Kuhn s conservatism VASSO KINDI. Fuller s project

Similar documents
8/28/2008. An instance of great change or alteration in affairs or in some particular thing. (1450)

Kant on wheels. Available online: 24 Jun 2010

Is There Anything Wrong with Thomas Kuhn? Markus Arnold, University of Klagenfurt

Relativism and the Social Construction of Science: Kuhn, Lakatos, Feyerabend

GV958: Theory and Explanation in Political Science, Part I: Philosophy of Science (Han Dorussen)

Truth and Method in Unification Thought: A Preparatory Analysis

Kent Academic Repository

The (Lack of) Evidence for the Kuhnian Image of Science: A Reply to Arnold and Bryant

Philip Kitcher and Gillian Barker, Philosophy of Science: A New Introduction, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2014, pp. 192

The topic of this Majors Seminar is Relativism how to formulate it, and how to evaluate arguments for and against it.

Normal Science and Normal Kuhn.

HISTORIOGRAPHY IN THE TWENTIETH CENTURY: FROM SCIENTIFIC OBJECTIVITY TO THE POSTMODERN CHALLENGE. Introduction

Lecture 3 Kuhn s Methodology

Media as practice. a brief exchange. Nick Couldry and Mark Hobart. Published as Chapter 3. Theorising Media and Practice

These are some notes to give you some idea of the content of the lecture they are not exhaustive, nor always accurate! So read the referenced work.

Critical Theory. Mark Olssen University of Surrey. Social Research at Frankfurt-am Main in The term critical theory was originally

PHILOSOPHY OF SOCIAL SCIENCE INTS 4522 Spring Jack Donnelly and Martin Rhodes -

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at

INTRODUCTION TO NONREPRESENTATION, THOMAS KUHN, AND LARRY LAUDAN

Sidestepping the holes of holism

Normative and Positive Economics

A Comprehensive Critical Study of Gadamer s Hermeneutics

Verity Harte Plato on Parts and Wholes Clarendon Press, Oxford 2002

Adam Smith and The Theory of Moral Sentiments

What counts as a convincing scientific argument? Are the standards for such evaluation

Introduction and Overview

Mitchell ABOULAFIA, Transcendence. On selfdetermination

Conceptual Change, Relativism, and Rationality

Brandom s Reconstructive Rationality. Some Pragmatist Themes

Mixed Methods: In Search of a Paradigm

In retrospect: The Structure of Scientific Revolutions

PART II METHODOLOGY: PROBABILITY AND UTILITY

TEST BANK. Chapter 1 Historical Studies: Some Issues

Colonnade Program Course Proposal: Explorations Category

Are There Two Theories of Goodness in the Republic? A Response to Santas. Rachel Singpurwalla

Introduction to The Handbook of Economic Methodology

PART 1. An Introduction to British Romanticism

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at

By Rahel Jaeggi Suhrkamp, 2014, pbk 20, ISBN , 451pp. by Hans Arentshorst

None DEREE COLLEGE SYLLABUS FOR: PH 4028 KANT AND GERMAN IDEALISM UK LEVEL 6 UK CREDITS: 15 US CREDITS: 3/0/3. (Updated SPRING 2016) PREREQUISITES:

Moral Judgment and Emotions

Necessity in Kant; Subjective and Objective

Hume s Sentimentalism: What Not Who Should Have The Final Word Elisabeth Schellekens

PHD THESIS SUMMARY: Phenomenology and economics PETR ŠPECIÁN

Notes on Gadamer, The Relevance of the Beautiful

Université Libre de Bruxelles

History Admissions Assessment Specimen Paper Section 1: explained answers

Rereading Kuhn REVIEW ARTICLE. Jouni-Matti Kuukkanen

Presented as part of the Colloquium Sponsored by the Lonergan Project at Marquette University on Lonergan s Philosophy and Theology

Philosophical Background to 19 th Century Modernism

TROUBLING QUALITATIVE INQUIRY: ACCOUNTS AS DATA, AND AS PRODUCTS

HPS 1653 / PHIL 1610 Introduction to the Philosophy of Science

Back to Basics: Appreciating Appreciative Inquiry as Not Normal Science

Guide to the Republic as it sets up Plato s discussion of education in the Allegory of the Cave.

Watcharabon Buddharaksa. The University of York. RCAPS Working Paper No January 2011

IS SCIENCE PROGRESSIVE?

History and Theory, Theme Issue 51 (December 2012), 1-5 Wesleyan University 2012 ISSN:

PHI 3240: Philosophy of Art

Plato s work in the philosophy of mathematics contains a variety of influential claims and arguments.

Research Topic Analysis. Arts Academic Language and Learning Unit 2013

Hypatia, Volume 21, Number 3, Summer 2006, pp (Review) DOI: /hyp For additional information about this article

History of Sociological Thought

The Concept of Nature

Reading/Study Guide: Lyotard. The Postmodern Condition

10/24/2016 RESEARCH METHODOLOGY Lecture 4: Research Paradigms Paradigm is E- mail Mobile

MAURICE MANDELBAUM HISTORY, MAN, & REASON A STUDY IN NINETEENTH-CENTURY THOUGHT THE JOHNS HOPKINS PRESS: BALTIMORE AND LONDON

CRITICAL CONTEXTUAL EMPIRICISM AND ITS IMPLICATIONS

Kuhn and coherentist epistemology

Visual Argumentation in Commercials: the Tulip Test 1

206 Metaphysics. Chapter 21. Universals

DEWEY AND THE QUALITATIVE. Rodman B. Webb and Robert R. Sherman University of Florida

THE RELATIONS BETWEEN ETHICS AND ECONOMICS: A COMPARATIVE ANALYSIS BETWEEN AYRES AND WEBER S PERSPECTIVES. By Nuria Toledano and Crispen Karanda

PHIL 144: Social and Political Philosophy University of California, Santa Cruz Department of Philosophy Summer 2015

Loggerhead Sea Turtle

Part II. Rational Theories of Leisure. Karl Spracklen

Emotion, an Organ of Happiness. Ruey-Yuan Wu National Tsing-Hua University

Care of the self: An Interview with Alexander Nehamas

Part IV Social Science and Network Theory

Adorno - The Tragic End. By Dr. Ibrahim al-haidari *

Broadcasting Authority of Ireland Guidelines in Respect of Coverage of Referenda

Responding Rhetorically to Literature and Survey of Literary Criticism. Lemon Bay High School AP Language and Composition Mr.

The Debate on Research in the Arts

ANALYSIS OF THE PREVAILING VIEWS REGARDING THE NATURE OF THEORY- CHANGE IN THE FIELD OF SCIENCE

Critical Spatial Practice Jane Rendell

1) Review of Hall s Two Paradigms

Realities of Music Teaching: A Conversation

Postmodernism. thus one must review the central tenants of Enlightenment philosophy

Owen Barfield. Romanticism Comes of Age and Speaker s Meaning. The Barfield Press, 2007.

New York University Department of Media, Culture, and Communication Special Topics in Critical Theory: Marx

UNIT SPECIFICATION FOR EXCHANGE AND STUDY ABROAD

that would join theoretical philosophy (metaphysics) and practical philosophy (ethics)?

Working BO1 BUSINESS ONTOLOGY: OVERVIEW BUSINESS ONTOLOGY - SOME CORE CONCEPTS. B usiness Object R eference Ontology. Program. s i m p l i f y i n g

What Can Experimental Philosophy Do? David Chalmers

The Shimer School Core Curriculum

Forms and Causality in the Phaedo. Michael Wiitala

The Picture of Dorian Gray

EPISTEMOLOGY, METHODOLOGY, AND THE SOCIAL SCIENCES

Holliday Postmodernism

Texas Southern University. From the SelectedWorks of Anthony M Rodriguez Ph.D. Michael A Rodriguez, Ph.D., Texas Southern University

This is an electronic reprint of the original article. This reprint may differ from the original in pagination and typographic detail.

Transcription:

SOCIAL EPISTEMOLOGY, 2003, VOL. 17, NOS. 2 & 3, 209 214 Kuhn s conservatism VASSO KINDI Fuller s project Steve Fuller in his book Thomas Kuhn: A Philosophical History of Our Times 1 attempts to place in historical context Kuhn s book The Structure of Scientific Revolutions 2 and provide through and around it what he calls a philosophical history of our times. By this term Fuller understands a Hegelian kind of endeavour, which lays more emphasis on philosophy rather than history. History, in this context, is used to assist in the promotion of a philosophical agenda, which, in the case that interests Fuller, is that of bringing the politics of knowledge production to the center of public arena (p. 11). Kuhn is seen as decisively contribut[ing] to reversing such a project, which, according to Fuller, has a history of 150 years and has been carried out by figures like Hegel, Comte, Weber, Peirce, Duhem, Russell, Popper and Feyerabend, among others (ibid.). These figures managed to [weave] their abstract arguments around a historical narrative punctuated by recognisable landmark episodes in Western civilization, (...) enabl[ing] a relatively large intellectual (...) public to find points of contact and contestation with what they had to say (p. 12). Kuhn and Conant Kuhn, it is maintained, not only shut the public out of the assessment of science by insulating in his work the production of scientific knowledge from external determinations, but also played, inadvertently, in the hands of James Bryant Conant. Conant, according to Fuller, had assumed the responsibility of carrying out a politically realist Cold War mission, namely, to defend American democracy against the New Dealers and the Communists by establishing and protecting the autonomy of science from the rest of society (pp. 33 34, 180). Conant saw the destabilising effect of making exaggerated demands on science which, in the course of the twentieth century, had developed into an industrial behemoth and, in Fuller s view, came to promote a matter of fact image of scientific practice (p. 214). He expected to bring the public closer to science, but also curb the public s high expectations for fear that science might be perverted, as it had happened in Nazi Germany and Soviet Russia (pp. 182 183). The public was supposed to get accustomed to science (p. 182), but not from too near. Future managers of science policy, the students of Conant s General Education course, were kept at a respectful distance. 3 They were not supposed to meddle into scientific affairs and second-guess Author: Vasso Kindi, University of Athens, Athens, Greece Social Epistemology ISSN 0269-1728 print/issn 1464-5297 online 2003 Taylor & Francis Ltd http://www.tandf.co.uk/journals DOI: 10.1080/0269172032000144180

210 VASSO KINDI the scientists (pp. 214 215). Criticism was discouraged. 4 The public was required to understand and not judge. The result was that the public accountability of science diminished just at the time when it was most needed, i.e. after the destructive effects of the use of science in the Second World War. Kuhn, according to Fuller, added an air of facticity (p. 152) to Conant s account, and became, therefore, an accomplice to these developments. Both as an instructor in the General Education course in Harvard and, subsequently, as a historian and philosopher of science, Kuhn offered the academic analogue of Conant s political vision (p. 169). 5 He insulated scientific practice from external determinations 6 concentrating on the internal conditions that make science possible. 7 He laid emphasis on the function of dogma in scientific research enhancing authority and restricting critical debate. He even restricted the historical basis of his model to examples drawn from the period between 1620 and 1920, so that the cases he examined would conform to the normative ideal that he had in mind 8 (p. 73). This normative ideal, backed up by an eclectic wandering into the history of science (what Fuller called hopscotching across the centuries ), served to give the impression that it is possible to understand the scientific turn of mind, regardless of the time and place in which science is practiced (p. 215). Consequently, the recent developments that relate to the industrial organisation of scientific research were brushed aside as not contributing to, or substantially affecting, Kuhn s model. Kuhn explicitly denied the need to change his account of science, in view of the contemporary scene, because, he said, his studying the nature of science is in the first instance a way of looking at the picture of knowledge. 9 Fuller finds what he calls retreat to the nature of knowledge, symptomatic of Kuhn s culturopathology, a state of uninvolvement and diminished cultural responsibility (pp. 397 398). Kuhn, Fuller maintains, could afford to disengage aristocratically from his responsibilities to society because of his privileged position in the academia and the success of his book (p. 399). He retreated into philosophy, leaving the world alone, and turning philosophy into an underlabourer and a simple accountant of science, an accountant that remains, nevertheless, completely unaccountable (p. 300). So Fuller paints the following picture: Conant had a clear Cold War mission that required the insulation of science from the rest of society. He hired for this mission Thomas Kuhn who just happened to be there and gave him the opportunity to provide the academic analogue to Conant s political project. Kuhn was inadvertently recruited and, given his culturopathology and privileged position, developed an account of science that managed to fit the demands of the times. The villain of the story is clearly James Bryant Conant; Kuhn was simply the aristocratic fool who turned out, however, to be highly successful in promoting the conservative cause of maintaining science s status quo for reasons that should not be attributed to him but rather to others who happened to think and do the relevant significant things at the time (pp. 397 399). Talk of coincidence or the cunning, not of reason, but of the conservative cause. Questioning Fuller s methodology The evidence provided by Fuller for his allegations and explanatory hypotheses is very thin, but he may not have had the need for any thicker. Fuller s professed aim is to write philosophical history of the Hegelian kind, which, apart from its reflexive dimension noted and admired by Fuller, is also marked by the little interest it shows

KUHN S CONSERVATISM 211 in the mere facts. Speculative or metaphysical philosophies of history of the Hegelian type look behind the appearance of haphazard facts to discover the underlying plot in the unfolding of history. If this is Fuller s undertaking, he needs to address the standard criticism leveled against it: teleology, a priorism, mystical guesswork. 10 At least in Hegel s case, or in the case of theology, it was the role of Reason or God in history that needed vindication; in the case of Fuller it is only Conant s malevolent plotting. To cater for this project Fuller indulges in making overhasty and precarious connections. For instance, in the chapter aptly entitled The Pilgrimage from Plato to NATO and in just one paragraph, Fuller connects what he describes as the Athenians taste for risky arguments to the development of a volatile foreign policy, which led to the downfall of Athens in the Peloponnesian Wars. He then offers an account of what he takes to be Plato s solution: Plato concluded that the main culprits were the Sophists (...). [His] solution, as detailed in the Republic, was to sequester students of the dialectic in the tranquil setting of the Academy (...). The main way of instilling the requisite patience was to have students write down their thoughts before opening their mouths. (...) Plato held that in a world where fondness for free speech can have such disastrous consequences, it might not be such a bad idea to create a little distance between one s thoughts and one s words. (...) [W]riting manufactured a sphere of delayed responses and deferred gratifications that has since become the life of the mind, a place where the conscious and the intentional are allowed free reign. (pp. 47 48) From the Sophists to writing and the life of the conscious mind, across centuries, disciplines and levels of thought, Fuller is putting forward an overwhelming ocean of ideas from sociology, philosophy, history, art history, economics, linguistics, psychology, psychoanalysis, politics, science and science studies, in order to build a case for Kuhn s conservatism. Often, the only qualification of these ideas is that they might not be so bad in rendering plausible Fuller s initial assumption or prejudice. Even inconsistencies that should have given Fuller a pause are either disregarded or treated ingeniously. A case in point is Kuhn s so-called marginalisation of prescriptivism (p. 292). Being included in the Platonist cult, Kuhn is supposed to be a prescriptivist. Yet, being assigned to Conant s mission, he has to respect science s status quo and leave his prescriptions aside. Fuller, instead of reconsidering his overall thesis in view of these conflicting statements, credits Kuhn with a Faustian bargain. [A] Faustian bargain may have been struck in Kuhn s mind: What science lost in its normative desirability, it replaced by providing a stable military industrial infrastructure and virtually the only source of legitimate authority for an increasingly fragmented and volatile populace. In light of these stakes, a policy of strategic vagueness on Kuhn s part would allow for a tame misreading of the book that would help ward off the drastic calls for the disestablishment of science (...) (p. 74) (emphasis added). Was Kuhn a conservative? Kuhn is proclaimed a conservative for refraining from being a political activist at a time that required, according to Fuller, not understanding but criticising science. 11 Kuhn sided with the positivists, Fuller says, giving prominence to an internalist account that deterred the requisite external evaluation of science. He was their Trojan horse (p. 288), smuggling in the radical times of the 1960s their reactionary agenda that had previously fallen into disrepute.

212 VASSO KINDI I am not going to discuss the progressiveness of logical positivism or whether Kuhn had in any way contributed to challenging its hegemony in philosophy of science. 12 Nor will I discuss whether Kuhn had to be a political activist of a certain kind 13 to be worthy of admiration. Strangely for Fuller given his explicit anti- Platonism he seems to still hanker, as Rorty says, for a state of affairs that connects intimately virtue and knowledge. 14 I will discuss what I consider Fuller s main argument in favour of the claim that Kuhn was a conservative, namely the emphasis on tradition in Kuhn s account of science. 15 I do not so much object to classifying Kuhn as a conservative (as long as this characterisation is not understood politically 16 ). Yet, I do object in taking this characterisation to be a reproach. Actually, I take it that being conservative, in the sense I intend here, breaks the spell of the rationalist illusion. Standard classifications place tradition on the antipodes of reason. Tradition is associated with commitment, trust, authority, habit, prejudice, and dogma. Reason is associated with critical deliberation, openness, independent and impartial judgment. Tradition is supposed to be observed not challenged. It is handed down with respect through propaganda and indoctrination or just mere inertia. Reason lives in argument; it thrives in disagreement. Its exercise, governed by rational principles, shapes rational conduct, offers intelligence and builds free minds. Tradition is passive and cumbersome; reason is active, intrepid and sharp. Fuller repeats this classification in Table 6 of his book, which illustrates scientific rationality before the Great Kuhnian Scrumble (p. 293). In the Enlightenment conception of rationality that Fuller presents, he assigns tradition to the image of the irrational and contrasts it with critique, which he assigns to the image of the rational. Kuhn is seen as breaching these standard distinctions. Kuhn wants tradition during normal science and critique in the revolutionary phase. But this critique, according to Fuller, is hardly rational. Kuhn [takes] responsibility for the choice between scientific languages out of the hands of self-conscious deliberators and placing it in the invisible hand of the Planck effect (p. 301). So, according to Fuller, Kuhn s preference for tradition makes him a conservative and an opponent of the Enlightenment. As for Kuhn s focus on scientific revolutions, which would normally place him on the Enlightenment side that bred the great political revolutions of the eighteenth century, Fuller has a different view. Relying on John Pocock, the historian of political ideas, he credits Kuhn with a romantic view of history (p. 308) that requires heroic revolutionary agents [to disrupt] the otherwise inexorable reproduction of the past (ibid.). I really doubt that Kuhn had indeed such a view of history, given that there are no heroic figures in his model and nothing inexorable in it. But I will not pursue this question further. I will turn to the rationalist illusion of the self-conscious deliberators. Michael Oakeshott, the conservative political philosopher, gives this description of the view that I believe Fuller endorses: In order that a man s conduct should be wholly rational, he must be supposed to have the power of first imagining and choosing a purpose to pursue, of defining that purpose clearly and selecting fit means to achieve it; and this power must be wholly independent, not only of tradition and the uncontrolled relics of his fortuitous experience of the world, but also of the activity itself to which it is a preliminary. 17 But Oakeshott continues: My view is that this is not a satisfactory notion of rational conduct because it is not a satisfactory account of any sort of conduct 18 (first

KUHN S CONSERVATISM 213 emphasis in the original, second one added). Oakeshott, but also Wittgenstein and Kuhn, have stressed in their work the importance of training, of precedent use and paradigm in following a rule and setting up any kind of practice. One cannot learn a language or how to do scientific research in the abstract, by theoretically understanding principles and rules. One needs to be taught by being exposed to exemplary and particular applications of rules against the background of tradition. This is how practices are shaped and new traditions emerge. [A] person goes by a sign-post only in so far as there exists a regular use of sign-posts, a custom. 19 To obey a rule, to make a report, to give an order, to play a game of chess, are customs (uses, institutions). To understand a language means to be a master of a technique. 20 But if tradition in this sense, far from being an impediment, becomes a condition of any human activity, is this activity rational? Kuhn s radical innovation was to bring these considerations to bear on the paradigm of rational activity, scientific practice. He was not always consistent, especially after the vehement criticism that he received from those who blamed him for irrationality, but he tried to show that the rationality of scientific practice is not to be judged by atemporal, abstract criteria applied in a Procrustean fashion. In that respect, we may need to adjust our notion of rationality, 21 in the direction of avoiding an idealised conception. 22 The rationality of a certain conduct is not to be assessed by an imposed contrived blueprint, but it emerges from the activity itself. So, Kuhn may have been a Burkean conservative in the company of Oakeshott and Wittgenstein, 23 but he was truly a radical for bringing into relief the embeddedness and indebtedness of science in and to tradition. Notes 1. Fuller, S., 2000, Thomas Kuhn: A Philosophical History of Our Time (Chicago, IL: The University of Chicago Press). All subsequent references to this book will be made in the text by the page number in parentheses. 2. Kuhn, T.S., 1970, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, 2nd edition (Chicago, IL: The University of Chicago Press). 3. That was facilitated by a hands-on approach, which was simultaneously hands-off. Opening the laboratories to the public certainly gives the impression that the scientists have nothing to hide. As a result, that gesture of openness may be just enough to discourage the public from further probing behind the scenes (p. 223). 4. Criticism was seen as verging on treason (pp. 172, 177). 5. Fuller says that Kuhn became the normal scientist in the political paradigm constructed by Conant (p. 5). 6. These external determinations from which science was cut off included, according to Fuller, not only society but also nature. Science was supposed to float unchecked from any kind of restrain relying solely on the authority of its internal tradition (p. 395). Yet, despite Kuhn s professed commitment to an internalist account of science, one should find relevant Kuhn s strong reservations regarding Ben- David s internalist account: Apparently [Ben-David] fears that the slightest concession [to the intervention of external social forces] would open doors to the sort of analyses science as an epiphenomenon of social and economic development once associated with Marxist historiography. In Kuhn, T.S., 1972, Scientific growth: reflections on Ben-David s Scientific Role. Minerva 10, 166 178, p. 168. 7. Fuller claims that whereas Conant drew a distinction between his own activities and the practising scientist, a distinction reminiscent of the Platonic one between the guardian and the philosophical castes, Kuhn did to Conant what Freud did to Plato, namely, internalise the protector in the manner of a superego (p. 182). 8. Elsewhere, instead of a normative ideal Fuller speaks of a mythical image that Kuhn constructs in order to appropriate history in his model. A more charitably disposed reader, Fuller allows, would

214 VASSO KINDI speak of a Weberian ideal type that is invoked by Kuhn to sensitise us to salient features of the object of inquiry (p. 195). For instance, Fuller believes that Kuhn developed the concept of normal science by superimposing different perspectives of normal science from different moments in history to construct a mythical image. Be it mythical image or ideal type, Kuhn is criticised not only as a covert Platonist but as a counterfeiter of history and an inventor of mythical constructs. 9. Sigurdsson, S., 1990, The nature of scientific knowledge: an interview with Thomas Kuhn. Harvard Review of Books, winter 18 25, p. 24, cited in Fuller 2000, p. 388. 10. See, for instance, Walsh, W.H., 1967, Philosophy of History (New York: Harper Torchbooks). 11. This is a strange contrast to draw. How can one criticise science without understanding it first? The only understanding that Fuller finds legitimate is understanding the role of science in the wide context of social life. Concentrating on an internalist understanding of science of the kind that Kuhn offered, is not seen as an innocent, superfluous addition but rather as a move that diverts attention from what is important and serious resulting thereof in strengthening the conservative side. 12. Fuller would acknowledge that Kuhn s Structure was used to discredit positivism but he wouldn t credit the author. Apart from Kuhn s political and academic affiliations, Fuller sees him as largely innocent of the details of logical positivism (note 51, p. 286). 13. I am saying of a certain kind because, according to Fuller, Kuhn, by being enlisted in Conant s mission, got involved in the political developments of the period, he took sides, if only passively and by inertia. I suppose Fuller would consider him an activist of the passive kind. Hence the characterisation of conservative. 14. Rorty, R., 1999, Philosophy and Social Hope (London: Penguin Books), p. 19. The idea that you can evaluate a writer s philosophical views by reference to their political utility seems to me a version of the bad Platonic Straussian idea that we cannot have justice until philosophers become kings or kings philosophers (ibid., p. 18). 15. I will set aside the puzzling suggestion that Fuller seems to be making in note 52 (p. 287). He seems to be implying that engagement in philosophical debate, in contrast with interest in the sociology of science, stamps one with conservative inclinations. I suppose philosophy is seen as inextricably linked to Platonism, whereas sociology to social criticism and responsibility. 16. I am not going to discuss Kuhn s alleged political conservatism for reasons of economy. My impression, however, for all it is worth, given mainly my personal contact with Kuhn and the long autobiographical interview that he gave in Athens where he talks about his family, education, and political orientation, is that Kuhn was what Rorty calls the typical left-wing Democrat professor (Rorty 1999, p. 19). Rorty sees this group of progressivists in a war ( tiny, unmarket, cultural war ) with the postmodernists who share Noam Chomsky s view of the United States as run by a corrupt elite (...) and think that nothing will change unless we get rid of humanism, liberal individualism, and technologism (ibid.). Despite his Popperianism, Fuller can be counted among the ranks of this postmodernist camp. Moreover, if Kuhn s personal convictions and Kuhn s own assessment of his involvement in politics are completely disregarded, one would be reminded of the standard accusation of objectively helping the class enemy that the Communist parties in Europe used to make against their dissident members. 17. Oakeshott, M., 1991, Rational conduct. in Rationalism in Politics and Other Essays (Indianapolis, IN: Liberty Press), p. 105. 18. ibid. p. 109. 19. Wittgenstein, L., 1958, Philosophical Investigations, translated by G.E.M. Anscombe (Oxford: Blackwell), 198. 20. ibid., 199. For a recent discussion of the rule-following issue in relation to Wittgenstein see the collection of articles Rule-Following and Meaning, edited by Alexander Miller and Crispin Wright, 2002 (Chesham: Acumen). 21. See Kuhn, T.S., 1971, Notes on Lakatos. In R.C. Buck and R.S. Cohen (eds), PSA 1970: In Memory of Rudolf Carnap, Proceedings of the 1970 Biennial Meeting Philosophy of Science Association, Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science, Volume 8 (Boston: D. Reidel), pp. 137 146, p. 144. 22. Toulmin calls it mathematical rationality. Toulmin, S., 2001, Return to Reason (Boston, MA: Harvard University Press), p. 205. 23. Wittgenstein was also labelled a conservative. See Nyiri, J.C., 1982, Wittgenstein s later work in relation to conservatism. In B. McGuinness (ed.), Wittgenstein and his Times (Chicago, IL: The University of Chicago Press).