A Happy Ending: Happiness in the Nicomachean Ethics and Consolation of Philosophy. Wesley Spears

Similar documents
Aristotle on the Human Good

The Doctrine of the Mean

In Utilitarianism, John Stuart Mill asserts that the principles of

On Happiness Aristotle

Nicomachean Ethics. p. 1. Aristotle. Translated by W. D. Ross. Book II. Moral Virtue (excerpts)

Nicomachean Ethics. Aristotle

VIRTUE ETHICS-ARISTOTLE

International Journal of Advancements in Research & Technology, Volume 4, Issue 11, November ISSN

13th International Scientific and Practical Conference «Science and Society» London, February 2018 PHILOSOPHY

that causes desolation, spoken of through the prophet Daniel let the reader understand then let those who are in Judea flee to the mountains.

Download Aristotle's Nicomachean Ethics (Focus Philosophical Library Series) Epub

Intelligible Matter in Aristotle, Aquinas, and Lonergan. by Br. Dunstan Robidoux OSB

The Human Intellect: Aristotle s Conception of Νοῦς in his De Anima. Caleb Cohoe

COURSE SYLLABUS. He psuche ta onta pos esti panta. Aristotle, De Anima 431 b21

1/9. The B-Deduction

Guide to the Republic as it sets up Plato s discussion of education in the Allegory of the Cave.

Title[ 一般論文 ]Is Mill an Anti-Hedonist? 京都大学文学部哲学研究室紀要 : PROSPECTUS (2011), 14:

Guiding Principles for the Arts Grades K 12 David Coleman

Aesthetics Mid-Term Exam Review Guide:

Aristotle and Human Nature

0:24 Arthur Holmes (AH): Aristotle s ethics 2:18 AH: 2:43 AH: 4:14 AH: 5:34 AH: capacity 7:05 AH:

Colonnade Program Course Proposal: Explorations Category

1/8. The Third Paralogism and the Transcendental Unity of Apperception

Plato s Forms. Feb. 3, 2016

Why Pleasure Gains Fifth Rank: Against the Anti-Hedonist Interpretation of the Philebus 1

PHI 3240: Philosophy of Art

Are There Two Theories of Goodness in the Republic? A Response to Santas. Rachel Singpurwalla

On Sense Perception and Theory of Recollection in Phaedo

Heideggerian Ontology: A Philosophic Base for Arts and Humanties Education

Jacek Surzyn University of Silesia Kant s Political Philosophy

Always More Than One Art: Jean-Luc Nancy's <em>the Muses</em>

Simulated killing. Michael Lacewing

SUMMARY BOETHIUS AND THE PROBLEM OF UNIVERSALS

CONCERNING music there are some questions

CANZONIERE VENTOUX PETRARCH S AND MOUNT. by Anjali Lai

The Theory and Practice of Virtue Education Edited by Tom Harrison and David I. Walker *

Truth and Method in Unification Thought: A Preparatory Analysis

In order to enrich our experience of great works of philosophy and literature we will include, whenever feasible, speakers, films and music.

Japan Library Association

ARISTOTLE. PHILO 381(W) Sec. 051[4810] Fall 2009 Professor Adluri Monday/Wednesday, 7:00-8:15pm

SYSTEM-PURPOSE METHOD: THEORETICAL AND PRACTICAL ASPECTS Ramil Dursunov PhD in Law University of Fribourg, Faculty of Law ABSTRACT INTRODUCTION

Dawn M. Phillips The real challenge for an aesthetics of photography

Introduction to Drama

Objective vs. Subjective

No (I, p. 208f)

Creative Actualization: A Meliorist Theory of Values

Pierre Hadot on Philosophy as a Way of Life. Pierre Hadot ( ) was a French philosopher and historian of ancient philosophy,

Aristotle. By Sarah, Lina, & Sufana

Adam Smith and The Theory of Moral Sentiments

Valuable Particulars

Proverbs 31 : Mark 9 : Sermon

FOLLY. Fools, Ignorance and Nonsense 1. ESSENCE Ignorance is the night of the mind, a night without moon or star. Confucius (B.C.

O ne of the most influential aspects of

Humanities 116: Philosophical Perspectives on the Humanities

POLSC201 Unit 1 (Subunit 1.1.3) Quiz Plato s The Republic

Marx, Gender, and Human Emancipation

The phenomenological tradition conceptualizes

Ovid s Revisions: e Editor as Author. Francesca K. A. Martelli. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. ISBN: $95.

Escapism and Luck. problem of moral luck posed by Joel Feinberg, Thomas Nagel, and Bernard Williams. 2

Mind Association. Oxford University Press and Mind Association are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Mind.

BENTHAM AND WELFARISM. What is the aim of social policy and the law what ends or goals should they aim to bring about?

Practical Intuition and Rhetorical Example. Paul Schollmeier

REBUILD MY HOUSE. A Pastor s Guide to Building or Renovating a Catholic Church ARTHUR C. LOHSEN, AIA

Wagner s The Ring of the Nibelung focuses on several types of love relationships,

The Academic Animal is Just an Analogy: Against the Restrictive Account of Hegel s Spiritual Animal Kingdom Miguel D. Guerrero

We study art in order to understand more about the culture that produced it.

CONTINGENCY AND TIME. Gal YEHEZKEL

Immanuel Kant Critique of Pure Reason

The Collected Dialogues Plato

NOTES ON THE METHODS OF INQUIRY OF PLATO AND ARISTOTLE 373

REVIEW ARTICLE IDEAL EMBODIMENT: KANT S THEORY OF SENSIBILITY

Nicomachean Ethics. by Aristotle 350 BC. translated by W. D. Ross. (public domain text at:

THE TIME OF OUR LIVES: ARISTOTLE ON TIME, TEMPORAL PERCEPTION, RECOLLECTION, AND HABITUATION. MICHAEL BRUDER, B.A., M.A. A Thesis

web address: address: Description

J.S. Mill s Notion of Qualitative Superiority of Pleasure: A Reappraisal

Ed. Carroll Moulton. Vol. 1. New York: Charles Scribner's Sons, p COPYRIGHT 1998 Charles Scribner's Sons, COPYRIGHT 2007 Gale

Self-Consciousness and Knowledge

Discovering the Skills of Writing

THE ROLE OF THE PATHE IN ARISTOTLE S CONCEPTION OF VIRTUE

QUESTION 7. The Circumstances of Human Acts

The Importance of Music Education. Ken Petress. Deciding what is taught in American schools is the province of teachers, principals, local school

Philosophy of Mind and Metaphysics Lecture III: Qualitative Change and the Doctrine of Temporal Parts

Nature's Perspectives

Chapter 6. The role of pleasure in making eudaimonia final and self-sufficient. The final reconsideration

Gadamer a philosophical rationale to approach teaching

Article On the Nature of & Relation between Formless God & Form: Part 2: The Identification of the Formless God with Lesser Form

Plato: Bringing Justice to Light. Plato BCE Republic, ca BCE

(Pre-print of text with page numbers follows the first text from Word for citation purposes. First text is given for legibility).

from Self-Reliance by Ralph Waldo Emerson

Lecture 12 Aristotle on Knowledge of Principles

(Courtesy of Michelle M.J. Aquing. Used with permission.) The Artist. The artist has been a mystery to many of us: unexplainably driven in his work;

Cambridge University Press The Theory of Moral Sentiments - Adam Smith Excerpt More information

ARISTOTLE AND THE UNITY CONDITION FOR SCIENTIFIC DEFINITIONS ALAN CODE [Discussion of DAVID CHARLES: ARISTOTLE ON MEANING AND ESSENCE]

QUESTION 49. The Substance of Habits

SOCRATES AND ARISTOPHANES BY LEO STRAUSS

Hamletmachine: The Objective Real and the Subjective Fantasy. Heiner Mueller s play Hamletmachine focuses on Shakespeare s Hamlet,

An Aristotelian Puzzle about Definition: Metaphysics VII.12 Alan Code

Care of the self: An Interview with Alexander Nehamas

Happiness - Essays On The Meaning Of Life By Carl Hilty

PH th Century Philosophy Ryerson University Department of Philosophy Mondays, 3-6pm Fall 2010

Transcription:

A Happy Ending: Happiness in the Nicomachean Ethics and Consolation of Philosophy By Wesley Spears For Samford University, UFWT 102, Dr. Jason Wallace, on May 6, 2010

A Happy Ending The matters of philosophy are often more transcendental, leaving philosophers frequently criticized for their lack of practicality. To be sure, Aristotle discusses different types of wisdom and virtue, Boethius pens lengthy poems espousing philosophical and theological principles, and these ideas do not seem to be easily applicable to everyday life. However, one issue discussed in Aristotle s Nicomachean Ethics and Boethius The Consolation of Philosophy is of extreme relevance: happiness. Both texts wrestle with this fundamental question: what is happiness? Aristotle begins his investigation with the assertion that happiness is that end which has no other end in mind. Boethius begins his investigation not out of philosophical inquiry in Consolation but out of distress as an exiled prisoner. Aristotle and Boethius both seek to identify that which is certainly not happiness before attempting to identify that which is happiness. In the end, Aristotle determines happiness to be the persistent activity of virtue as it is the participation in the Good. Boethius builds upon many of Aristotle s constructions, assuming that the Good is God and participation in him is true happiness. Therefore, in Consolation Boethius affirms and challenges (or Christianizes) Aristotle s Nicomachean definition of happiness. These two texts approach their search for happiness differently. The Nicomachean Ethics has no running narrative and simply begins the philosophical query into such things as happiness, but there is an obvious narrative in Consolation that leads Boethius to inquire after happiness. Whereas Aristotle begins his search by identifying his objective as discovering that to which all things aim, 1 Boethius is in prison far from any sort of Academy distraught over his circumstance, weeping with the Muses. Lady Philosophy visits Boethius character, declaring him ill (by which she means that he is unhappy) and in need of treatment. What is his 1 Aristotle, Joe Sachs, trans., Nichomachean Ethics (Newburyport, MA: Focus Publishing, 2002), 1. 1

illness? Philosophy says No I know the other cause, or rather the major cause of your illness [read: unhappiness]: you have forgotten your true nature. 2 She says that Boethius has clearly suffered greatly, but there is no cause whatsoever for unhappiness in his downfall. 3 So then discovering his true nature seems to be understanding why he should not be unhappy he needs to arrive at a correct understanding of happiness. The Consolation pair begins to investigate happiness in a similar way to the Nicomachean inquiry, though with different conclusions. In patterning so many assertions in Consolation on Nicomachean Ethics, the origin of Boethius understanding of happiness is, to an extent, in Aristotle. Before defining what they believe happiness to be, both Boethius and Aristotle identify that which is not happiness: namely those things that can be taken away. Aristotle identifies wealth, pleasure, honor, health, and other such temporal obsessions as not being happiness. Wealth, to the Nicomachean Aristotle, deserves a secondary place, and is not true happiness because there are certainly human beings who do without wealth and are happy. 4 Likewise, he says of pleasure that it is not happiness because it is not the name of a particular sort of activity, that one can take pleasure in many things. 5 It follows that there must be a more complete 6 thing in which to take pleasure that must be true happiness. Honor also is lacking, for people seem to pursue honor in order to be convinced that they themselves are good, and they are seeking to be honored by those who are truly good. 7 Honor, then, is only an imitation of 2 Anicius Boethius, Victor Watts, trans., The Consolation of Philosophy (London: Penguin Books, 1999), 20. 3 John Marenbon, Boethius (New York: Oxford University Press, 2003), 102. 4 Francis Sparshott, Taking Life Seriously: A Study of the Argument of Nicomachean Ethics (Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1994), 60. 5 Ibid., 59. 6 That which Aristotle values the most is that which is complete. This is why he often discusses complete virtue and complete life (Aristotle, Sachs, trans, Ethics, 11-12.) among other things. 7 Aristotle, Sachs, trans., Ethics, 5. 2

that on account of which honor is sought 8 which is what is happy. Health also is not a source of happiness for that is to be happy by chance, and for what is greatest and most beautiful [read: happiness] to be left to chance would be too discordant. 9 A final thing denied by Aristotle as happiness is the concept of amusement. He calls much of the above amusements and claims that, it is absurd to suppose that the end (of life) is amusement and that we toil all our life long for the sake of amusing ourselves. 10 Therefore, Aristotle can be understood as saying that such temporal things are not true happiness. Boethius also denies these things wealth, position, power, fame, pleasure 11 as true happiness, coming to the same conclusion as Aristotle. One of the assertions that Consolation makes about happiness is that it is something that leaves man free of want and selfsufficient. 12 It is by this criterion that Boethius eliminates certain things as happiness just as Aristotle did previously. Wealth claims to fulfill this requirement for a human being, but it breaks this promise and can thus not be happiness. Money cannot be self-sufficient because it has no inherent property such as to stop it being taken away from those who possess it, against their will. 13 Consolation also condemns the enjoyment of fame and honor as happiness before the present misfortune of Boethius. This sort of worldly fame does not matter in any sense or perspective, for if the whole of a man dies fame is nothing at all and even if the mind stays 8 Thomas Aquinas, C.I. Litzinger, trans., Commentary on Aristotle s Nicomachean Ethics (Notre Dame, IN: Dumb Ox Books, 1993), 22. 9 Aristotle, Sachs, trans., Ethics, 15. 10 Aristotle, Christopher Biffle, trans., Aristotle s Nicomachean Ethics (Mountain View, CA: Mayfield Publishing Company, 1991), 136. 11 Boethius, Watts, trans., Consolation, 49. 12 Ibid., 52. 13 Ibid. 3

surely it will despise every earthly affair. 14 It is not happiness, then, to be focused on things separate and external but on blessings of your own inside you. 15 Just as Aristotle denies health as happiness because of its inconstancy, Consolation denies such things of chance as being true happiness because Fortune by her very mutability can t hope to lead to happiness. 16 In denying all of these, Boethius also claims that he denies pleasure as happiness, for taking only those [things mentioned above] into consideration, Epicurus with perfect consistency stated that pleasure was the highest good, because all others bring the mind enjoyment, 17 but Boethius attests to a different highest good. In so doing, Boethius also affirms Aristotle s position on amusement. For all of these things can provide amusement, but none provide happiness. Therefore, like Aristotle, Boethius can be understood as saying that these temporary things are not true happiness. At this point, both authors identify a transcending good to be happiness instead of these passing things. Aristotle equates happiness with what he calls the Good. The Good, like happiness, is that at which all things aim. 18 It is what is worthy in itself, not to any other end. Aristotle does acknowledge that there are things apart from the ultimate Good that are good, but he asserts that if there are more than one of them [read: those things which are good], it would be the most complete of these. 19 All the other goods seem to be imitations of the Good (though not necessarily in the Platonic sense). The assertion in Nicomachean Ethics is that completeness 14 Ibid., 41. 15 Ibid., 35. 16 Ibid., 31. 17 Ibid., 49. 18 Aristotle, Sachs, trans., Ethics, 1. 19 Ibid., 10. 4

is that which is never chosen on account of anything else. 20 Therefore, it follows that the Good and happiness should be the same, for happiness is that thing on account of which all other things are sought. Indeed, Aristotle makes it clear himself: And happiness seems to be of this sort most of all, since we choose this always on account of itself and never on account of anything else. 21 Therefore, happiness is the Good. Boethius begins his departure with Aristotle here, for he gives a name to the Good. Boethius equates happiness with what he calls God. God, then, is that at which all things aim 22 and is worthy in himself, not to any other end. Like Aristotle, Boethius acknowledges that there are lesser things that resemble goods or happiness. He makes a distinction between two kinds of happiness: felicitas and beatitudo. 23 Boethius allows for the goods of fortune [to] bring some felicity, which is felicitas, but not happiness, which is beatitudo. 24 God is not felicitas, then, but beatitudo, because all things aim at happiness, beatitude, which is a good which once obtained leaves nothing more to be desired. 25 Boethius clearly borrows from Aristotle in his claims at this point in his search, saying, We have already defined the supreme good as happiness 26 and the end of all things is the good. 27 As is asserted above, however, Boethius goes further than Aristotle does. He asserts that it is the universal understanding that God is good, so much so that even basic reason shows that God is so good that we are convinced that His goodness is 20 Ibid. 21 Ibid. 22 Ibid., 1. 23 Marenbon, Boethius, 103. 24 Ibid. 25 Boethius, Watts, trans., Consolation, 48. 26 Ibid., 49. 27 Ibid., 77. 5

perfect, or complete, and therefore happiness. 28 Now, we have to agree that God is the essence of happiness. 29 Happiness equated with God is thereby equated with divinity for Boethius, so that he or she who possesses happiness possesses divinity, for each happy individual is divine. 30 Therefore, happiness is God. Happiness must not only be understood as an abstract idea, and it is not for either philosopher; rather, there is a practical element of action with both the Good and God. Marenbon asks of Boethius in light of this assertion, how [does] the individual man [ ] relate to happiness? 31 Aristotle, having happiness and the Good equivalent, claims that the Good is expressed and happiness achieved in the practice of virtue, or goodness. 32 In Nicomachean Ethics, he says that happiness is a certain way of being at work in accordance with complete virtue. 33 This concept is similar to when Aristotle speaks of the human being, referring to his or her work as the being-at-work of the soul in accordance with reason. 34 Indeed, when Aristotle speaks of the human being, he would refer to his or her happiness as the being-at-work of the soul in accordance with virtue. By becoming virtuous, one becomes good and therefore happy. 35 The Nicomachean definition of virtue is one that sees it either as pertaining to 28 Ibid., 69. Emphasis added. 29 Ibid., 70. 30 Ibid., 71. 31 Marenbon, Boethius, 110. Emphasis added. 32 which means how one relates to the Good 33 Aristotle, Sachs, trans., Ethics, 19. 34 Ibid., 11. 35 Robert Bartlett, Aristotle s Introduction to the Problem of Happiness, American Journal of Political Science 52, no. 3 (2008): 679. 6

thinking or to character. 36 Happiness, being concerned with goodness ad thus being-atwork 37 is associated with the latter. Excellence of character, 38 also is the product of habituation, 39 so happiness (and goodness) are one of the active states of one s soul, 40 demonstrated in the practice of virtue. Happiness, then, is participation in the good by acting virtuously. If Boethius has happiness and God being equivalent and continues to follow the Nicomachean pattern, participation in God must be happiness. Now, participation in God takes multiple forms; among them being thought, prayer, and grace. Boethius asserts that the human being s mind is made in the image of God 41 and that Providence is the divine reason itself, 42 so it follows that whenever the human being thinks, he is, in some way, participating in the Christian Creator God. Boethius calls prayer 43 the one and only means of communication between man and God, 44 suggesting that this discipline is the primary, if not sole, means of participation, or communion, with God. The final manner by which the human being participates in the divine is through the divine grace. For prayer is only possible if we do obtain 36 Aristotle, Sachs, trans., Ethics, 21. 37 Ibid., 11. 38 Ibid., 21. 39 Bartlett, Problem of Happiness, 679. 40 Aristotle, Sachs, trans., Ethics, 24. 41 Boethius, Watts, trans., Consolation, 35. 42 Ibid., 104. 43 associated in this section with hope, which is a possible allusion to the Christian idea of hope and prayer suggested in passages such as Romans 12:12. 44 Boethius, Watts, trans., Consolation, 122. 7

for the price of due humility the inestimable return of divine grace. 45 The Christian God of grace, then, brings about participation in him. 46 Participation in God is thus found in thought, prayer, and in God s grace there is happiness for Boethius if God is said to be the essence of happiness. 47 45 Ibid. 46 Which is why Boethius must spend a significant portion of the final section of Consolation dealing with free-will and this foreknown grace of God. 47 Boethius, Watts, trans., Consolation, 70. 8