INTERNATIONAL SUMMER SCHOOL FOR SEMIOTIC AND STRUCTURAL STUDIES SUMMER SCHOOLS AND FESTIVAL: 25 YEARS SEMIOTICS IN IMATRA

Similar documents
1/8. The Third Paralogism and the Transcendental Unity of Apperception

Colloque Écritures: sur les traces de Jack Goody - Lyon, January 2008

Comments on Bence Nanay, Perceptual Content and the Content of Mental Imagery

On Recanati s Mental Files

Conclusion. One way of characterizing the project Kant undertakes in the Critique of Pure Reason is by

Self-Consciousness and Knowledge

Peirce and Semiotic an Introduction

The Observer Story: Heinz von Foerster s Heritage. Siegfried J. Schmidt 1. Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2011

Introduction SABINE FLACH, DANIEL MARGULIES, AND JAN SÖFFNER

Thomas Szanto: Bewusstsein, Intentionalität und mentale Repräsentation. Husserl und die analytische Philosophie des Geistes

Incommensurability and Partial Reference

The Nature of Time. Humberto R. Maturana. November 27, 1995.

Perception and Mind-Dependence Lecture 3

Necessity in Kant; Subjective and Objective

UNIT SPECIFICATION FOR EXCHANGE AND STUDY ABROAD

PHILOSOPHY PLATO ( BC) VVR CHAPTER: 1 PLATO ( BC) PHILOSOPHY by Dr. Ambuj Srivastava / (1)

By Tetsushi Hirano. PHENOMENOLOGY at the University College of Dublin on June 21 st 2013)

Ontological Categories. Roberto Poli

1. What is Phenomenology?

THE LOGICAL FORM OF BIOLOGICAL OBJECTS

KINDS (NATURAL KINDS VS. HUMAN KINDS)

What do our appreciation of tonal music and tea roses, our acquisition of the concepts

The Cognitive Nature of Metonymy and Its Implications for English Vocabulary Teaching

(Ulrich Schloesser/ Humboldt-Universität zu Berlin)

MAURICE MANDELBAUM HISTORY, MAN, & REASON A STUDY IN NINETEENTH-CENTURY THOUGHT THE JOHNS HOPKINS PRESS: BALTIMORE AND LONDON

Kant s Critique of Judgment

In his essay "Of the Standard of Taste," Hume describes an apparent conflict between two

Mind Association. Oxford University Press and Mind Association are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Mind.

ENVIRONMENTAL EXPERIENCE: Beyond Aesthetic Subjectivism and Objectivism

Martin, Gottfried: Plato s doctrine of ideas [Platons Ideenlehre]. Berlin: Verlag Walter de Gruyter, 1973

INTERVIEW: ONTOFORMAT Classical Paradigms and Theoretical Foundations in Contemporary Research in Formal and Material Ontology.

Towards a Phenomenology of Development

Edward Winters. Aesthetics and Architecture. London: Continuum, 2007, 179 pp. ISBN

Loughborough University Institutional Repository. This item was submitted to Loughborough University's Institutional Repository by the/an author.

Review of David Woodruff Smith and Amie L. Thomasson, eds., Phenomenology and the Philosophy of Mind, 2005, Oxford University Press.

Scientific Philosophy

THE STRUCTURALIST MOVEMENT: AN OVERVIEW

Heideggerian Ontology: A Philosophic Base for Arts and Humanties Education

SUMMARY BOETHIUS AND THE PROBLEM OF UNIVERSALS

Stones, Screens, and Spirits: Opacity and Transparency in Hegel and Beyond. (c) David Kolb, 2008 (unfinished lecture draft)

Notes on Gadamer, The Relevance of the Beautiful

IIL-HEGEL'S TREATMENT OF THE CATE- GORIES OF OUALITY.

observation and conceptual interpretation

Is Genetic Epistemology of Any Interest for Semiotics?

Nature's Perspectives

The phenomenological tradition conceptualizes

Phenomenology and Non-Conceptual Content

Übungen Simple past. Übung 1: Erkläre das simple past. Übung 2: Setze die richtige Form von to be (was / were) ein.

CARROLL ON THE MOVING IMAGE

SocioBrains THE INTEGRATED APPROACH TO THE STUDY OF ART

The identity theory of truth and the realm of reference: where Dodd goes wrong

Mass Communication Theory

Twentieth Excursus: Reference Magnets and the Grounds of Intentionality

Image and Imagination

Naïve realism without disjunctivism about experience

Arnheim and Ingarden on the Ontology of the Arts

What is Character? David Braun. University of Rochester. In "Demonstratives", David Kaplan argues that indexicals and other expressions have a

Habit, Semeiotic Naturalism, and Unity among the Sciences Aaron Wilson

The Language Revolution Russell Marcus Fall Class #7 Final Thoughts on Frege on Sense and Reference

Intersubjectivity and Language

Social Mechanisms and Scientific Realism: Discussion of Mechanistic Explanation in Social Contexts Daniel Little, University of Michigan-Dearborn

A Comprehensive Critical Study of Gadamer s Hermeneutics

Metaphors we live by. Structural metaphors. Orientational metaphors. A personal summary

The Language Revolution Russell Marcus Fall 2015

What is Postmodernism? What is Postmodernism?

My thesis is that not only the written symbols and spoken sounds are different, but also the affections of the soul (as Aristotle called them).

The Polish Peasant in Europe and America. W. I. Thomas and Florian Znaniecki

Mind, Thinking and Creativity

Action, Criticism & Theory for Music Education

[My method is] a science that studies the life of signs within society I shall call it semiology from the Greek semeion signs (Saussure)

Hear hear. Århus, 11 January An acoustemological manifesto

Practical Intuition and Rhetorical Example. Paul Schollmeier

Review of Krzysztof Brzechczyn, Idealization XIII: Modeling in History

In Defense of the Contingently Nonconcrete

UNIVERSITY OF TORONTO INSTRUCTORSHIPS IN PHILOSOPHY CUPE Local 3902, Unit 1 SUMMER SESSION 2019

du Châtelet s ontology: element, corpuscle, body

Information Seeking, Information Retrieval: Philosophical Points. Abstract. Introduction

WITHOUT QUALIFICATION: AN INQUIRY INTO THE SECUNDUM QUID

Four Characteristic Research Paradigms

Space, Time, and Interpretation

Categories and Schemata

Plato s work in the philosophy of mathematics contains a variety of influential claims and arguments.

THE PROBLEM OF NOVELTY IN C.S. PEIRCE'S AND A.N. WHITEHEAD'S THOUGHT

COMPUTER ENGINEERING SERIES

124 Philosophy of Mathematics

We know of the efforts of such philosophers as Frege and Husserl to undo the

KANT S TRANSCENDENTAL LOGIC

Composition, Counterfactuals, Causation

Community and Media: a Weakness of Phenomenology?

Department of Philosophy Florida State University

What Can Experimental Philosophy Do? David Chalmers

Natika Newton, Foundations of Understanding. (John Benjamins, 1996). 210 pages, $34.95.

Pierre Hadot on Philosophy as a Way of Life. Pierre Hadot ( ) was a French philosopher and historian of ancient philosophy,

Kuhn Formalized. Christian Damböck Institute Vienna Circle University of Vienna

Phenomenology Glossary

Culture, Space and Time A Comparative Theory of Culture. Take-Aways

138 Great Problems in Philosophy and Physics - Solved? Chapter 11. Meaning. This chapter on the web informationphilosopher.com/knowledge/meaning

6 The Analysis of Culture

Verity Harte Plato on Parts and Wholes Clarendon Press, Oxford 2002

Phenomenology and Structuralism PHIL 607 Fall 2011

Transcription:

INTERNATIONAL SUMMER SCHOOL FOR SEMIOTIC AND STRUCTURAL STUDIES SUMMER SCHOOLS AND FESTIVAL: 25 YEARS SEMIOTICS IN IMATRA Imatra, Finland, June 11 15, 2010 Symposium on the Interrelationships of Arts: Gesture, Genre and Gender Roman Ingarden s Objectivity vs. Subjectivity as a problem of Translatability Gabriel Pareyon Department of Musicology University of Helsinki The concept of Aristotelian purity, concerning the objective subjective debate, has been broadly treated from a plethora of perspectives. This lecture does not attempt to review such perspectives, but barely to analyze the Ingardean opposition of pure states of beings particularly from the view of aesthetics against a unstable notion of beings, whose ontologically fuzzy borders enable the concept of impurity. Roman Ingarden (1893 1970), a philosopher who developed and transformed many aspects of Husserlian phenomenology, conceived ontological stages of beings, similarly to physical states of matter in which a combination of quantities and qualities can be false or true in order to obtain a stable point of substances (see Wachter 2005:79 80). For Ingarden, substances appear on their immanent properties, but also they come clear from the kind of relationships they establish with other ontologies. This sort of phenomenology does make a radical difference regarding Husserl trascendental idealism, as Ingarden invites for a re-appraisal of the classical dialectics between realism and idealism, with a corresponding relationship between main and subsidiary meanings. Ingardean aesthetics are strongly based on the assumption that works of art do exist. Obviously, this belief is highly idiosyncratic. The concepts of work, art, and artwork as they are understood by most of the modern tratises on the topic are concepts tightly involved with the evolution of culture in the European countries and their historical extensions and areas of influence. In this context, imaginary and physically located musea are precincts for the artworks, which are milestones for the construction of idiosyncrasy, and the strengthening of cultural dominance. A good 1/5

example of this is the preservation of the standard meter rod in Paris, which usually is not considered a work of art, but has an analogous function of objective reference, like a masterpiece. Many other objects can similarly be mentioned as imaginary and tangible sources for objective reference and dominance. Equivalent concepts of museum already have been explored and criticized by Ludwig Wittgenstein, in philosophy; by Rush Rhees in linguistics, and by William van Orman Quine, specifically in its semantic and ontological implications. After this criticism it can be abstracted that the supposed purity of ontologies is very depending on the kind of museum one desires to build, not necessarily as an inferential construction, but merely as an imposed form of reality, in the sense we impose words, symbols or objects to others. To this view, will and intentionality (as a power of will) are fundamental for understanding the interplay between objectivity and subjectivity, on construing aesthetic ontologies. Influenced by Hegel s categories of Pure Being, Ingarden (1962, 1964) thinks that artworks exist in an Objective purely intentional manner. According to this idea, objectivity and subjectivity are opposed forms of existence, parallel to the opposition between realism and idealism. Ingarden believes on intrinsec values of things, with pure-intentional qualifiers (cf. Gumpel 1994:25), by contrast to representational references. Consequently, Ingarden concerns about the kind of act that generates pure objectivity, as an act of meaning. 1 Nevertheless, a doubt arises when considering a representation as a mental value in itself. This consideration, improbable in the Ingardean conceptualization, has indeed its own place as synecdoche: an efficient and pervasive device for the construction of both, objective and subjective perspectives on things. Synecdoche is a very basic transaction of the mind, importantly contributing to establish ontologies in the Ingardean way of the term. Adam Wegrzecki (1994:220), a specialist on Ingarden s aesthetic theories, defines ontology as the central domain of philosophy to which other its parts directly or indirectly refer. Thus, ontologies operate in philosophy as synecdoche does in language, pointing the sense of the general into the particular and viceversa. 1 Referred to as Meinungsakt in Ingarden 1931. 2/5

The many affinities and similarities among different sign systems, like those found across the interrelationships of arts, are embedded into a transversal, synecdochic intersemiosis. An important question, from this view, is whether Ingarden s pure objectivities lie basically on the impossibility of translation, therefore being absolute self-referential constructions. In a such case, it would be impossible to translate pure intentional objectivities into something else. It might nonetheless be useful to consider that a same kind of act of meaning can also have twofold or manifold sorts of expression and representation. This is not to say only that an act of meaning can be interpreted through subjective ways. Rather, it is to point out that an act of meaning even as a pure intentionality can have the same kind of trigger another act of meaning has. If so, then a same state of the same mind can simultaneously produce compatible substages of meaning, in different, yet correlated networks. This is the very point of this lecture: since synesthesia and analogy are possible in this manner, then how can we consider a pure intentional stage a of mindobject e.g. a musical chord independently from a simultaneous stage of another directly related mind-object e.g. a visual, intuitive form of the same chord. A relevant question at this point is whether are there pure objectivities translatable into other pure objectivities. From the Ingardean point of view this is impossible. As a matter of fact, Ingarden (1962:229) does not talk about any intersemiotic translation between arts, but about a kinship (verwandtschaft) or reconstruction mean (Rekonstruktionsmittel) between different aesthetic fields. At the beginning of this lecture I promised I would not go forward into the so discussed Aristotelian purity of beings. Nevertheless, I would like to call your attention to the idea of phisical purity, very popular during the Ingarden formative period as intellectual. I address, therefore, not to Aristotle nor to any Peripatetic philosopher, but to an influential thinker who published many articles on music philosophy before Ingarden s ontology of artworks: [T]he Greeks were a Southern people, on whose temperaments the purely physical experience of music, especially of singing, would be far more direct and far more powerful than it is upon people like ourselves whose Northern temperament has in the course of centuries developed a more consciously intellectual attitude towards the art. 3/5

This is Edward J. Dent (1928:313) words; the sort of mandatory source for any European aesthetician writing on music during the World Between Wars period. It is difficult to assert that Dent could directly influentiate Ingarden in this particular. But it is quite notorious that this Positivistic view on music was very generalized in those years, in which physicality of things including biological and geographical issues embraced the meaning of aesthetic and cultural values. Presumably, Ingarden could keep this kind of focus during the development of his Ontology of Art (1962). However, one may see Ingarden effort to explain the existence of things particularly the aesthetic heteronomies, in the light of his own ultimate ideas, in which he considers a germinal notion of translation rather as an efficient reorientation of the senses, from the ordinary similarities perceived in the world, towards the original heteronomies of the world. 2 If we consider these heteronomies as memories, then the Ingardean dichotomy between Objectivity and Subjectivity can sufficiently be assimilated to a problem of translatability. Contemplating the most general features of aesthetic phenomena, realism and idealism cannot be pure oppositions but aspects of a single process of cognition in different strata. 3 Furthermore, realism can be resumed as an empirical extreme of idealism, and idealism can be resumed as a pre-operative extreme of realism. Both kind of systems of knowledge are mutually associated by a synecdoche, featuring main tasks of mental order and categorisation. Consequently, one may suggest that the supposed opposition between objectivity and subjectivity, raises a problem of existential categories, not in absolute terms, but in terms of affinity and self-affinity between cognitive domains and mental spaces. Last but not least, it must be stressed that Ingardean purity should be regarded very appart from the Aristotelian one: Ingarden explicitly recognizes as pure objective ontologies those qualities that remain untouchable in translation. This point is also clear in Roman Jakobson; for him there is something that dissappears in every translation; something remains, but something is completely gone with 2 This idea (Ingarden 1962:319) appears originally in the following words: Infolgedessen hat der Zuschauer es nicht direkt mit Personen, Dingen und Vorgängen zu tun, sondern lediglich mit deren Abbildern. Indessen: indem der Zuschauer diese Abbilder erfaßt, stellt er sich unwillkürlich auf das Abgebildete selbst ein, sieht in den Bildern die betreffenden Personen und Dinge selbst, ohne sich ausdrücklich zum Bewußtsein zu bringen, daß diese Gegenstände ihm, streng genommen, nicht selbstgegenwärtig sind. 3 Ingarden usually admits too few strata (Schichten) for his aesthetic theory on pure objective intentionalities. This fact has been noticed as a hindrance for its development and analytical application (see for example Simons 1994:138 139, and Thomasson 2005:36 37). 4/5

translation: what is gone, according to Ingarden, is ontological purity. From this perspective, for any translation a lost purity may have been obliterated by another pure ontology. Purity, in this case, should be understood as a deviation from homology, and as a stage in a process of self-affinity, within its variated degrees of analogy and heterology. Sources Dent, Edward J. (1928). The Relation of Music to Human Progress, The Musical Quarterly, vol. 14, no. 3; pp. 307 319. Gumpel, Liselotte (1994). Language as Bearer of Meaning: The Phenomenology of Roman Ingarden in (W. Galewicz, E. Ströker & W. Strożewski, eds.) Kunst und Ontologie: Für Roman Ingarden zum 100. Geburtstag, Editions Rodopi, Amsterdam; 21 57. Ingarden, Roman (1931). Das literarische Kunstwerk. Eine Untersuchung aus dem Grenzgebiet der Ontologie, Logik und Literaturwissenschaft, Max Niemeyer, Halle. Ingarden, Roman (1962). Untersuchungen zur Ontologie der Kunst: Musikwerk Bild Architektur Film, Max Niemeyer Verlag, Tübingen. Simons, Peter M. (1994). Strata in Ingarden s Ontology in (W. Galewicz, E. Ströker & W. Strożewski, eds.) Kunst und Ontologie: Für Roman Ingarden zum 100. Geburtstag, Editions Rodopi, Amsterdam; 119 140. Thomasson, Amie L. (2005). Ingarden and the Ontology of Cultural Objects in (A. Chrudzimski, ed.) Existence, Culture, and Persons: the Ontology of Roman Ingarden, Ontos Verlag, Heusenstamm bei Frankfurt; 115 136. Wachter, Daniel von (2005). Roman Ingarden s Ontology: Existential Dependence, Substances, Ideas, and Other Things Empiricists Do not Like in (A. Chrudzimski, ed.) Existence, Culture, and Persons: the Ontology of Roman Ingarden, Ontos Verlag, Heusenstamm bei Frankfurt; 55 82. Wegrzecki, Adam (1994). The Function of Ontology and Experience in Roman Ingarden s Axiological Investigations in (W. Galewicz, E. Ströker & W. Strożewski, eds.) Kunst und Ontologie: Für Roman Ingarden zum 100. Geburtstag, Editions Rodopi, Amsterdam; 219 228. 5/5