Between the Philosophy of Science and Machine Learning

Similar documents
Thomas Kuhn's "The Structure of Scientific Revolutions"

8/28/2008. An instance of great change or alteration in affairs or in some particular thing. (1450)

HPS 1653 / PHIL 1610 Introduction to the Philosophy of Science

An Alternative to Kitcher s Theory of Conceptual Progress and His Account of the Change of the Gene Concept

Structural Realism, Scientific Change, and Partial Structures

Domains of Inquiry (An Instrumental Model) and the Theory of Evolution. American Scientific Affiliation, 21 July, 2012

26:010:685 Social Science Methods in Accounting Research

Necessity in Kant; Subjective and Objective

HPS 1653 / PHIL 1610 Introduction to the Philosophy of Science

10/24/2016 RESEARCH METHODOLOGY Lecture 4: Research Paradigms Paradigm is E- mail Mobile

AN ALTERNATIVE TO KITCHER S THEORY OF CONCEPTUAL PROGRESS AND HIS ACCOUNT OF THE CHANGE OF THE GENE CONCEPT. Ingo Brigandt

Lecture 3 Kuhn s Methodology

TEST BANK. Chapter 1 Historical Studies: Some Issues

The Epistemological Status of Theoretical Simplicity YINETH SANCHEZ

Kuhn Formalized. Christian Damböck Institute Vienna Circle University of Vienna

Philosophy of Science: The Pragmatic Alternative April 2017 Center for Philosophy of Science University of Pittsburgh ABSTRACTS

Jenann Ismael & Huw Price. July 19, 2006

Kuhn and the Structure of Scientific Revolutions. How does one describe the process of science as a human endeavor? How does an

Kuhn. History and Philosophy of STEM. Lecture 6

Philip Kitcher and Gillian Barker, Philosophy of Science: A New Introduction, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2014, pp. 192

Review of Krzysztof Brzechczyn, Idealization XIII: Modeling in History

SAMPLE COURSE OUTLINE PHILOSOPHY AND ETHICS ATAR YEAR 11

Modeling Scientific Revolutions: Gärdenfors and Levi on the Nature of Paradigm Shifts

Aristotle. Aristotle. Aristotle and Plato. Background. Aristotle and Plato. Aristotle and Plato

The Shimer School Core Curriculum

Bas C. van Fraassen, Scientific Representation: Paradoxes of Perspective, Oxford University Press, 2008.

Challenging Times. Introduction. Evolution of Galilean Newtonian Scientific Thinking

ANALYSIS OF THE PREVAILING VIEWS REGARDING THE NATURE OF THEORY- CHANGE IN THE FIELD OF SCIENCE

Social Mechanisms and Scientific Realism: Discussion of Mechanistic Explanation in Social Contexts Daniel Little, University of Michigan-Dearborn

Is Situational Analysis Merely Rational Choice Theory?

Logic and Philosophy of Science (LPS)

Kuhn s Notion of Scientific Progress. Christian Damböck Institute Vienna Circle University of Vienna

WHITEHEAD'S PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE AND METAPHYSICS

(as methodology) are not always distinguished by Steward: he says,

Reality According to Language and Concepts Ben G. Yacobi *

Sidestepping the holes of holism

SAMPLE COURSE OUTLINE PHILOSOPHY AND ETHICS GENERAL YEAR 12

The Discussion about Truth Viewpoint and its Significance on the View of Broad-Spectrum Philosophy

Epistemology and Philosophy of Science

Four kinds of incommensurability. Reason, Relativism, and Reality Spring 2005

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE: AN INTRODUCTION

Meaning Change in the Context of Thomas S. Kuhn s Philosophy. Jouni-Matti Kuukkanen

Scientific Revolutions as Events: A Kuhnian Critique of Badiou

Caught in the Middle. Philosophy of Science Between the Historical Turn and Formal Philosophy as Illustrated by the Program of Kuhn Sneedified

Intersubjectivity and physical laws in post-kantian theory of knowledge: Natorp and Cassirer Scott Edgar October 2014.

observation and conceptual interpretation

Incommensurability and Partial Reference

PHILOSOPHY OF SOCIAL SCIENCE INTS 4522 Spring Jack Donnelly and Martin Rhodes -

Lecture Notes in The Philosophy of Computer Science

Writing Strategies. Cover Page and Cover Letter. 1. Prepare a perfect cover page and an abstract

GV958: Theory and Explanation in Political Science, Part I: Philosophy of Science (Han Dorussen)

WHY IS BEAUTY A ROAD TO THE TRUTH? 1. Introduction

HEAVEN PALLID TETHER 1 REPEAT RECESS DESERT 3 MEMORY CELERY ABCESS 1

Kęstas Kirtiklis Vilnius University Not by Communication Alone: The Importance of Epistemology in the Field of Communication Theory.

Working BO1 BUSINESS ONTOLOGY: OVERVIEW BUSINESS ONTOLOGY - SOME CORE CONCEPTS. B usiness Object R eference Ontology. Program. s i m p l i f y i n g

EUROPEAN JOURNAL OF PRAGMATISM AND AMERICAN PHILOSOPHY. The History of Reception of Charles S. Peirce in Greece 1

Relativism and the Social Construction of Science: Kuhn, Lakatos, Feyerabend

Peircean concept of sign. How many concepts of normative sign are needed. How to clarify the meaning of the Peircean concept of sign?

Mind, Thinking and Creativity

Verity Harte Plato on Parts and Wholes Clarendon Press, Oxford 2002

Thomas Kuhn s Concept of Incommensurability and the Stegmüller/Sneed Program as a Formal Approach to that Concept

Natika Newton, Foundations of Understanding. (John Benjamins, 1996). 210 pages, $34.95.

Are There Two Theories of Goodness in the Republic? A Response to Santas. Rachel Singpurwalla

scholars have imagined and dealt with religious people s imaginings and dealings

THE LANGUAGE OF SCIENCE: MEANING VARIANCE AND THEORY COMPARISON HOWARD SANKEY *

According to Maxwell s second law of thermodynamics, the entropy in a system will increase (it will lose energy) unless new energy is put in.

Society for the Study of Symbolic Interaction SSSI/ASA 2002 Conference, Chicago

PHILOSOPHICAL APPLICATIONS OF COGNITIVE SCIENCE COURSE STRUCTURE

The Barrier View: Rejecting Part of Kuhn s Work to Further It. Thomas S. Kuhn s The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, published in 1962, spawned

REVIEW. Patrick Enfield

INTERVIEW: ONTOFORMAT Classical Paradigms and Theoretical Foundations in Contemporary Research in Formal and Material Ontology.

Thomas Kuhn. 1. Life and Career

Can Kuhn s Taxonomic Incommensurability Be an Image of Science?

AN ABSTRACT OF THE THESIS OF

In inquiry into what constitutes interpretation in natural science. will have to reflect on the constitutive elements of interpretation and three

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at

The topic of this Majors Seminar is Relativism how to formulate it, and how to evaluate arguments for and against it.

THE STRUCTURE OF SCIENTIFIC REVOLUTIONS

Is perspectivism realistic enough for science? Ed Brandon

1/6. The Anticipations of Perception

Holism, Concept Individuation, and Conceptual Change

Kuhn s normal and revolutionary science

Quine s Two Dogmas of Empiricism. By Spencer Livingstone

Lisa Randall, a professor of physics at Harvard, is the author of "Warped Passages: Unraveling the Mysteries of the Universe's Hidden Dimensions.

Is Genetic Epistemology of Any Interest for Semiotics?

Darwinian populations and natural selection, by Peter Godfrey-Smith, New York, Oxford University Press, Pp. viii+207.

In Search of Mechanisms, by Carl F. Craver and Lindley Darden, 2013, The University of Chicago Press.

Thomas Kuhn and Perspectival Realism. A thesis presented to. the faculty of. the College of Arts and Sciences of Ohio University

Toward an Alternative Notion of Information Systems Ontologies: Information Engineering as a Hermeneutic Enterprise

Varieties of Nominalism Predicate Nominalism The Nature of Classes Class Membership Determines Type Testing For Adequacy

1 Introduction Steganography and Steganalysis as Empirical Sciences Objective and Approach Outline... 4

MORAL PHILOSOPHY AND THE DARWINIAN PROBLEM OF SOCIAL EVOLUTION

Ontological and historical responsibility. The condition of possibility

EPISTEMOLOGY, METHODOLOGY, AND THE SOCIAL SCIENCES

Intelligible Matter in Aristotle, Aquinas, and Lonergan. by Br. Dunstan Robidoux OSB

ON PARADIGMS, THEORIES AND MODELS. Fecha de recepción: 7 de agosto de Fecha de aprobación: 7 de octubre de 2002.

An Introduction to Effective Science Communication

CHAPTER 2 THEORETICAL FRAMEWORK

SYNTHESE LIBRARY MONOGRAPHS ON EPISTEMOLOGY, LOGIC, METHODOLOGY, PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE, SOCIOLOGY OF SCIENCE AND OF KNOWLEDGE,

Natural Kinds and Concepts: A Pragmatist and Methodologically Naturalistic Account

Transcription:

Between the Philosophy of Science and Machine Learning David Corfield University of Kent

Kevin Korb: Machine learning should be regarded as "experimental philosophy of science".

Kevin Korb: Machine learning should be regarded as "experimental philosophy of science". Why should we expect philosophy to think up principles to be tested in Machine learning? Philosophy has a tendency to lose control of its offspring, such as the group-theoretic basis to perception (from Kant to Helmholtz & Poincaré to Cassirer to Mallat?).

Kevin Korb: Machine learning should be regarded as "experimental philosophy of science". But for many, History of science is a testing ground for philosophy of science.

Kevin Korb (revised): Machine learning should be regarded as "experimental philosophy of science". History of science is a testing ground for philosophy of science. Machine learning could be a testing ground for formal philosophy of science. Or maybe the association is looser.

Did Popper have the seed of a fundamental idea in statistical learning theory? VC-dimension: largest number of points which can be shattered Popper-dimension: smallest number of points which can't be shattered. (see Falsificationism and Statistical Learning Theory) Popper close, but not quite there? Or was he on a different agenda?

Induction is a myth Arrival at hypotheses is a matter of psychology As a matter of fact they tend to come from myth and metaphysics We don't just go about observing things in the world, we only do so in the context of a test. The testing of a theory is a matter of using modus tollens. We tend to have a bias to look for confirmation, but this is a childish weakness, like neurotics expecting the same patterns. Scientists (and adults) have had to learn to look to falsify their theories.

Perhaps we might say the 'metaphysics' of Popper inspired the 'science' of Vapnik, just as Robert Boyle drew inspiration from the atomism of Epicurus. From a metaphysics of learning to a science of learning. And the debt paid back to philosophy? As with Harman and Kulkarni?

A better account of the ML-Philosophy relationship might decribe it as a 'dynamic interaction'. (Jon Williamson). E.g., Judea Pearl meets David Lewis in the analysis of counterfactuals. A counterfactual is true if in the world closest to ours where the antecedent holds, so does the consequent. Pearl doesn't buy the existence of possible worlds, but takes on the idea of minimal changes.

Rivals of Popper, the Vienna Circle and then the Logical Empiricists, such as Carnap, developed a probability based confirmation theory. Bayesianism as the magic ingredient for learning theory? Whistler 2006 conclusion: frequentists seem more inventive when it came to integrating Background knowledge: cluster assumption, invariance under small changes, robustness under adversarial deletion, structural correspondence (pivot words). Only the first two had been Bayesianised. (See my chapter in ' Dataset Shift in Machine Learning')

Popper attacked Bayesianism Laws have zero prior by principle of indifference Good science looks for the unlikely not the likely But there followed a raft of attacks on both.

Kuhn and Lakatos Science is not in any important way algorithmic. It's about conceptual change. Not only the change of language, but changes to the way we should ask questions of the world. Bayesianism presupposes a fixed theoretical framework. Popper just looked at the revolutionary part, badly. No-one, not even great scientists, ever throws away a theory that easily. Falsificationism is falsified itself by the history of science. For Kuhn, we don't just change our theories, we change what we take to be worth answering. We can lose explanatory power. E.g., phlogiston theory gave a reason why metals are similar in a way that oxygen theory did not. Kuhn replaces one uniformity with another. Copernican revolution is a pattern for all other revolutions.

Feyerabend Galileo must resort to propaganda to have the new science heard. He has to gain the upper hand in describing what an observation is, i.e., that it concerns only relative motion. Would anyone in the scientific revolution have benefited from a ML algorithm? Aristotle, Ptolemy, Galileo? Function estimation for Copernicus? Kepler had plenty of good data from Tycho Brahe. How would it arrive at the relative positions of points on different ellipses? (cf. BACON and the attempt to learn the power law between T and R) The idea of breaking with circular motion was so profound that Galileo rejected it. He had so much invested in circular inertia (hence sketches of the moon with an erroneous circular crater on the midline?).

Perhaps philosophers of science invested too much in early episodes of science. Perhaps modern science is different and offers the opportunity for machine learning. But further worries...

Ernan McMullin on metaphor and creative incompleteness (Jacob Bronowski too). (Occurs in Machine Learning, e.g., Mallat Pushing the energy into low frequencies.) Equivalent formulations of the same theory suggest very different extensions, e.g., Hamiltonian and Langrangian reformulation of Newtonian dynamics. Plenty of work done on varieties of scientific models, their role in between theory and data: Probing models, phenomenological models, computational models, developmental models, explanatory models, impoverished models, testing models, idealized models, theoretical models, scale models, heuristic models, caricature models, didactic models, fantasy models, toy models, imaginary models, mathematical models, substitute models, iconic models, formal models, analogue models and instrumental models are but some of the notions that are used to categorize models. http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/models-science/ 'Models as Mediators' (Morgan and Morrison). Even here, Hartmann and the narrative of the model. Humans seem to want a story of what's going on.

Polanyi's tacit knowledge and the scientist's passionate anticipation of an indeterminate range of yet unknown (and perhaps yet inconceivable) true implications. The kind of knowledge I have of my body by dwelling in it is the paradigm of knowing particulars subsidiarily with a bearing on the comprehensive entity formed by them. Hence when I rely on my awareness of particulars for attending to a whole I handle things as I handle my body. In this sense I know comprehensive entities by indwelling their functional parts, as if they were parts of my body. Such is my conception of knowing by indwelling.

The Holy Grail of integrating automated reasoning across all relevant representations and processes seems far from current reality. This is in no small part due to our continuing ignorance of the creative human thought processes guiding the art of doing science...it will be a fascinating and instructive endeavor requiring contributions across technology, science, and even philosophy to develop and understand the full spectrum of such inference systems. (Mjolsness and DeCoste, Machine learning for science: state of the art and future prospects, 2001) But is all this just too high level? Why mimic the top end of learning, the natural scientist? Perhaps we shouldn't expect ML to be there for the revolutions, more for the normal science. Even so, we need to know more about scientific learning.

Dudley Shapere, critic of historical philosophers projecting from their case studies. There is a history of scientific learning: Metaphysical; piecemeal domains (falling bodies, salts, electrical phenomena); unifying domains (Whewell consilience), e.g., chemical bonds, static electricity. It could not be foretold that these strategies would work. Where we were once satisfied with two astronomies (Greek crystal spheres and ptolemaic epicycles), we had to learn (Shapere with McMullin) that testable theoretical postulation was worth doing, to trust instruments (against Aristotle and adequacy of senses) to use mathematics (against Aristotle), to use a form of experimental method (against Hobbes, and Aristotle on natural rather than violent motion), not to expect the Bible to be a guide to scientific truth (against Newton).

Dudley Shapere (cont.) We have learned how to learn. There is no ahistorical split between the scientific (forces, fields, genes) and the metascientific (observation, theories, explanation, laws). E.g., desirable patterns of explanation change: Newton's gravitational force was unsatisfactory to Cartesians (and himself); Hershel's verae causae, and natural selection as "the law of Higgledy piggledy"; the gruppenpest in physics (coming soon to Machine Learning?); Hilbert's Theology (Gordon's description of proof of Nullstellensatz).

But is there not a single account of explanation, or of causation? Perhaps not a universal account, but enough local pockets of meaning? Causality as difference making (counterfactual, agential ideal intervention, statistical) or productive (continuous transmission of quantity, mechanism). Can absences or omissions be causes? In cases of causation between absences, production is unnecessary; in cases of redundant causation, differencemaking is unnecessary; and there may be cases that involve neither production nor difference-making (Schaffer) Causality in the Sciences, Edited by Phyllis McKay Illari, Federica Russo, and Jon Williamson, OUP, 952 pages.

Shapere again:...the problems we face in our inquiries about nature, and the methods with which we deal with those problems, co-evolve with our beliefs about nature. Might we learn how to use machines to learn? Might new methodologies emerge allowing for further automation?

As ever, the role of background knowledge is key: "Even when prior beliefs are mentioned, their role or roles in new inquiry tend to go undiscussed; even for the hypotheticodeductivists, they may have been "verified" or "confirmed," but their roles in a large variety of the most important functions of scientific inquiry are left out of account, indeed receive no mention.

We should be answering the following questions: (1) What considerations (or, better, types of considerations, if such types can be found) lead scientists to regard a body of information as a body of information - that is, as constituting a unified subject matter or domain to be examined or dealt with? (2) How is description of the items of the domain achieved and modified at sophisticated stages of scientific development? (3) What sort of inadequacies, leading to the need for further work, are found in the bodies of information, and what are the grounds for considering these to be inadequacies or problems requiring further research? (Included here are questions not only regarding the generation of scientific problems about domains, but also scientific priorities - the questions of importance of the problems and of the "readiness" of science to deal with them.)

(4) What considerations lead to the generation of specific lines of research, and what are the reasons (or types of reasons) for considering some lines of research to be more promising than others in the attempt to resolve problems about the domain? (5) What are the reasons for expecting (sometimes to the extent of demanding) that answers of certain sorts, having certain characteristics, be sought for those problems? (6) What are the reasons (or types of reasons) for accepting a certain solution of a scientific problem regarding a domain as adequate. (Shapere 1984, 277-8). He reckons that only the last, and to some extent (2), have been seriously examined by philosophers of science.

Surely these are central features of the scientific enterprise; to ignore them is to ignore the heart of science. But to deal with them successfully it is necessary to recast the way philosophy of science is done, shifting away from the essentialist, atemporal methodology that has too often characterized it, to focussing rather on the ways in which science moves from one stage to another in its inquiries on its evolution."

In current science, there has been internalised a huge number of background beliefs. With these in place we can talk of 'the given' (data). But it is not something read simply off the world. Never forget our shaping of the data. Let's look to see where ML techniques can be used: Data Mining and Machine Learning in Astronomy, Ball & Brunner, http://arxiv.org/abs/arxiv:0906.2173 star/galaxy galaxy morphology detection of quasars We conclude that, so long as one carefully selects an appropriate algorithm, and is guided by the astronomical problem at hand, data mining can be very much the powerful tool, and not the questionable black box.

To conclude: There is no indication that we should expect some universal method, but there's a possibility for local methodologies using ML to emerge. There would need to be a pairing between what aspects of the theory of the domain being studied are accessible and the ML technique. Some domains won't easily lend themselves, e.g., Mathematics. Nor some disciplines at certain stages. Perhaps theories could co-evolve with ML methodologies. There's some potentially useful philosophy literature (modelling, causality, explanation, philosophy of specific sciences)