SCIENCE: PERCEPTION AND INSTABILITY CAN THERE BE A SINGLE DESCRIPTION?

Similar documents
10/24/2016 RESEARCH METHODOLOGY Lecture 4: Research Paradigms Paradigm is E- mail Mobile

observation and conceptual interpretation

Conclusion. One way of characterizing the project Kant undertakes in the Critique of Pure Reason is by

CRITIQUE OF PARSONS AND MERTON

GV958: Theory and Explanation in Political Science, Part I: Philosophy of Science (Han Dorussen)

The Strengths and Weaknesses of Frege's Critique of Locke By Tony Walton

Objectivity and Diversity: Another Logic of Scientific Research Sandra Harding University of Chicago Press, pp.

Kant on wheels. Available online: 24 Jun 2010

Necessity in Kant; Subjective and Objective

UNIT SPECIFICATION FOR EXCHANGE AND STUDY ABROAD

SCIENTIFIC KNOWLEDGE AND RELIGIOUS RELATION TO REALITY

Kent Academic Repository

Philip Kitcher and Gillian Barker, Philosophy of Science: A New Introduction, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2014, pp. 192

Part IV Social Science and Network Theory

Lecture 3 Kuhn s Methodology

Kęstas Kirtiklis Vilnius University Not by Communication Alone: The Importance of Epistemology in the Field of Communication Theory.


Semiotics of culture. Some general considerations

foucault s archaeology science and transformation David Webb

SYSTEM-PURPOSE METHOD: THEORETICAL AND PRACTICAL ASPECTS Ramil Dursunov PhD in Law University of Fribourg, Faculty of Law ABSTRACT INTRODUCTION

What counts as a convincing scientific argument? Are the standards for such evaluation

Kant, Peirce, Dewey: on the Supremacy of Practice over Theory

An essay on Alasdair MacIntyre s Relativism. Power and Philosophy

8/28/2008. An instance of great change or alteration in affairs or in some particular thing. (1450)

(as methodology) are not always distinguished by Steward: he says,

INTERNATIONAL CONFERENCE ON ENGINEERING DESIGN ICED 05 MELBOURNE, AUGUST 15-18, 2005 GENERAL DESIGN THEORY AND GENETIC EPISTEMOLOGY

Environmental Ethics: From Theory to Practice

Architecture is epistemologically

TROUBLING QUALITATIVE INQUIRY: ACCOUNTS AS DATA, AND AS PRODUCTS

High School Photography 1 Curriculum Essentials Document

Análisis Filosófico ISSN: Sociedad Argentina de Análisis Filosófico Argentina

Ralph K. Hawkins Bethel College Mishawaka, Indiana

TEST BANK. Chapter 1 Historical Studies: Some Issues

What do our appreciation of tonal music and tea roses, our acquisition of the concepts

that would join theoretical philosophy (metaphysics) and practical philosophy (ethics)?

Valuable Particulars

Four Characteristic Research Paradigms

TERMS & CONCEPTS. The Critical Analytic Vocabulary of the English Language A GLOSSARY OF CRITICAL THINKING

Capstone Design Project Sample

Penultimate draft of a review which will appear in History and Philosophy of. $ ISBN: (hardback); ISBN:

Introduction. Lior Rabi. José Ortega y Gasset is the most prominent Spanish philosopher in the 20 th century.

Hypatia, Volume 21, Number 3, Summer 2006, pp (Review) DOI: /hyp For additional information about this article

WHITEHEAD'S PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE AND METAPHYSICS

ANALYSIS OF THE PREVAILING VIEWS REGARDING THE NATURE OF THEORY- CHANGE IN THE FIELD OF SCIENCE

Practical Intuition and Rhetorical Example. Paul Schollmeier

Harris Wiseman, The Myth of the Moral Brain: The Limits of Moral Enhancement (Cambridge, MA and London: The MIT Press, 2016), 340 pp.

INTRODUCTION TO NONREPRESENTATION, THOMAS KUHN, AND LARRY LAUDAN

Caught in the Middle. Philosophy of Science Between the Historical Turn and Formal Philosophy as Illustrated by the Program of Kuhn Sneedified

1/9. Descartes on Simple Ideas (2)

A Handbook for Action Research in Health and Social Care

Giving Reasons, A Contribution to Argumentation Theory

A Comprehensive Critical Study of Gadamer s Hermeneutics

Jacek Surzyn University of Silesia Kant s Political Philosophy

Humanities Learning Outcomes

This is an electronic reprint of the original article. This reprint may differ from the original in pagination and typographic detail.

1/10. Berkeley on Abstraction

On the Analogy between Cognitive Representation and Truth

A Letter from Louis Althusser on Gramsci s Thought

1/8. The Third Paralogism and the Transcendental Unity of Apperception

A Confusion of the term Subjectivity in the philosophy of Mind *

CONRAD AND IMPRESSIONISM JOHN G. PETERS

NON-EXAMPLES AND PROOF BY CONTRADICTION

Seven remarks on artistic research. Per Zetterfalk Moving Image Production, Högskolan Dalarna, Falun, Sweden

Challenging the View That Science is Value Free

The Ancient Philosophers: What is philosophy?

Culture and Art Criticism

Aristotle. Aristotle. Aristotle and Plato. Background. Aristotle and Plato. Aristotle and Plato

EXPANDED COURSE DESCRIPTIONS UC DAVIS PHILOSOPHY DEPARTMENT SPRING, Michael Glanzberg MWF 10:00-10:50a.m., 176 Everson CRNs:

The Human Intellect: Aristotle s Conception of Νοῦς in his De Anima. Caleb Cohoe

UNIT SPECIFICATION FOR EXCHANGE AND STUDY ABROAD

An Intense Defence of Gadamer s Significance for Aesthetics

Sidestepping the holes of holism

Science and Values: Holism and Radical Environmental Activism

What Can Experimental Philosophy Do? David Chalmers

The Embedding Problem for Non-Cognitivism; Introduction to Cognitivism; Motivational Externalism

CRITICAL CONTEXTUAL EMPIRICISM AND ITS IMPLICATIONS

Kuhn s Notion of Scientific Progress. Christian Damböck Institute Vienna Circle University of Vienna

Guidelines for Manuscript Preparation for Advanced Biomedical Engineering

SUMMARY BOETHIUS AND THE PROBLEM OF UNIVERSALS

THE RELATIONS BETWEEN ETHICS AND ECONOMICS: A COMPARATIVE ANALYSIS BETWEEN AYRES AND WEBER S PERSPECTIVES. By Nuria Toledano and Crispen Karanda

3. The knower s perspective is essential in the pursuit of knowledge. To what extent do you agree?

Hume s Sentimentalism: What Not Who Should Have The Final Word Elisabeth Schellekens

SocioBrains THE INTEGRATED APPROACH TO THE STUDY OF ART

KANT S TRANSCENDENTAL LOGIC

Corcoran, J George Boole. Encyclopedia of Philosophy. 2nd edition. Detroit: Macmillan Reference USA, 2006

KINDS (NATURAL KINDS VS. HUMAN KINDS)

INTERVIEW: ONTOFORMAT Classical Paradigms and Theoretical Foundations in Contemporary Research in Formal and Material Ontology.

Phenomenology and Non-Conceptual Content

Cyclic vs. circular argumentation in the Conceptual Metaphor Theory ANDRÁS KERTÉSZ CSILLA RÁKOSI* In: Cognitive Linguistics 20-4 (2009),

Mixed Methods: In Search of a Paradigm

PHILOSOPHY OF SOCIAL SCIENCE INTS 4522 Spring Jack Donnelly and Martin Rhodes -

Holliday Postmodernism

The Debate on Research in the Arts

An Alternative to Kitcher s Theory of Conceptual Progress and His Account of the Change of the Gene Concept

Philosophical Background to 19 th Century Modernism

Reply to Stalnaker. Timothy Williamson. In Models and Reality, Robert Stalnaker responds to the tensions discerned in Modal Logic

Introduction to The Handbook of Economic Methodology

Cultural Studies Prof. Dr. Liza Das Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Guwahati

PHILOSOPH ICAL PERSPECTI VES ON PROOF IN MATHEMATI CS EDUCATION

Disputing about taste: Practices and perceptions of cultural hierarchy in the Netherlands van den Haak, M.A.

Transcription:

MÈTODE Science Studies Journal, 5 (2015): 209-215. University of Valencia. DOI: 10.7203/metode.84.3889 ISSN: 2174-3487. Article received: 14/07/2014, accepted: 19/09/2014. SCIENCE: PERCEPTION AND INSTABILITY CAN THERE BE A SINGLE DESCRIPTION? PEDRO RUIZ-CASTELL Science has become the main standard of truth for contemporary societies. But what exactly is scientific knowledge? This article tries to answer the question by critiquing towards the description of science as a single universal model based on a distinctive method of obtaining knowledge. The text addresses the impossibility of defending the existence of an alleged scientific method, highlighting the complexity of scientific activity and its relationship to time-bound social and cultural aspects. Thus, we consider the importance of understanding how scientific knowledge is constructed and legitimised with a number of connections and interactions of various elements that provide a historical form to what we understand by science. Keywords: science, scientific method, scientific knowledge. We have all made a distinction, at some point, between sciences and humanities. The idea that these two fields of knowledge are divorced is quite widespread in contemporary culture. According to tradition, the separation started to build up during the nineteenth century with the appearance of new fields and specialities, consolidated within laboratories and university departments. The process was accompanied by the transformation of research into a professional activity and the development of a new industry based on scientific knowledge and its application to economic activity. As a consequence, the progressive separation of science and humanities during the nineteenth century led to growing isolation and distance between both cultures with disastrous effects for contemporary culture (Snow, 1959). Whether or not we share the perception that there are two distinct cultures, it is true that when we use the word science we usually refer to what we know as hard or natural sciences. Those are disciplines like physics, chemistry, mathematics or biology. Undoubtedly, in the collective imagination, a scientist is the professional of those sciences. Conversely, we call «humanists» those devoted to the study of history, philology, sociology or law. It goes without saying «WHEN WE USE THE WORD SCIENCE WE USUALLY REFER TO WHAT WE KNOW AS HARD OR NATURAL SCIENCES» that most people think the latter are anything but scientists; in any case, they are often seen as scholars or intellectuals, a perception shared by many people working within humanities. But to what point is this differentiation real and effective? And if it is, what characteristics define sciences and humanities? We can reformulate the question in the following way: can the knowledge provided by humanities be branded as scientific? Can we say that history, philology, sociology or law are sciences? In other words, does it make sense to talk about human and social sciences? THE WORD To be able to answer these questions, we must first ask ourselves what we understand as science. Coming from the Latin form scientia, the Spanish word ciencia appeared at the beginning of the seventeenth century in the first Spanish monolingual dictionary and related to the ability to understand things given their causes or principles (Covarrubias, 1611). In this sense, in texts of the time it is not strange to read expressions such as ciencias humanas (human sciences, Fonseca, 1622), as they were framed in a philosophical tradition or knowledge system that would survive into MÈTODE 209

the Modern Era, mainly in universities. However, its meaning would change over the years. In a wide sense, the term ciencia encompassed acquired knowledge or that which is able to create new knowledge. Nonetheless, there were many forms of knowledge. Which one could be safely believed? What characteristics must exist for a certain type of knowledge to be considered scientific and, therefore, real and truthful? Authors such as Francis Bacon (1561-1626), René Descartes (1596-1650) or Immanuel Kant (1724-1804) tried to offer, in different historical eras, a general characterisation of what science should be. We may understand this interest in building a logically articulated system of knowledge extraction, regulated by institutions and publications exerting an adequate control, as part of the quest for autonomy to which natural philosophers, who started being called scientists in the nineteenth century, aspire. In this way, legitimised by academic and university institutions, science was identified during the eighteen hundreds with pure knowledge created, independently from other powers, in separate and supposedly neutral intellectual spaces. Those who produced that knowledge and were now given the name scientists, far from being held responsible for the misuse of their discoveries, were portrayed as selfless characters exclusively dedicated to cultivating their intellect and obtaining knowledge for the common good. It was, undoubtedly, a biased account the success of which must be understood within the framework of the social, economic and cultural transformation that this type of knowledge fostered and which allowed us, precisely, to understand the different connections that condition the development of scientific activity. Not without reason, science was destined to represent a central role in the development of modern societies and in the transformation of the world, serving the ideals and moral values of western civilisation (because they were able to separate myth from reality and fact from fiction, unlike the rest of cultures). The interest in identifying scientific knowledge in order to distinguish it from other kinds of knowledge like religious or metaphysical knowledge, reached its peak in the 1920s and 1930s, with the defence of science by the logical positivists of the Vienna Circle. Science had to selflessly search for the truth and be responsible for the production of objective knowledge, verified by facts. Scientific knowledge had to be universal and independent from the context in which it was formulated. This could only be achieved through the application of a special and distinctive method named the scientific method. Portrait Gallery of Dulwich, London Authors such as Francis Bacon, René Descartes or Immanuel Kant tried to offer, in different historical moments, a general characterisation of what science should be. Above, portrait of Francis Bacon, circa 1622. «SCIENCE IS NOT, CONTRARY TO THE COMMON BELIEF, CIRCUMSCRIBED AND STABLE OVER TIME» 210 MÈTODE

THE PROBLEM WITH METHOD Royal Society We may understand this interest in building a logically articulated system of knowledge extraction, regulated by institutions and publications, as part of the quest for autonomy to which natural philosophers, who started being called scientists in the nineteenth century, aspire. In the picture, cover of the first issue of the journal Philosophical Transactions, first edited by the Royal Society in London in 1665. «THE ACCOUNT OF THE SINGLE AND UN IVERSAL SCIENTIFIC MODEL WAS GREATLY INFLUENCED BY THE SUCCESS OF CONTEMPORARY PHYSICS IN THE NINETEENTH AND TWENTIETH CENTURIES» The astounding success of disciplines such as physics in the nineteenth and twentieth centuries made many fields of study want to be characterised as «scientific», in an attempt to get recognition for the strength of their methods and how fruitful their results were. Unsurprisingly, during the twentieth century science became the main standard for truth, capable of determining what is real and what is fiction. To this end, it was necessary for those fields to formulate and apply what was known as the scientific method. But, what was the method about? As mentioned above, the common vision of science maintains that scientific knowledge directly stems from facts. Science the positivists say produces true knowledge from objective facts that are revealed to thorough and unprejudiced observers directly through their senses. There are two aspects we must take into account in connection to this, however: the nature of facts and how scientific knowledge stems from it. It is true that facts alone do not mean much. What really constitutes a novelty and contributes to the development of science is the formulation of observational statements. But the formulation of such statements requires a conceptual framework that is conditioned by our education, our knowledge and our expectations. The perception of the same fact can change from one person to another depending on the conceptual frame and the theoretical background in which the experience must be necessarily situated. Without a doubt, it is easier to observe and discern something when we know what we are looking for and how to interpret it. In this sense, observation cannot be said to guarantee the extraction of immutable truth. Observational statements are verifiable and revisable, as the history of science shows. There are lots of examples showing how what was accepted for hundreds of years as observable facts sustained by evidence like the Earth s immobility or Newton s mechanics, has later been considered wrong (Chalmers, 1976). There are some who defend that it is really the experiment rather than mere observation that is necessary in order to obtain relevant facts with which to get the reliable foundation with characterises scientific knowledge and, thus, correctly describe the processes of nature. But this demand does not solve the essential problem: establishing these experimental results can be wrong if the knowledge sustaining them both theoretical and practical is deficient or inadequate. Experimental results are also fallible and MÈTODE 211

revisable and their meaning can change depending on the function of the theoretical framework in which they are formulated. Certainly, the human mental abilities from which these results are obtained is closely adapted to the cultures in which they operate. Therefore, we cannot say that the true knowledge that allegedly stems from science derives from fact to experience, despite the fact that they have been acquired through observation and experimentation. This «naïve inductivism», as some authors call it, shows important inconsistencies coming from the subjectivity of the observation and the possibility of obtaining false conclusions from inductive inference based on true premises, as some authors have highlighted (Russell, 1959). Even when we suppose that the scientific method may function starting with statements from speculative and provisional theories, verified through observation and experimentation, the truth is we can never conclusively claim that a theory is valid. In any case it will be the best available, that is, the most suitable for the tests to which it is subjected, because theories are fallible and can be improved or substituted (Popper, 1959). Moreover, the history of science is full of examples that allow us to see how the process of reasoning, observation and experimentation evolves historically. We know that the methods used by researchers are subjected to transformations and that scientists have been able to change their own rules. In other words, the regulating principles of science have changed over time. And as much as we can identify historical rules in scientific practice that were only accepted in a particular moment, we cannot claim there is a universal scientific method. In short, the verification that scientific theories cannot be proven conclusively denies the existence of a distinctive and characteristic method for science. This made some authors give up the idea that science is a special rational activity, different from those of other forms of obtaining knowledge, as some modern authors and sociologists indicate, inspired by what is known as epistemological anarchism (Feyerabend, 1975). WHAT IS SCIENCE? The account of the single and universal scientific model, founded on a distinctive method for obtaining knowledge, was greatly influenced by the success of contemporary physics in the nineteenth and twentieth centuries. However, as we have already seen, this paradigm of what science should be is not sustainable if we go deep into the functioning of some of the most established scientific disciplines. Miguel Lorenzo Scientific knowledge is not directly extracted or distilled from nature to be then applied to technical and social ends. It is rather «constructed» from observation and experimentation, turning the obtained information into something intelligible, interesting and useful. We can never, therefore, see scientific activity isolated from its context. «THE PERCEPTION OF THE SAME FACT CAN CHANGE FROM ONE PERSON TO ANOTHER DEPENDING ON THE CONCEPTUAL FRAME AND THE THEORETICAL BACKGROUND IN WHICH THE EXPERIENCE MUST BE NECESSARILY SITUATED» Anna Mateu 212 MÈTODE

Scientists themselves know that the methods for the resolution of questions addressed by different fields of study are different in form and number. If we pay attention, for instance, to experiment reproducibility an aspect understood by many as fundamental to establish scientific fact and obtain the consensus that provides stability to scientific knowledge, we would realise that its role is not so decisive. Sure enough, there are scientific disciplines such as cosmology where this is of no importance. Similarly, people, societies and ecological systems are not inanimate objects and cannot be manipulated as physical objects are. Simply put, not all scientific disciplines work the same way. That is why some authors prefer referring to «sciences», instead of «science», when they speak about methodology and the production of trustworthy knowledge about the real world. Some authors such as Dominique Pestre (in the picture) chose to use new categories to describe the complex process that is science. Hence the characterisation of the history of science as a string of «knowledge regimes» articulated on «social modes of existence» or certain ways of social commitment, production practices and political management. «SOME THINKERS AND SCIENTISTS BELIEVE THAT THE RELATIVISM AND THE SOCIOLOGICAL CONSTRUCTIVISM DEVELOPED IN THE LATE DECADES OF THE TWENTIETH CENTURY EXAGGERATE UNCERTAINTY WITHIN SCIENTIFIC ACTIVITY» Besides, as mentioned before, fact perception presents a marked social and cultural component, since it is conditioned by elements such as previous knowledge and expectations. Scientific knowledge is not directly extracted or distilled from nature to be then applied to technical and social ends. It is rather «invented» and «constructed» from observation and experimentation, turning the obtained information into something intelligible, interesting and useful. We can never, therefore, see scientific activity isolated from its context, since it includes not only intellectual and technical dimensions, but also cognitive, institutional, social, political and other dimensions. The results obtained by scientists can offer information both about nature and about culture. Therefore, scientific investigation must be conceived as a complex network of practical activities that act on the natural world and not as the mere formation of a group of theoretical propositions verified via the simple observation of the world. The influence of social aspects in the development of scientific activity is also accepted by most authors, and is evidenced by studying the social organisation of science or the development of some scientific policy. There are also a lot of concepts and techniques with a social origin used in scientific disciplines, as proved in Thomas Malthus work (1766-1834) on the development of the Darwinian idea of natural selection. Hence, we can claim that all scientific practice has a clear social nature. Consequently, science emerges from a series of connections that involve different aspects and are articulated differently in each historical era, including knowledge results, instrumental and discursive practices, values and rules, institutional and organisational realities, political and social mores, economic and legal scenarios, etc. Science is not, contrary to the common belief, circumscribed and stable over time. In this sense, some authors chose to use new categories in order to describe this complex process. Hence the characterisation of the history of science as a string of «knowledge regimes» articulated on «social modes of existence» or certain ways of social commitment, production practices and political management (Pestre, 2005). In this way we would be able to consider both the interdependence of different MÈTODE 213

Nico Munuera. Intuitive Colour Knowledge VI, 2014. Collage in mixed technique on paper, 21 30 cm. 214 MÈTODE

aspects that affect the development of «sciences», and the transformations that, over history, have allowed for the regulation and legitimation of what was considered at a particular moment good scientific practice a fact revealing multiple logics with their own temporary nature. From this perspective, scientific knowledge also covers elements that are often built in a routine way and at a local scale, without depending on particularly great or excessively rational methods. This vision provides a much richer, complex and suggestive perspective about scientific activity, highlighting the persuasion and credibility work of scientists in organised spaces where such knowledge is formalised and spread. That is why science historians are interested not only in the development of ideas and arguments and in the techniques and tools designed to research nature, but also in the ways of representing and communicating the results and the institutional strategies to promote science. EPILOGUE Not every author is completely convinced of the virtue in unmasking science s aura of objectivity and truth. Some thinkers and scientists believe that the relativism and the sociological constructivism developed in the late decades of the twentieth century exaggerate uncertainty within scientific activity, favouring radical scepticism towards science arising from a false and harmful stereotype. It is, perhaps, a rather extreme perception aimed at maintaining the epistemological status acquired by scientific knowledge during the last centuries. However, it does not seem ridiculous to think that something exists that distinguishes sciences from other types of knowledge such as religious or mystical knowledge. The problem is that, despite the impossibility of accepting the existence of a universal scientific method and the difficulty in answering the question of what science is as crudely evidenced when exploring in detail the way different scientific disciplines answer their questions, we have no inconvenient in identifying, however ambiguously or imprecisely, the existence of something called «science» (Chalmers, 1976; Ziman, 2003). Thus, what would best characterise the sciences is their attempt to establish generalisations or models to «SCIENTIFIC ACTIVITY INVOLVES A MULTITUDE OF METHODS AND TECHNIQUES. AND IN MOST CASES, BOTH LOGIC AND IMAGINATION ARE USUALLY COMBINED» explain in a rational, agreed upon way what happens in nature in relation to human beings. Even though, regarding what has been discussed here, the demand for certainty is unrealistic, we can at least argue that scientific generalisations that is, the formulation of laws and theories allow us to expand and improve our knowledge, without being justified beforehand or imposed due to value judgements or individual criteria. For some authors, these statements are enough to fight the most extreme scepticism and relativism, providing a substitute for the universal method that would define science and we have rejected. However, what is really interesting is the way this scientific knowledge is constructed and legitimised starting with a series of connections and interactions between different elements. Scientific activity involves a multitude of methods and techniques. And in most cases, both logic and imagination are usually combined in order to deduce processes from certain structures or behaviours. The «hard» sciences share this methodology with the «humanities», which are not alien to what has been explained here and which, therefore, are also capable of generating scientific knowledge. The key lies in understanding how, in any of these fields of representation of reality, imagination is limited and disciplined by a series of rules and values that can, no doubt, change over time, giving a historical context i.e., variable over time to everything we understand as science. REFERENCES CHALMERS, A. F., 1976. What Is This Thing Called Science? University of Queensland Press. St. Lucia, Queensland. COVARRUBIAS, S., 1611. El tesoro de la lengua castellana o española. Luis Sánchez. Madrid. FEYERABEND, P., 1975. Contra el método. Esquema de una teoría anarquista del conocimiento. Ariel. Barcelona. FONSECA, C., 1622. Quarta parte de la Vida de Christo. Luis Sanchez. Madrid. PESTRE, D., 2005. Ciencia, dinero y política. Nueva Visión. Buenos Aires. POPPER, K. R., 1959. The Logic of Scientifi c Discovery. Hutchinson. London. RUSSELL, B., 1959. The Problems of Philosophy. Oxford University Press. New York. SNOW, C. P., 1959. The Two Cultures. Cambridge University Press. London. ZIMAN, J., 2003. Qué es la ciencia? Cambridge University Press. Madrid. Pedro Ruiz-Castell. Professor at the Department of History of Science and Documentation. López Piñero Institute for the History of Medicine and Science. University of Valencia (Spain). MÈTODE 215