3 9. 1 Immanuel Kant The later philosophy of Immanuel Kant, the philosophy which brings about the Copernican revolution in thought, is a critical system, in a particular sense of the word. His use of the term is allied to his assertion of human finitude. Critique, for Kant, refers to an examination of the scope and limits of our cognitive powers; in particular, a demonstration of both the possibility of knowledge within experience and the impossibility of knowledge beyond the limits of experience. As such, it is a reply to the scepticism characteristic of empiricist philosophy and to the dogmatic metaphysics of rationalism. Philosophy, as Kant finds it, is polarized between the rationalism of Descartes, Leibniz, and Baumgarten on the continent and the empiricism of Locke and Hume in Britain. The presuppositions of both systems, Kant observes, ultimately works to undermine them and prevent them from offering coherent theories of knowledge and action. For example, Descartes fails in the Meditations (1641) to guarantee clear and distinct ideas and Hume realizes in the Treatise (1740) that an empiricist model of knowledge cannot account for abstract, structural concepts such as causality, number, and the self. Critical philosophy seeks to avoid these problems. Human finitude means that our concepts necessarily open onto the world as it is received by us through sensibility (what Kant calls die Anschauung or intuition ): concepts without intuition are empty, intuition without concepts are blind. 1 This necessary interrelationship disarms Hume s doubt regarding the justification of our concepts and demonstrates to the rationalist that our categories are not abstractions which can be detached from experience and used to construct dogmatic metaphysical schemes. Kant s main task is to argue for this interrelationship between mind and reality and, in particular, to explain how objectivity is possible given that the subject has been made

Immanuel Kant 39 the basis of experience. This project occupies all three of the books which make up Kant s critical system. The Critique of Pure Reason (1781, revised 1787) lays the foundations and considers the application of our cognitive powers (or reason (die Vernunft) in Kant s broad sense of the term) to experience. The consequences of finitude for morality are considered in the Critique of Practical Reason (1788). Here, Kant faces the question of how a universal moral imperative supplied by reason in advance of experience can serve as a principle for showing us how we ought to act in particular situations. The Critique of Judgment (1790) completes the critical trilogy not just because it is the third and final volume but, more importantly, because it bridges the gap created by the previous two. For example, in the Critique of Pure Reason, Kant surrenders the operation of the mind which brings pure concepts into relation with empirical intuition as an art concealed in the depths of the human soul, whose real modes of activity nature is hardly likely ever to allow us to discover. 2 The gulf which has to be crossed is between the sensible and the supersensible. The supersensible in this context refers to human reason and, in particular, its capacity for going beyond what is given in immediate (sensible) experience. While Kant maintains the philosophical tradition (following Aristotle, Aquinas, and Descartes) of defining reason as the ability to think creatively and act according to principles which are independent of nature, he nevertheless departs from tradition with his claim that the objectivity or validity of these supersensible principles lies not in themselves, in their own terms, but in their application to sensible reality. This is the relationship which has to be explained. As a result, Kant faces the question of the interaction between the sensible and the supersensible on two accounts, since reason goes beyond the given in both theoretical (or cognitive) and practical ways, as argued in the Critique of Pure Reason and the Critique of Practical Reason respectively. The questions which arise are: theoretically, how do (supersensible) pure, transcendental concepts projected in advance of experience accommodate (sensible) empirical intuitions; and practically, how can a (supersensible) universal moral imperative supplied by reason in advance of experience serve as a principle for showing us how we ought to act in (sensible) particular situations?

Immanuel Kant 40 In completing the critical project, the Critique of Judgment explores those aspects of experience which allow the fullest exposition of the interrelationship between subject and object: art, beauty, and the appearance of design in nature. Aesthetics is not treated in isolation but made central to Kant s entire project, and shown to be directly relevant to moral and epistemological issues. The main question which Kant asks in the third Critique is how a subjective, aesthetic judgment, a judgment of taste, can claim universal assent. Aesthetic judgments are those utterances where we describe something as beautiful or has having special significance, e.g. This is a beautiful landscape, This is a powerful work of art. The problem he finds with these judgments is that, although in one sense they are a description of a personal feeling, they nevertheless appear to make a claim about the object concerned, a claim (about its beauty or aesthetic strength) which arguably should hold for everyone. Kant refers to this as the antinomy of taste. How can the contradictory aspects of subjectivity and objectivity be reconciled? In order to overcome the antinomy, Kant distinguishes between determinative and reflective judgment. This distinction is vital. Judgment in general, he writes, is the ability to think the particular under the universal (CJ 179). 3 Determinative judgments, on the one hand, subsume a particular under a universal or, in a more Kantian idiom, an intuition under a concept, and determine an object to be a certain kind of thing, for example, This is a tomato. Reflective judgments, on the other, do not identify or assign properties to an object. Judgments of taste are reflective: to describe a landscape as beautiful or a piece of music as sad is not to ascribe empirically determinate qualities to the objects. No determination is made by these judgments, Kant maintains, for the simple reason that no definite concept is available to them. (Resistance to conceptualization, we can recall, is the traditional charge made against aesthetic experience by philosophy.) Instead, he argues, our cognitive powers have to look for a concept. Reflective judgment then needs a concept for, in Kantian terms, all experience requires concepts and intuitions, but not a determinate concept. To meet this need, judgment presupposes the indeterminate concept of nature s subjective purposiveness

Immanuel Kant 41 (Zweckmäßigkeit), the idea that the world appears to us as if it had been designed for our awareness: Someone who feels pleasure in the mere reflection on the form of an object, without any concern about a concept, rightly lays claim to everyone s assent, even though this judgment is empirical and a singular judgment. For the basis of this pleasure is found in the universal, though subjective, condition of [aesthetic] reflective judgments, namely, the purposive harmony of an object (whether a product of nature or of art) with the mutual relation of the cognitive powers (imagination and understanding) that are required for every empirical cognition. (CJ 191, emphasis added) We experience beauty or aesthetic delight, Kant declares, when we recognize that the order we perceive in the world is a reflection of the order we require for meaningful, intelligible experience. In other words, moments of beauty, for Kant, are moments when we glimpse the conditions of possibility of experience. Isn t this simply a restatement of the premise that there is a necessary interrelationship between mind and nature? The only way a philosophy which starts from the point of view of the subject can explain objectivity, it would seem, is to make the rather grand assumption that mind and nature simply interlock. Kant is not guilty of this though. To rely on the indeterminate concept of nature s subjective purposiveness, he avers, is not to assume that the laws of nature are the laws of our understanding, for it is only reflective [as opposed to determinative] judgment that uses this idea as a principle... In using this principle, judgment gives a law only to itself, not to nature (CJ 180). Kant is not asserting that nature has been designed for our awareness, not arguing for the presence of a particular order in nature. This distinguishes him from the Enlightenment belief that our categories cut reality at the joints and deliver to us conceptually all that the world can be. Instead, Kant is arguing for the possibility of order, the state of affairs upon which any experiential, intelligible purchase on the world is conditional. Without this, empirical differences might still be so great that it would be impossible for our

Immanuel Kant 42 understanding... to divide nature s products into genera and species (CJ 185). Purposiveness, he writes, is a principle by which judgment prescribes, not to nature (which would be autonomy) but to itself (which is heautonomy), a law for its reflection on nature... [W]e must think nature, as regards its merely empirical laws, as containing the possibility of an endless diversity of empirical laws that [despite being laws] are nonetheless contingent as far as we can see... And yet we must necessarily presuppose and assume this unity, since otherwise our empirical cognition could not thoroughly cohere to [form] a whole of experience (CJ 183-86). By transforming the determinate notion of purpose (Zweck) into the indeterminate notion of purposiveness (Zweckmäßigkeit), Kant is reconciling another pair of philosophical opposites. Eighteenth-century science was trying to accommodate two world-views: Aristotelian teleology and Renaissance empiricism. Teleology is the study of purpose in nature. It derives from Aristotle s concept of final cause or telos. Every inanimate object or organism, Aristotle argues, has a natural place or state and all motion or growth can be explained in terms of transition towards this final state. For example, objects fall to the ground, Aristotle suggests, because the earth is their natural state. The Renaissance though brought the recognition that knowledge could be generated simply by detecting regularity through observation, and much of the evidence of the senses was found to conflict with Aristotle s system, e.g. his theory of the celestial spheres. As a result, Aristotle s influence waned. However, deriving mechanical laws from observed regularities cannot explain the sense of organization found in organisms where parts interact in the interests of the greater whole. Thus the Aristotelian notion of purpose was still a necessary explanatory component. In Kant s system, purposiveness (or the appearance of a purpose) becomes the transcendental principle which explains how the apprehension of regularity in experience is possible. One question raised by this account is the source of the indeterminate concept of nature s subjective purposiveness. Where does it come from? This is a taxing question

Immanuel Kant 43 for a metaphysics which is trying to extrapolate conditions of possibility from a minimal set of relations between sensibility (phenomenal nature and our sensory being) and supersensibility (noumenal reality or reality as it is in itself and our capacity for free, independent thought and action), and which, therefore, cannot rely upon a ghost in the machine, an architectonic-saving device that is parachuted in from outside. I said above that judgment presupposes the concept. In writing this, I am following Kant s language. For example, he writes: [J]udgment must assume, as an a priori principle for its own use, that what to human insight is contingent in the particular (empirical) natural laws does nevertheless contain a law-governed unity, unfathomable but still conceivable by us, in the combination of what is diverse in them to [form] an experience that is intrinsically [an sich] possible. (CJ 183-84; emphasis added) Judgment for Kant, to clarify the term, is one of our cognitive powers, a mediating link between understanding and reason (CJ 168). Judgment is exercised by reason, the capacity to think and act according to principles which are independent of nature, applying concepts (from the faculty of the understanding) to sensible intuition, thereby generating ordered, intelligible experience. In completing Kant s critical trilogy, the Critique of Judgment attempts to address some of the gaps left by the previous two. Judgment becomes the focus because Kant reasons, by analogy, that it is the territory to explore for laws which can bridge the gaps. 4 However, it would appear the precise nature of the origin of purposiveness remains unresolved. Equating purposiveness with the subjective principle [of] the indeterminate idea of the supersensible in us, Kant declares that its sources are concealed from us, that we can do no more than point to it, and there is nothing we can do that would allow us to grasp it any further (CJ 340). 5 While it might appear that a gap remains in Kant s system at this crucial point, it is important to note that Kant is sensitive to the boundaries of what can be known and articulated; his critical project is, after all, a study of the limits of reason. There are several declarations within the third Critique to the effect that it is beyond reason s grasp what happens at the supersensible level (see, for example, CJ 411, 412, 422). This

Immanuel Kant 44 though might sound like an all-too-easy get-out clause: when the architectonic gets tough, just hold up your hands and say it s an art concealed in the depths of the human soul. 6 It cannot be denied that Kant s enquiry has a self-referential aspect: to make a determinate, theoretical proposition about a supersensible source would effectively contradict the aim of the first Critique: to demonstrate the possibility of knowledge within experience, and the impossibility of knowledge beyond the limits of experience. However, there are studies which argue that Kant does carry out various pointing and grasping gestures with regard to the supersensible via analogy, and his account of rational ideas (of which purposiveness is one): an idea which can never become cognition because it contains a concept (of the supersensible) for which no adequate intuition can ever be given (CJ 342). 7 In making my selections from the Critique of Judgment, I have chosen extracts which fit together to give an indication of the relationship which the third Critique (on art and teleology) has with its predecessors (the first on epistemology and the second on morality). The majority of the sections reproduced here show how the problems posed by aesthetic judgment and the experience of beauty lead to the concept of purposiveness and, more especially, purposiveness as it is displayed in art. Purposiveness, as the feeling of freedom in the play of our cognitive powers (CJ 306), is the basis of the relationship between mind and nature which allows us to bring nature under concepts. It is therefore the term which completes Kant s explanation of finitude from the Critique of Pure Reason, the necessarily interwoven nature of concept and intuition. There are sections from the Analytic of Aesthetic Judgment and the Dialectic of Aesthetic Judgment. The analytic dialectic structure is common to all three Critiques: analytic, in this context, refers to what can be said about judgment (bringing an intuition under a concept) as it applies to experience, whereas dialectic refers to the transcendental reasoning beyond experience Kant undertakes in order to resolve the antinomies of metaphysics. The Analytic sections outline the significance Kant attaches to fine art, and the contradictory aspects of aesthetic judgments (subjective statements making objective claims) which define the antinomy of taste. Reproduced from the Dialectic of Aesthetic Judgment is the solution to the antinomy.

Immanuel Kant 45 There is still disagreement within Kantian scholarship over the relation between beauty and morality in Kant s critical system. The key issue for some commentators is whether Kant s theory of taste can be regarded as complete and coherent on its own terms, i.e. independently of a theory of reflective judgment, or whether it requires isomorphic links to other parts of his architectonic. Each path, of course, leads to a different interpretation of Kant s aesthetics and, more significantly, provides a different account of the universal condition which underpins the normativity of aesthetic judgment. Guyer and Allison maintain (albeit for different reasons) 8 that the universal validity of aesthetic judgment is fully accounted for in epistemological terms. For Guyer, the strategy of Kant s deduction of aesthetic judgment consists in the argument that attribution of pleasure to the harmony of the faculties makes it universally valid just because this state is the subjective condition of knowledge in general. 9 In a comparable vein, Allison argues that the deduction of aesthetic judgment has at its core the argument that the subjective formal conditions of judgment which underlie our liking an object are also the conditions of judgment per se, therefore, they can be held to apply to everyone. 10 In contrast, a number of commentators (for example, Elliott, 11 Genova, 12 Gotshalk, 13 Kemal, 14 Pluhar 15 and Rogerson 16 ) insist that the normativity of aesthetic judgment cannot be justified purely in epistemological terms and that the universality which is required is in fact supplied by an analogical link to Kant s moral philosophy. These accounts also rely upon and promote the strategies of interpretation which can be applied when Kant s critical philosophy is regarded as a coherent unity. What distinguishes the epistemological interpretation of normativity from the moral approach is the importance which the latter places on 59, the final paragraph of the Critique of Aesthetic Judgment (included here), where Kant asserts that beauty is the symbol of morality. Various suggestions are made as to how the symbolic or analogical link between aesthetics and morality is to be understood. To give two examples, one from Kemal, the other from Gotshalk. Emphasis is placed by Kemal on the purposiveness of nature considered heuristically as design by God, where the concept of design or technic is conceived by analogy to the human production of art. 17 On this basis, Kemal argues, the beauty of nature [is given] an importance because nature appears to be art,

Immanuel Kant 46 as if it had freedom and a rational will at its base. 18 A different perspective is offered by Gotshalk, who concentrates upon the analogy between art and morality used by Kant to characterize the expressive, unbounded nature of aesthetic ideas. The connection which Gotshalk makes is that since the moral life has a similar aspiration towards achievements of infinite [or unbounded] quality, nature expressed through aesthetic ideas in art therefore can be regarded as presenting evidence of a congruence between its [nature s] being and the laws and powers properly guiding our conduct in the realm of freedom. 19 The critical trilogy is a very elaborate structure, and its overall coherence as a unified system continues to be the subject of contemporary scholarship. The importance it holds for aesthetics is immense, since it positions the aesthetic as that realm of human experience where we appraise the relationship between the world and our conceptual understanding of it. We enjoy art, literature, and music because they move us subjectively to offer objective judgment, and it is this tension or interplay between subjectivity and objectivity, Kant affirms, which we find in moral reasoning, the construction of knowledge, and, in fact, every waking moment. Thus, the demands made by an artwork on us to find the right words to describe its effect or significance are paradigms for the conceptual or interpretative decisions which have to be made in moral and epistemological judgments. Fine art, for Kant, is the product of genius. The concept of genius is formulated in eighteenth- and nineteenth-century Romanticism (arguably as an extension of the ancient image of the inspired poet and the Renaissance concept of the divino artista), 20 and is presented as the capacity of an artist to produce work which transcends the established rules of composition. In Kantian terms, the genius is an artist who can give phenomenal form to aesthetic ideas. An aesthetic idea is a presentation of the imagination which prompts much thought, but to which no determinate thought whatsoever, i.e. no [determinate] concept, can be adequate, so that no language can express it completely and allow us to grasp it (CJ 314). The artistgenius can also display some sense of purposiveness through their artwork. In [dealing with] a product of fine art, Kant writes, we must become conscious that it is art rather than nature, and yet the purposiveness [the appearance of design or purpose] in its form

Immanuel Kant 47 must seem as free from all constraint of chosen rules as if it were a product of mere nature (CJ 306). The appearance of art as if it were a product of mere nature would seem to suggest that Kant confines fine art to mimesis. This is not the case. While it is true that much eighteenth century painting seeks to define or perfect beauty in nature, it is important to remember that Kant makes beauty a function of the interplay between our cognitive faculties and the world. Fine art then, for Kant, is first and foremost an activity through which we explore the nature of our moral and perceptual contact with the world. This means art and aesthetics become practices in which new alignments between concept and intuition are generated, and can be theorized in Kantian terms on account of the way they force us to reconceptualize what we experience. Kantian appraisals of the revolutions in representation generated by modernism, such as impressionism, fauvism, cubism, can be given in terms of the concepts we have to import from studies of light, materiality and movement, for example, in order to describe and appreciate them. The acoustic art (das Neue Hörspiel) which emerged from experimentations with radio in 1920s Germany is another example. 21 Here the aesthetic and technical properties of the medium prompt directors to montage sounds, e.g. speech, animal cries, natural sounds of wind and water, machinery and the noises generated by radio itself, in a way which thwart the listener s stable categorization and placing of the source objects in the world. Kant also has relevance for postmodern aesthetics. One of the distinctive characteristics of postmodern practice, according to Fredric Jameson, is a complexity of conceptual borrowing and intermingling which frustrates any simple or straightforward assimilation of that practice in the name of a given or predicted end. 22 As a result, in the context of art, the postmodern aesthetic, in Jameson s words, has a schizophrenic effect on its audience, that is to say, the audience is completely and utterly disoriented when, instead of being presented with a familiar, shared narrative, they are confronted by a network of competing styles. 23 Kant s philosophy can be considered here in as much as it offers a framework for dealing with those occasions when our cognitive faculties are overwhelmed or cannot get a purchase on what is in front of them. The position which aesthetic experience holds in Kant s critical framework has also lead to interest in his philosophy from philosophers and scientists working in neuroaesthetics. 24

Immanuel Kant 48 1 Extracts from Analytic of Aesthetic Judgement and Dialectic of Aesthetic Judgement, Critique of Judgment Immanuel Kant [Insert original Kant extracts] Translated by Werner S. Pluhar Select bibliography of major works by Immanuel Kant in English Observations on the Feeling of the Beautiful and Sublime (1764), trans. J.T. Goldthwait, Berkeley: University of California Press, 1960. Theoretical Philosophy, 1755-1770, ed. and trans. D. Walford with R. Meerbote, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1992. Critique of Pure Reason (1781, 1787), trans. N Kemp Smith, London, Macmillan, 1929. Critique of Pure Reason (1781, 1787), trans. W.S. Pluhar, Indianapolis, Hackett, 1996. Critique of Pure Reason (1781, 1787), trans. P. Guyer and A.W. Wood, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1999. Prolegomena to Any Future Metaphysics (1783), trans. L.W. Beck, Indianapolis, Bobbs- Merrill, 1950 [now Macmillan]. Prolegomena to Any Future Metaphysics (1783), trans. G. Hatfield, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 2004. Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals (1785), trans. H.J. Paton, London: Hutchinson, 1948. Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals (1785), ed. and trans. M. Gregor, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1998.

Immanuel Kant 49 Critique of Practical Reason (1788), trans. L.W. Beck, Indianapolis, Bobbs-Merrill, 1956 [now Macmillan]. Practical Philosophy, ed. M. Gregor, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1999. Critique of Judgement (1790), trans. J. Creed Meredith, Oxford, Clarendon, 1928. Critique of Judgment (1790), trans. W.S. Pluhar, Indianapolis, Hackett, 1987. Critique of the Power of Judgment (1790), trans. P. Guyer and E. Matthews, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 2000. The Metaphysics of Morals (1797), ed. M. Gregor, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996. Further reading For introductions to the systematic nature of Kant s aesthetics, see Kemal (1997), McCloskey, and Wenzel. Closer, more technical studies of the structure of his aesthetic philosophy including the place of art, beauty, taste, aesthetic pleasure, and imagination in his theory, are given by Allison, Banham, Berger, Crawford, Guyer (1993, 1997, 2005), Kirwan, Pluhar, Rogerson (1986, 2008) and Schaper (1979). Anthologies providing a range of perspectives are Chadwick and Cazeaux, Cohen and Guyer, Guyer (1992, 2003), and Rehberg and Jones. For a dictionary of Kantian concepts and themes, see Caygill (1995). The systematic nature of Kant s critical philosophy means that the relationship between the subjects of his three Critiques knowledge and experience, morality, and art and teleology is a vital question for Kantian scholarship. The relation between aesthetics, knowledge and cognition has been explored by Cazeaux (2003), Gasché, Ginsborg, Hughes (2007), Kukla, and Rush. The question of the relation between aesthetics and morality, and the unity of Kant s critical philosophy as a whole, is addressed by Allison, Banham, Bell, Cazeaux (2007), Cohen, Crowther, Elliott, Genova, Gotshalk, Guyer (1993, 1997, 2005), Henrich, Kemal (1992), Kneller, Rogerson (1992), and Wachter. On purposiveness, arguably the pivotal concept in the third Critique, and Kant s entire critical system, see Hughes (2006, 2007), Pluhar, and Zuckert.

Immanuel Kant 50 Many studies focus on individual themes within the Critique of Judgment or apply its content to debates within contemporary aesthetics and culture. For assessments of the importance of the third Critique to questions of hermeneutics, poststructuralism, and ontology, see Caygill (1989), Derrida, Gasché, Makkreel, de Man, Rehberg and Jones, Ross, and Shaviro. How Kant s aesthetics fares in the encounter with works of art is considered by Caygill (1997), De Duve, Gaiger, Kemal, Savile, and Winchester, with Crowther, Lazaroff, Lyotard, Makkreel, and Pillow paying special attention to the sublime. H.E. Allison, Kant's Theory of Taste: A Reading of the Critique of Aesthetic Judgment, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2001. G. Banham, Kant and the Ends of Aesthetics, Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan, 2000. D. Bell, The art of judgement, Mind, 1987, vol. 96, 221-244. Reproduced in Chadwick and Cazeaux (eds), Immanuel Kant: Critical Assessments vol. 4, pp. 13-38. D. Berger, Kant's Aesthetic Theory: The Beautiful and Agreeable, London: Continuum, 2009. H. Caygill, The Art of Judgment, Oxford: Blackwell, 1989., A Kant Dictionary, Oxford: Blackwell, 1995., Stelarc and the chimera: Kant s Critique of Prosthetic Judgment, Art Journal, 1997, vol. 56, 46-51. C. Cazeaux, Art and knowledge in Kant s aesthetics, in Working Papers in Art and Design, 2003. Online. Available HTTP: <http://www.herts.ac.uk/artdes1/research/papers/wpades/vol2/cazeaux.h tml> (accessed 3 April 2010)., Metaphor and Continental Philosophy: From Kant to Derrida, New York: Routledge, 2007, pp. 35-55. R. Chadwick and C. Cazeaux (eds), Immanuel Kant: Critical Assessments vol. 4, London: Routledge, 1992. T. Cohen, Why beauty is a symbol of morality, in Cohen and Guyer (eds), Essays in Kant's Aesthetics, pp. 221-36). T. Cohen and P. Guyer (eds), Essays in Kant's Aesthetics, Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1982.

Immanuel Kant 51 D.W. Crawford, Kant's Aesthetic Theory, Madison: University of Wisconsin Press, 1974. P. Crowther, The Kantian Sublime: From Morality to Art, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1991. T. De Duve, Kant after Duchamp, Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1998. J. Derrida, The Truth in Painting, trans. G. Bennington and I. MacLeod, Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1987. Extract from the chapter Parergon included in this volume. R.K. Elliott, The unity of Kant s Critique of Aesthetic Judgment, in Chadwick and Cazeaux (eds), Immanuel Kant: Critical Assessments vol. 4, pp. 293-308 J. Gaiger, Constraints and conventions: Kant and Greenberg on aesthetic judgement, British Journal of Aesthetics, 1999, vol. 39, 376-91. R. Gasché, The Idea of Form: Rethinking Kant's Aesthetics, Stanford: Stanford University Press, 2003. A.C. Genova, Kant s complex problem of reflective judgment, in Chadwick and Cazeaux (eds), Immanuel Kant: Critical Assessments vol. 4, pp. 54-76. H. Ginsborg, The Role of Taste in Kant's Theory of Cognition, New York: Garland Publishing Company, 1990. D.W. Gotshalk, Form and expression in Kant s aesthetics, in Chadwick and Cazeaux (eds), Immanuel Kant: Critical Assessments vol. 4, pp. 147-57 P. Guyer (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Kant, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1992., Kant and the Experience of Freedom: Essays on Aesthetics and Morality, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993., Kant and the Claims of Taste, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1997. 2nd edition., (ed.), Kant s Critique of the Power of Judgment: Critical Essays, Lanham: Rowman and Littlefield, 2003., Kant s System of Nature and Freedom: Selected Essays, Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2005. D. Henrich, Aesthetic Judgment and the Moral Image of the World: Studies in Kant, Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1994. F. Hughes, On aesthetic judgement and our relation to nature: Kant s concept of purposiveness, Inquiry, 2006, vol. 49, 547-72.

Immanuel Kant 52, Kant's Aesthetic Epistemology: Form and World, Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press, 2007. B. Kalar, Demands of Taste in Kant's Aesthetics, London: Continuum, 2006. S. Kemal, Kant and Fine Art: An Essay on Kant and the Philosophy of Fine Art and Culture, Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1986., The importance of artistic beauty, in Chadwick and Cazeaux (eds), Immanuel Kant: Critical Assessments vol. 4, London: Routledge, 1992, pp. 104-26, Kant's Aesthetic Theory: An Introduction, Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan, 1997. 2nd edition. J. Kirwan, The Aesthetic in Kant, London: Continuum, 2006. J. Kneller, Aesthetic value and the primacy of the practical in Kant's philosophy, Journal of Value Inquiry, 2002, vol. 36, 369-82. A. Lazaroff, The Kantian sublime: aesthetic judgement and religious feeling, Kant- Studien, 1980, vol. 71, 202-20. Reproduced in Chadwick and Cazeaux (eds), Immanuel Kant: Critical Assessments vol. 4, pp. 356-77). J. F. Lyotard, Lessons on the Analytic of the Sublime, trans. E. Rottenberg, Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1994. M.A. McCloskey, Kant s Aesthetic, Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan, 1987. R. Makkreel, Imagination and Interpretation in Kant: The Hermeneutical Import of the Critique of Judgment, Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1990., Imagination and temporality in Kant s theory of the sublime, Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 1984, vol. 42, 303-15. Reproduced in Chadwick and Cazeaux (eds), Immanuel Kant: Critical Assessments vol. 4, pp. 378-96. P. de Man, Phenomenality and materiality in Kant, in G. Shapiro and A. Sica, eds, Hermeneutics: Questions and Prospects, Amherst: University of Massachusetts Press, 1984, pp. 121-44. Reproduced in Chadwick and Cazeaux (eds), Immanuel Kant: Critical Assessments vol. 4, pp. 334-55. R. Kukla, Aesthetics and Cognition in Kant's Critical Philosophy, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2006. K. Pillow, Sublime Understanding: Aesthetic Reflection in Kant and Hegel, Cambridge, Massachusetts: MIT Press, 2000.

Immanuel Kant 53 W.S. Pluhar, Translator s Introduction, in I. Kant, Critique of Judgment, Indianapolis: Hackett, 1987. A. Rehberg and R. Jones (eds), The Matter of Critique, London: Clinamen, 2000. K.F. Rogerson, Kant's Aesthetics: The Roles of Form and Expression, Lanham: University Press of America, 1986., The meaning of universal validity in Kant s aesthetics, in Chadwick and Cazeaux (eds), Immanuel Kant: Critical Assessments vol. 4, London: Routledge, 1992, pp. 309-20., The Problem of Free Harmony in Kant's Aesthetics, New York: State University of New York Press, 2008. A. Ross, The Aesthetic Paths of Philosophy: Presentation in Kant, Heidegger, Lacoue-Labarthe, and Nancy, Stanford: Stanford University Press, 2007. F.L. Rush, The harmony of the faculties: Kant's general theory of cognition and his account of aesthetic judgment, Kant-Studien, 2001, vol. 92, 38-61. A. Savile, Kantian Aesthetics Pursued, Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press, 1993. E. Schaper, Studies in Kant's Aesthetics, Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press, 1979. S. Shaviro, Without Criteria: Kant, Whitehead, Deleuze, and Aesthetics, Cambridge, Massachusetts: MIT Press, 2009. A. Wachter, The aesthetics of manners: the affinity of aesthetic emotion and practical rationality in Kant, Kant-Studien, 2006, vol. 97, 396-400. H. Wenzel, An Introduction to Kant s Aesthetics: Core Concepts and Problems, Malden, MA: Wiley Blackwell, 2005. J. Winchester, Understanding aesthetic judgments across cultural borders: bell hooks, Kant, Cornel West and the understanding of aesthetic judgments of others, Southern Journal of Philosophy, 2000, vol. 38, 499-525. R. Zuckert, The purposiveness of form: a reading of Kant's aesthetic formalism, Journal of the History of Philosophy, 2006, vol. 44: 599-622. Notes [to follow Editor s introduction to Kant]

Immanuel Kant 54 1 I. Kant, Critique of Pure Reason, trans. N. Kemp Smith, London: Macmillan, 1929, A51, B75, p. 93. Numbers refer to the pagination of the original Akadamie edition, included in the margin of this translation. A denotes the first edition Critique (1781), B the second (1787). 2 Ibid., A141, B180-81, pp. 82-83. 3 I. Kant, Critique of Judgment, trans. W.S. Pluhar, Indianapolis: Hackett, 1987. Numbers refer to the pagination of the original Akadamie edition, included in the margin of this translation. 4 The project of uniting the sensible and the supersensible ultimately leads Kant, in the Critique of Judgment, to the problem of reconciling two concepts of the supersensible: the suspersensible substrate of all appearances in accordance with the laws of nature, and the supersensible substrate of our freedom to act in accordance with the moral law; or in other words, the supersensible as the substrate of nature and as the substrate of our freedom to act in ways which are not determined by nature. It is by means of analogy that Kant identifies our power of judgment as the principle to which we should turn in order to achieve the desired resolution. He does this in his second introduction to the Critique of Judgment. Reviewing his work from the first two Critiques, Kant observes that the concepts of nature which contain a priori the basis for all theoretical cognition, were found to rest on the legislation of the understanding, and similarly that the concept of freedom was found to contain a priori the basis for all practical precepts that are unconditioned by the sensible, and to rest on the legislation of reason (CJ 176). On this basis, he argues, we have cause to suppose, by analogy, that [judgment] too may contain a priori, if not a legislation of its own, then at least a principle of its own, perhaps merely a subjective one, by which to search for laws. Even though such a principle would lack a realm of objects as its own domain, it might still have some territory; and this territory might be of such a character that none but this very principle might hold it. (CJ 177)

Immanuel Kant 55 5 For an account of Kant s equation of nature s subjective purposiveness with the subjective principle [of] the indeterminate idea of the supersensible in us, see Pluhar s Translator s Introduction, in I. Kant, Critique of Judgment, trans. W.S. Pluhar, pp. lxii-lxiii, xciv-xcviii. 6 Kant, Critique of Pure Reason, A141, B180-81, pp. 82-83. 7 See J. Derrida, Parergon in this volume, and C. Cazeaux, Metaphor and Continental Philosophy: From Kant to Derrida, London: Routledge, 2007, pp. 35-55. 8 Allison gives his account of these reasons at H.E. Allison, Kant s Theory of Taste, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2001, pp. 180-82. 9 P. Guyer, Kant and the Claims of Taste, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1997, 2nd edition, p. 101. 10 Allison, Kant s Theory of Taste, p. 176. These accounts from Guyer and Allison, it should be pointed out, do not amount to the claim that taste and morality are not connected in Kant s philosophy; both accept that a connection exists. What they do deny is that judgments of taste are grounded by the connection between taste and morality. 11 R.K. Elliott, The unity of Kant s Critique of Aesthetic Judgment, in Chadwick and Cazeaux (eds), Immanuel Kant: Critical Assessments vol. 4, London: Routledge, 1992, pp. 293-308. 12 A.C. Genova, Kant s complex problem of reflective judgment, in Chadwick and Cazeaux (eds), Immanuel Kant: Critical Assessments vol. 4, pp. 54-76. 13 D.W. Gotshalk, Form and expression in Kant s aesthetics, in Chadwick and Cazeaux (eds), Immanuel Kant: Critical Assessments vol. 4, pp. 147-57. 14 S. Kemal, The importance of artistic beauty, in Chadwick and Cazeaux (eds), Immanuel Kant: Critical Assessments vol. 4, pp. 104-26. 15 Pluhar presents his interpretation of the normativity of aesthetic judgment as part of the introduction to his translation of the Critique of Judgment, especially pp. lxilxvi. 16 K.F. Rogerson, The meaning of universal validity in Kant s aesthetics, in Chadwick and Cazeaux (eds), Immanuel Kant: Critical Assessments vol. 4, pp. 309-20. 17 Kemal, The importance of artistic beauty, p. 107.

Immanuel Kant 56 18 Ibid., p. 118. 19 Gotshalk, Form and expression in Kant s aesthetics, pp. 154-55. 20 See P. Murray, Genius: History of an Idea, Oxford: Blackwell, 1989. 21 Good accounts of the development of the Neue Hörspiel (although not in any Kantian context) are given in M. Cory, The Emergence of an Acoustical Artform: An Analysis of the German Experimental Hörspiel of the 1960s (Lincoln: University of Nebraska Press, 1974), and D. Kahn and G. Whitehead (eds.), Wireless Imagination: Sound, Radio and the Avant-Garde (Cambridge, Massachusetts: MIT Press, 1992). 22 F. Jameson, Postmodernism, or the Cultural Logic of Late Capitalism (London: Verso, 1991); also The Cultural Turn: Selected Writings on the Postmodern, 1983-1998 (London: Verso, 1998). 23 Jameson, Postmodernism and consumer society, The Cultural Turn, p. 3. 24 See, for example, J. McMahon, Aesthetics and Material Beauty: Aesthetics Naturalized, New York: Routledge, 2007.