ships sailing past each other in the night. Delcomminette serves scholarship well, therefore, by drawing together these many discussions of the

Similar documents
Why Pleasure Gains Fifth Rank: Against the Anti-Hedonist Interpretation of the Philebus 1

Plato s work in the philosophy of mathematics contains a variety of influential claims and arguments.

Forms and Causality in the Phaedo. Michael Wiitala

Aesthetics Mid-Term Exam Review Guide:

Virtues o f Authenticity: Essays on Plato and Socrates Republic Symposium Republic Phaedrus Phaedrus), Theaetetus

Conclusion. One way of characterizing the project Kant undertakes in the Critique of Pure Reason is by

that would join theoretical philosophy (metaphysics) and practical philosophy (ethics)?

Plato s. Analogy of the Divided Line. From the Republic Book 6

SUMMARY BOETHIUS AND THE PROBLEM OF UNIVERSALS

Myth and Philosophy in Plato s Phaedrus

An Aristotelian Puzzle about Definition: Metaphysics VII.12 Alan Code

Intelligible Matter in Aristotle, Aquinas, and Lonergan. by Br. Dunstan Robidoux OSB

PHL 317K 1 Fall 2017 Overview of Weeks 1 5

The Human Intellect: Aristotle s Conception of Νοῦς in his De Anima. Caleb Cohoe

Truth and Method in Unification Thought: A Preparatory Analysis

Predication and Ontology: The Categories

7AAN2026 Greek Philosophy I: Plato Syllabus Academic year 2015/16

Riccardo Chiaradonna, Gabriele Galluzzo (eds.), Universals in Ancient Philosophy, Edizioni della Normale, 2013, pp. 546, 29.75, ISBN

Aristotle on the Human Good

Are There Two Theories of Goodness in the Republic? A Response to Santas. Rachel Singpurwalla

Doctoral Thesis in Ancient Philosophy. The Problem of Categories: Plotinus as Synthesis of Plato and Aristotle

Guide to the Republic as it sets up Plato s discussion of education in the Allegory of the Cave.

Julie K. Ward. Ancient Philosophy 31 (2011) Mathesis Publications

124 Philosophy of Mathematics

1/9. The B-Deduction

ARISTOTLE S METAPHYSICS. February 5, 2016

Theory or Theories? Based on: R.T. Craig (1999), Communication Theory as a field, Communication Theory, n. 2, May,

CURRICULUM VITAE MEHMET M. ERGINEL

The Pure Concepts of the Understanding and Synthetic A Priori Cognition: the Problem of Metaphysics in the Critique of Pure Reason and a Solution

POLSC201 Unit 1 (Subunit 1.1.3) Quiz Plato s The Republic

On Sense Perception and Theory of Recollection in Phaedo

Naïve realism without disjunctivism about experience

The Value of Mathematics within the 'Republic'

The Concept of Nature

Theory or Theories? Based on: R.T. Craig (1999), Communication Theory as a field, Communication Theory, n. 2, May,

Humanities Learning Outcomes

Plato s Forms. Feb. 3, 2016

Verity Harte Plato on Parts and Wholes Clarendon Press, Oxford 2002

The Aesthetic Idea and the Unity of Cognitive Faculties in Kant's Aesthetics

THESIS MIND AND WORLD IN KANT S THEORY OF SENSATION. Submitted by. Jessica Murski. Department of Philosophy

KANT S TRANSCENDENTAL LOGIC

Bas C. van Fraassen, Scientific Representation: Paradoxes of Perspective, Oxford University Press, 2008.

Philosophy of Science: The Pragmatic Alternative April 2017 Center for Philosophy of Science University of Pittsburgh ABSTRACTS

Rethinking the Aesthetic Experience: Kant s Subjective Universality

The Good as Unity: Its Role in the Good Life in Plato's Later Thought

Two Platonic Criticisms of Pleasure

A COMBINED DOCTRINE OF KNOWLEDGE FOR PLATO

Pleasure, Pain, and Calm: A Puzzling Argument at Republic 583e1-8

A Comprehensive Critical Study of Gadamer s Hermeneutics

Sidestepping the holes of holism

On The Necessity of Individual Forms in Plotinus

The Art Of Rhetoric (Penguin Classics) Books

Varieties of Nominalism Predicate Nominalism The Nature of Classes Class Membership Determines Type Testing For Adequacy

Immanuel Kant, the author of the Copernican revolution in philosophy,

Kęstas Kirtiklis Vilnius University Not by Communication Alone: The Importance of Epistemology in the Field of Communication Theory.

Cyclic vs. circular argumentation in the Conceptual Metaphor Theory ANDRÁS KERTÉSZ CSILLA RÁKOSI* In: Cognitive Linguistics 20-4 (2009),

Categories and Schemata

Pain and Pleasure in Plato s Physiology

False Pleasures of the Imagination: Philebus 36c6-40e5

Pierre Hadot on Philosophy as a Way of Life. Pierre Hadot ( ) was a French philosopher and historian of ancient philosophy,

Reality According to Language and Concepts Ben G. Yacobi *

Lecture 12 Aristotle on Knowledge of Principles

MODULE 4. Is Philosophy Research? Music Education Philosophy Journals and Symposia

Georg W. F. Hegel ( ) Responding to Kant

A large portion of Plato s Philebus is occupied by an elusive discussion of the surprising claim

Plato s Enlightenment, History of Philosophy Quarterly, Vol 14, No 2, April 1997, pp

Ed. Carroll Moulton. Vol. 1. New York: Charles Scribner's Sons, p COPYRIGHT 1998 Charles Scribner's Sons, COPYRIGHT 2007 Gale

SAMPLE COURSE OUTLINE PHILOSOPHY AND ETHICS ATAR YEAR 11

Logic and Philosophy of Science (LPS)

Aristotle s Metaphysics

Aristotle's Stoichiology: its rejection and revivals

Is Hegel s Logic Logical?

Plotinus and the Principal of Incommensurability By Frater Michael McKeown, VI Grade Presented on 2/25/18 (Scheduled for 11/19/17) Los Altos, CA

The Origin of Aristotle's Metaphysical Aporiae

Image and Imagination

Plato's Basic Metaphysical Argument against Hedonism and Aristotle's Presentation of It at Eudemian Ethics 6.11

Kant: Notes on the Critique of Judgment

1. What is Phenomenology?

Aristotle (summary of main points from Guthrie)

Magdalena Płotka THE RECOVERY OF THE SELF. PLOTINUS ON SELF-COGNITION 1. Abstract

Jacek Surzyn University of Silesia Kant s Political Philosophy

1. Physically, because they are all dressed up to look their best, as beautiful as they can.

REVIEW ARTICLE IDEAL EMBODIMENT: KANT S THEORY OF SENSIBILITY

Literary Precursors and the Development of Absurdist Humor Throughout the Ages. Student s Name and Surname. Course. Due Date

Martin, Gottfried: Plato s doctrine of ideas [Platons Ideenlehre]. Berlin: Verlag Walter de Gruyter, 1973

Religion as Aesthetic Practice: Aesthetic Experience and the Paradox of Religious Toleration

Necessity in Kant; Subjective and Objective

Università della Svizzera italiana. Faculty of Communication Sciences. Master of Arts in Philosophy 2017/18

Review of Li, The Confucian Philosophy of Harmony

Practical Intuition and Rhetorical Example. Paul Schollmeier

SpringBoard Academic Vocabulary for Grades 10-11

1/10. Berkeley on Abstraction

Valuable Particulars

A Happy Ending: Happiness in the Nicomachean Ethics and Consolation of Philosophy. Wesley Spears

What counts as a convincing scientific argument? Are the standards for such evaluation

Nevertheless: The Philosophical Significance of the Questions Posed at Philebus 15b

Philosophy of Art. Plato

Emily Fletcher Mellon Chair in Ancient Greek Philosophy University of Wisconsin-Madison

On Aristotelian Universals and Individuals: The Vink that is in Body and May Be In Me

- 1 - I. Aristotle A. Biographical data 1. Macedonian, from Stagira; hence often referred to as "the Stagirite". 2. Dates: B. C. 3.

Transcription:

Le Philèbe de Platon. Introduction à l Agathologie Platonicienne. By Sylvain Delcomminette. Leiden and Boston: Brill, 2006. Pp. xi + 680. $209. ISBN 978 9004150 26 3. [<2300 words] George Rudebusch The Philebus is Plato s most difficult dialogue to interpret as a unified, compelling work, to judge from the percentage of its commentators who have asserted such an interpretation is impossible. In this comprehensive commentary, Sylvain Delcomminette makes the case that the Philebus contains compelling arguments united by their dialectical development of an account of the good, an account that complements Plato s other work. The book makes a significant contribution to the study of Plato that is essential reading for scholars at work on the Philebus. As a commentary, the book follows the Philebus closely, discussing virtually every speech in the dialogue, while the chapter divisions break the dialogue into its different stages. Chapter One opens the debate about the good: Is it pleasure, cognition, or something else? Chapter Two marks a metaphysical transition: when Protarchus objects to Socrates efforts to distinguish pleasure into intrinsically distinct pleasures, Socrates responds by generalizing Protarchus s objection to a problem of one and many. Chapter Two also describes how Protarchus comes to accept Socrates hypothesis that any one not merely a material one like Protarchus or Socrates but even a formal one like Cognition or Pleasure is many, that the air of paradox is a linguistic phenomenon, and that the hypothesis is a necessary presupposition of scientific research and pedagogical exposition. Chapter Three refutes two identity theses, showing that the good in human life cannot simply be identical either to pleasure or to knowledge. The remaining inquiry is: what is the good, and what is its relation to pleasure and knowledge? Chapter Four articulates four formal tools needed in the inquiry: the Unlimited, Limit, Mixture, and Cause. Chapters Five through Ten distinguish the one, Pleasure, as many different kinds of pleasure, including different kinds of intrinsically true and false pleasures as well as pleasures intrinsically either mixed with or pure of pain. Chapters Eleven through Thirteen distinguish different branches of knowledge in terms of their intrinsic precision and certainty. Chapter Fourteen summarizes the progress made in the dialogue in preparation for the climax, namely, an account of the forms of pleasure and knowledge acceptable in a good human life (Chapter Fifteen); the form of the good in relation to other dialogues, in particular the Republic (Chapter Sixteen); and the final ranking of intelligence far above pleasure in its likeness to the good (Chapter Seventeen). Scholarship on the Philebus has proliferated since the most recent commentaries, by M. Migliori (L uomo fra piacere, intelligenza e bene: commentario storico-filosofical al Filebo di Platone, Milan: Vita e Pensiero, 1993) and D. Frede (Platon: werke, Übersetzung und Kommentar, vol. III.2, Philebos, Göttingen: Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht, 1997). And these two commentaries themselves were written in ignorance of each other, like great

ships sailing past each other in the night. Delcomminette serves scholarship well, therefore, by drawing together these many discussions of the myriad aspects of the Philebus into a single discussion. The references have sufficient breadth and depth to guide the reader through the extraordinary diversity of scholarship in antiquity as well as in modern English, French, German, Italian, and Latin (a 1947 essay on lines 66a7-8), with indexes of both names and passages. There are no references to work in Modern Greek, Portuguese, or Spanish, the most significant omission being Francisco Bravo s Las Ambigüedades del Placer (Sankt Augustin: Academia, 2003). In addition to his huge achievement of inclusive scholarship, Delcomminette makes sensible judgments about the competing interpretations and has many brilliant insights into the particulars of the dialogue, for example, the true pleasures at 51b: the so-called beautiful colors and shapes and most pleasures of fragrance and sound and all perceived and pleasant fillings of unperceived and painless lacks. Delcomminette rightly sides with those who read this list as an account of true pleasure, giving a definition felt restoration of unfelt lack with illustrative examples colors, shapes, fragrances, and sounds. But this has raised a question: What painless lacks do colors, shapes, and sounds restore? Delcomminette finds the key to the solution at Timaeus 47a-e, which presents vision and sound as divine gifts with the purpose of making human beings capable of attaining inner harmony by contemplating the exterior harmony presented by the beauty of the regular movements of the heavens or of music (p. 466). People are not pained by this postulated inner disharmony which is nothing but a lack of virtue as such. When they contemplate the regularities of audible harmony thanks to the instruments of music and the regularities of the visible motions of the cosmos thanks to the constructions of geometry, their souls recover to some extent the lost harmony. Delcomminette s interpretation gives us a good fit with the text of the Philebus and a plausible theory of psychic restoration. In addition to many insights about particulars, the book makes two breakthroughs towards a charitable view of the dialogue as a whole, with respect to its unity both with itself (Chapter One) and with a project left unfinished in Plato s Republic (Chapter Sixteen). The Philebus opens by alluding to a prior debate off camera, as it were between Socrates and Philebus: is it pleasure or cognition that makes life good? Scholars often complain that the opening passage presents Philebus s position about pleasure in an indeterminate or perhaps inconsistent way: either that pleasure is identical to the good, as Protarchus interprets him, or that it is one good, perhaps among other goods, as Socrates interprets him. Some scholars emend or strain the meaning of the Greek text to give a single thesis to Philebus; others express disappointment at the vagary. Chapter One s breakthrough is to accept the text at face value: Socrates and Protarchus differ in their interpretations of Philebus. Such a reading unites this dialogue that has been notorious for its disunity. For, as Delcomminette shows, Socrates refutes two target theses about the good in the course of the dialogue. To refute the Protarchan identity thesis that pleasure is identical to the good, Socrates uses

thought experiments to show that neither pleasure without cognition nor cognition without pleasure is sufficient for what any person would want from life (20e-22c). As Socrates says, for this argument they will not yet (oèd n ti ) need the divisioninduced forms of pleasure (20c4-5 another riddle of a passage that Delcomminette is able to solve without emendation). But in order to refute the thesis that all pleasure as such is good the thesis Socrates (as opposed to Protarchus) attributes to Philebus as well as to establish Socrates own thesis that cognition is far more similar than pleasure to the good, Socrates will use the laborious process of dividing pleasure and knowledge into the many kinds relevant to these questions (31a-59d), which in turn requires the prior metaphysical agreement to talk about one being many (12a-16e), the Divine Method (16c-19c) and the formal ontology of Limit, Limitlessness, Mix, and Cause (22d-30e). In a second breakthrough, Chapter Sixteen demonstrates a unity of project between the Republic and the Philebus. The Philebus begins with the alternatives both of which the Republic (at 505b) found unsatisfactory, namely that the good is either pleasure or knowledge. The dialogue proceeds not hypothetically from unargued postulates, not metaphorically with an image of the sun, but dialectically in a conversation where even basic metaphysics, method, and ontology are under discussion. In the course of that discussion, the good is shown to be neither pleasure nor cognition but a trinity of measure, beauty, and truth. The investigation of the Philebus has succeeded in providing what the Republic denied us: the logos of the good (p. 586). Delcomminette shows how the trinity of measure, beauty, and truth corresponds to the Republic s image of the sun and explains in what sense the good transcends all other forms in dignity: the form of the good, as measure, is the cause of the measure of all other Forms yet is not itself measured (p. 600) by another. A work of Delcomminette s magnitude deserves, more than notice, critical discussion. In conclusion, I attempt to provide such criticism at three points. (I make these and other criticisms in my Argument Analysis of Plato s Philebus, forthcoming online at Archelogos.com.) I. The book gives an unsatisfactory account of the problem of one and many. Delcomminette s original reading is that the one is a logos, that is, a definition of a species, and the many its parts (p. 36). Such a reading is implausible for at least two reasons. First, it requires clairvoyance on the part of Protarchus, since, according to Delcomminette, this interpretation of the text can be obtained only when its relation to the method introduced a little later (16c5-17a4) is rightly understood (p. 22): without clairvoyance, therefore, Socrates speech at 15b must be unintelligible to Protarchus when he hears it. Second, Delcomminette must take the divine method of 16c-17a to give rise to the problems of one and many (p. 29), but the text states, on the contrary, that there is no better way (16b) than this method to avoid the problems caused by the three controversies by providing euporia, a solution that works (15c: for further discussion of this problem see also F. Muniz and G. Rudebusch, Philebus 15b: A Problem Solved, Classical Quarterly 2004 vol. 54: 394-405).

2. The book s reading (p. 218) of the apeiron as indefinite or indeterminate (a reading that follows e.g. J.C.B. Gosling, Philebus, Oxford: Clarendon, 1975) leads to an unsatisfactory reading of Philebus s speech at 27e, where Philebus claims that pleasure is good because of its being apeiron in magnitude. Philebus of course is claiming that what makes pleasure good is that it can increase ever more in magnitude, not that it is indeterminate in magnitude, so that apeiron must mean limitless or boundless, not one of those things so indeterminate that they can never be grasped by cognition (qui échappent toujours à l intelligence, p. 221). 3. It is unsatisfactory for Delcomminette not to take seriously but to dismiss as play (jeu, p. 263) the argument that there is a particular cognition call it Zeus that rules heaven and earth (28c) and that Cognition is a species of Cause (30d-e). His reading of the argument fails both to identify the argument s inferential structure and to locate the alleged instances of comical or playful inferences or premises. The definition of organic body as a unity of the elements earth, air, fire and water (29d7-8) is the only false premise I find in the argument. My judgment of this premise s falsity, like Plato s judgment of its truth, depends upon an understanding of the type of chemical organization necessary for organic bodies. Whereas science today finds such life-establishing organization to be lacking at the cosmic level, the science of Plato s day found no such lack. Given a macrocosmic life and the causal priority of the macrocosm to its microcosmic inhabitants (29a-e), the rest of the argument s premises and inferences are plausible. We ought to explain why the argument contains the false definition of organic body by reference to the scientific understanding of Plato s day, which turned out to be false, not by the hypothesis that Plato saw the implausibility of a scientific commonplace of his day and wished to play a game with that commonplace. Delcomminette asserts that Socrates himself calls the argument a game at 28c3 and 30e6-7 (p. 263). But this is more than the text says. At 28c3 Socrates says that he stirred up [Philebus] by exalting [his own god, Cognition] in play (σεμνύνων ἐν τῷ παίζειν ἐθορύβησα). What stirred up Philebus was Socrates suggestion that, were we to assign the species Cognition to the wrong genus, we would sin against a god (ἂν ἀσεβοῖμεν, 28a6). Socrates assumption that Cognition is a divinity against which we might sin draws Philebus back into a conversation he had left, complaining, You are exalting your god (σεμνύνεις... τὸν σεαυτοῦ θεόν 28b1) to which Socrates in effect says, I was just kidding when I suggested Cognition is a god. Socrates thereupon directly proves precisely that Cognition is a god, indeed the supreme god Zeus of the cosmos. This text, therefore, only shows Socrates calling a game his unargued suggestion at 28a6, not his rigorous proof at 29a-30e in answer to Philebus s challenge. Thus this text does not support Delcomminette s interpretation that the argument for Cognition s divinity and causal nature is but a game. At 30e6-7 Socrates says that play is sometimes a respite from spoudē, that is, from religious zealotry, partisan rivalry, or any serious talk. But it is left to the reader to interpret what exactly he is calling play. His lengthy argument that Cognition is god of the cosmos is an unlikely candidate, since he has just

affirmed that that argument was nothing idle (30d6), that it validates the wisdom of men of old (30d7-8), and that it has successfully given Socrates answer to his question, since the argument shows that Cognition is a species of Cause (30d10- e3). A much better candidate for the play is in the immediate antecedent to Socrates speech, where Protarchus points out that Socrates classified Cognition, although the answer escaped my notice (καίτοι με ἀποκρινάμενος ἔλαθες, 30e4-5). To answer a man s question without his noticing it is, unlike an argument from cosmic design, a recognized form of play. And when the answer may offend against the religious convictions of one faction in the audience (by making one god, Cognition, supreme over a rival god, Pleasure), it is clear why such play would be a relief from zealotry. Thus this text supports Delcomminette s interpretation no more than 28c3.