Lecture 7: Incongruent Counterparts

Similar documents
Conclusion. One way of characterizing the project Kant undertakes in the Critique of Pure Reason is by

Pure and Applied Geometry in Kant

Reflections on Kant s concept (and intuition) of space

that would join theoretical philosophy (metaphysics) and practical philosophy (ethics)?

MODELS IN PERCEPTION AND MODELS IN SCIENCE. lohan Arnt Myrstad

1/8. Axioms of Intuition

Published in Philosophical Studies 100/2 (2000): THE AESTHETICS OF MIRROR REVERSAL "The mirror is the master of painters" Leonardo Da Vinci

What is Character? David Braun. University of Rochester. In "Demonstratives", David Kaplan argues that indexicals and other expressions have a

Bennett on Parts Twice Over

Varieties of Nominalism Predicate Nominalism The Nature of Classes Class Membership Determines Type Testing For Adequacy

Naïve realism without disjunctivism about experience

Immanuel Kant Critique of Pure Reason

Chudnoff on the Awareness of Abstract Objects 1

KANT S THEORY OF SPACE AND THE NON-EUCLIDEAN GEOMETRIES

1/6. The Anticipations of Perception

1/9. The B-Deduction

Between Concept and Form: Learning from Case Studies

The Aesthetic Idea and the Unity of Cognitive Faculties in Kant's Aesthetics

Reply to Stalnaker. Timothy Williamson. In Models and Reality, Robert Stalnaker responds to the tensions discerned in Modal Logic

Sense and soundness of thought as a biochemical process Mahmoud A. Mansour

Permutations of the Octagon: An Aesthetic-Mathematical Dialectic

The Philosophy of Language. Grice s Theory of Meaning

KANT S TRANSCENDENTAL LOGIC

Immanuel Kant, the author of the Copernican revolution in philosophy,

WHAT IS WRONG WITH THE RELATIONAL THEORY OF CHANGE? Gonzalo Rodriguez-Pereyra Hertford College, Oxford

Intelligible Matter in Aristotle, Aquinas, and Lonergan. by Br. Dunstan Robidoux OSB

Phenomenology Glossary

6 Bodily Sensations as an Obstacle for Representationism

Verity Harte Plato on Parts and Wholes Clarendon Press, Oxford 2002

Steven E. Kaufman * Key Words: existential mechanics, reality, experience, relation of existence, structure of reality. Overview

Logic and Philosophy of Science (LPS)

Philosophy 405: Knowledge, Truth and Mathematics Spring Russell Marcus Hamilton College

Parmenides, Hegel and Special Relativity

Philosophy of Mind and Metaphysics Lecture III: Qualitative Change and the Doctrine of Temporal Parts

What do our appreciation of tonal music and tea roses, our acquisition of the concepts

Necessity in Kant; Subjective and Objective

The Unity of the Manifest and Scientific Image by Self-Representation *

Kant s Negative Answer to Molyneux s Question. Richard David Creek

POST-KANTIAN AUTONOMIST AESTHETICS AS APPLIED ETHICS ETHICAL SUBSTRATUM OF PURIST LITERARY CRITICISM IN 20 TH CENTURY

Hoyningen Symposium Systematicity: The Nature of Science

AREA OF KNOWLEDGE: MATHEMATICS

The Concept of Nature

A Note on Analysis and Circular Definitions

A Confusion of the term Subjectivity in the philosophy of Mind *

Making Modal Distinctions: Kant on the possible, the actual, and the intuitive understanding.

PAUL REDDING S CONTINENTAL IDEALISM (AND DELEUZE S CONTINUATION OF THE IDEALIST TRADITION) Sean Bowden

Sidestepping the holes of holism

THESIS MIND AND WORLD IN KANT S THEORY OF SENSATION. Submitted by. Jessica Murski. Department of Philosophy

Architecture as the Psyche of a Culture

META-COGNITIVE UNITY IN INDIRECT PROOFS

Persistence and Determination 1

Are There Two Theories of Goodness in the Republic? A Response to Santas. Rachel Singpurwalla

Perception and Mind-Dependence Lecture 3

Kant, Peirce, Dewey: on the Supremacy of Practice over Theory

Berkeley s idealism. Jeff Speaks phil October 30, 2018

It is from this perspective that Aristotelian science studies the distinctive aspects of the various inhabitants of the observable,

The Senses at first let in particular Ideas. (Essay Concerning Human Understanding I.II.15)

Dawn M. Phillips The real challenge for an aesthetics of photography

On The Search for a Perfect Language

Intersemiotic translation: The Peircean basis

1/9. Descartes on Simple Ideas (2)

IS SCIENCE PROGRESSIVE?

PHL 317K 1 Fall 2017 Overview of Weeks 1 5

Robin Le Poidevin, editor, Questions of Time and Tense ~Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1998!, xii 293 pp.

(Ulrich Schloesser/ Humboldt-Universität zu Berlin)

This is an electronic reprint of the original article. This reprint may differ from the original in pagination and typographic detail.

124 Philosophy of Mathematics

Incommensurability and Partial Reference

Aristotle's Stoichiology: its rejection and revivals

Spectrum inversion as a challenge to intentionalism

1/10. Berkeley on Abstraction

Unit Plan Sample: Mathematics Topics. Stage 1: Desired Results

Aristotle s Modal Syllogistic. Marko Malink. Cambridge Harvard University Press, Pp X $ 45,95 (hardback). ISBN:

The Constitution Theory of Intention-Dependent Objects and the Problem of Ontological Relativism

RESPONDING TO ART: History and Culture

Resemblance Nominalism: A Solution to the Problem of Universals. GONZALO RODRIGUEZ-PEREYRA. Oxford: Clarendon Press, Pp. xii, 238.

A Succession of Feelings, in and of Itself, is Not a Feeling of Succession

Music and Mathematics: On Symmetry

Culture and Art Criticism

observation and conceptual interpretation

Philosophy of sound, Ch. 1 (English translation)

The Kantian and Hegelian Sublime

dialectica The Place of Subjects in the Metaphysics of Material Objects

Symmetry and Transformations in the Musical Plane

1/8. The Third Paralogism and the Transcendental Unity of Apperception

Notes on Gadamer, The Relevance of the Beautiful

Instance and System: a Figure and its 2 18 Variations

SUMMARY BOETHIUS AND THE PROBLEM OF UNIVERSALS

REVIEW ARTICLE IDEAL EMBODIMENT: KANT S THEORY OF SENSIBILITY

An Essay towards a New Theory of Vision

From Individuality to Universality: The Role of Aesthetic Education in Kant

On Recanati s Mental Files

THE ECOLOGICAL MEANING OF EMBODIMENT

INTERNATIONAL CONFERENCE ON ENGINEERING DESIGN ICED 05 MELBOURNE, AUGUST 15-18, 2005 GENERAL DESIGN THEORY AND GENETIC EPISTEMOLOGY

SUMMIT LAW GROUP PLLC 315 FIFTH AVENUE SOUTH, SUITE 1000 SEATTLE, WASHINGTON Telephone: (206) Fax: (206)

Article The Nature of Quantum Reality: What the Phenomena at the Heart of Quantum Theory Reveal About the Nature of Reality (Part III)

The Strengths and Weaknesses of Frege's Critique of Locke By Tony Walton

Kant IV The Analogies The Schematism updated: 2/2/12. Reading: 78-88, In General

Types of perceptual content

Lecture 24 Sociology 621 December 12, 2005 MYSTIFICATION

Transcription:

Lecture 7: Incongruent Counterparts 7.1 Kant s 1768 paper 7.1.1 The Leibnizian background Although Leibniz ultimately held that the phenomenal world, of spatially extended bodies standing in various distance relations from one another, was not fundamental, he believed that our everyday notion of space as something independent of bodies was an abstraction from this order. That all spatial facts are to be reducible to facts about the relative distances between material bodies is the defining thesis of the classical relationalist. Kant s 1768 paper certainly has this position in its sights. But the thinking behind Kant s paper is perhaps made more transparent when one takes into account some key features of Leibniz s analysis situs. In this, the fundamental notion in analyzing spatial qualities was to be the relation of congruence, which Leibniz understood in terms of equality of magnitude and similarity of form. I shall here use the relations of congruence, which I shall express by the character. For example, in the first figure (Figure 1), ABC DEF means that triangles ABC and DEF are congruent with respect to the order of their points, that they can occupy exactly the same place, and that one can be applied or placed on the other without changing anything in the two figures except their place. (Leibniz 1969, 251) D B A C E F Fig. 1 Kant initially defended a Leibnizian account of space, but he became disaffected with it during the 1760s. 7.1.2 The significance of orientation Kant aims to convince us that there is a clear proof that: Absolute space, independently of the existence of all matter... has a reality of its own. (Kant 1992a, 366; Kant s own emphasis) He had come to believe that specifying a system s relative configuration (i.e. the relative distances between the parts of the system), did not exhaust all there was to say. Reflection on such things as maps was meant to suggest the necessity of specifying the orientation of a system, in addition to its relative configuration: 1

... the most precise map of the heavens, if it did not, in addition to specifying the positions of the stars relative to each other, also specify the direction by reference to the position of the chart relative to my hands, would not enable me, no matter how precisely I had it in mind, to infer from a known direction, for example, the north, which side of the horizon I ought to expect the sun to rise. The same thing holds of geographical and, indeed, of our most ordinary knowledge of the position of places. Such knowledge would be of no use unless we could also orientate the things thus ordered, along with the entire system of their reciprocal positions, by referring them to the sides of our body. (Kant 1992a, 367 8) So, in addition to relative distances, Kant thought that the notion of direction was fundamental. To fully specify a body s spatial characteristics, one needs to say how it is oriented and this is ultimately supposed to depend on how the body is related to space as whole:... the positions of the parts of space in reference to each other presuppose the direction in which they are ordered in such relation... In the case of any extended thing, the position of its parts relative to each other can be adequately known by reference to the thing itself. The direction, however, in which this order of parts is orientated, refers to the space outside the thing. To be specific: it refers not to places in the space for that would be the same thing as regarding the position of the parts to the thing in question in an external relation but rather to universal space as a unity... (Kant 1992a, 365) What we are trying to demonstrate, then, is the following claim. The ground of the complete determination of a corporeal form does not depend simply on the relation and position of its parts to each other; it also depends on the reference of that physical form to universal absolute space, as it is conceived by the geometers. (Kant 1992a, 369) Incongruent counterparts then play a key role in showing that facts about orientation go beyond facts about relative distances: If two figures drawn on a plane surface are equal and similar, then they will coincide with each other. But the situation is often entirely different when one is dealing with corporeal [bodies]... They can be exactly equal and similar, and yet still be so different in themselves that the limits of the one cannot also be the limits of the other [... ] [T]he most common and clearest example is furnished by the limbs of the human body... The right hand is similar and equal to the left hand. And if one looks at one of them on its own, examining the proportion and the position of its parts to each other, and scrutinising the magnitude of the whole, then a complete description of the one must apply in all respects to the other, as well. I shall call a body which is exactly equal and similar to another, but which cannot be enclosed in the same limits as that other, its incongruent counterpart. (Kant 1992a, 369 70) 2

7.1.3 The argument Kant s philosophical application of incongruent counterparts runs as follows: It is apparent from the ordinary example of the two hands that the shape of the one body may be perfectly similar to the shape of the other, and the magnitudes of their extensions may be exactly equal, and yet there may remain an inner difference between the two, this difference consisting in the fact, namely, that the surface which encloses the one cannot possibly enclose the other. Since the surface which limits the physical space of the one body cannot serve as a boundary to limit the other, no matter how that surface be twisted and turned, it follows that the difference must be one which rests on an inner ground. This inner ground cannot, however, depend on the difference of the manner in which the parts of the body are combined with each other. For as we have seen from our example, everything may in this respect be exactly the same. Nonetheless, imagine that the first created thing was a human hand. That [hand] would have to be either a right hand or a left hand. The action of the creative cause in producing the one would have of necessity to be different from the action of the creative cause in producing the counterpart. Suppose that one were to adopt the concept entertained by many modern philosophers, especially German philosophers, according to which space simply consists in the external relation of the parts of matter which exist alongside each other... [Since] there is no difference in the relation of the parts of the hand to each other, and that is so whether it be a right hand or a left hand; it would therefore follow that the hand would be completely indeterminate in respect of such a property. In other words, the hand would fit equally well on either side of the human body; but that is impossible. (Kant 1992a, 370 1) 7.1.4 Immediate comments 1. How absurd is it to suppose that the lone hand would fit equally well on either side of the human body? (Cf. Remnant 1963; Dainton 2001, 227 31) 2. What, exactly, is the nature of the relation which left hands bear to space but which right hands don t? Hoefer suggests that haecceitist substantivalists have an answer (Hoefer 2000, 241ff). 7.1.5 What the relationalist needs to do: 1. Explain the incongruence of counterparts; 2. Explain what it is to be of one particular handedness (in a way that is consistent with the denial of Kant s main premise); 3. Explain how we can use maps. 3

7.2 Nerlich s argument Another related spatial property one might wish to give an account of is that shared by incongruent counterparts but not shared by objects that can only have congruent counterparts. Kant suggests that to be an object that can have incongruent counterparts to be an enantiomorph rather than a homomorph an object must not consist of two halves which are symmetrically arranged relatively to a single intersecting plane (Kant 1992a, 370). But as Nerlich points out (Nerlich 1994, Ch. 2), this is merely a necessary condition: the dimensionality and orientability of space are also crucial. Here substantival space plays an obvious role that is independent of haecceitism. Nerlich s variant of Kant s claim is that were the first created thing a human hand, it would have to be either a homomorph or an enantiomorph. Let us return to this challenge later... 7.3 Intrinsic versus extrinsic Despite talk of inner differences Kant seemed to regard being of a particular handedness as an extrinsic matter. There is clearly an alternative: Incongruent counterparts differ intrinsically (such differences are to be exploited in explanations of their incongruence and of what it is to be of one particular handedness) Incongruent counterparts are intrinsically identical (in which case explanations of incongruence and of the handedness must appeal to something extrinsic to the handed object) Problems with the first option (see Nerlich 1994, 51 3; Frederick 1991, 8; Van Cleve 1991, 22 3; Earman 1971, 134 9): 1. higher-dimensional spaces 2. non-orientable spaces 3. epistemology The second, parsimonious, option is thus overwhelmingly more attractive. 7.4 A relational account of handedness 7.4.1 The relational basis of incongruence The notions of rigid motion, and of one body s being able to occupy the space of another, are obviously relationally acceptable. It is simply a mathematical fact, and a perfectly comprehensible one that, when constrained to obey the algebraic relationships of Euclidean geometry, some numbers (the possible distances between two congruent counterparts) can be continuously altered so as to vanish while others (the distances between two incongruent counterparts) cannot. 4

Which things in a given space lie in one direction and which things incline in the opposite direction cannot be described discursively nor reduced to characteristic marks of the understanding by any astuteness of the mind. Thus, between solid bodies which are perfectly similar and equal but incongruent, such as left and right hands (in so far as they are conceived only according to their extension), or spherical triangles from two opposite hemispheres, there is a difference, in virtue of which it is impossible that the limits of their extension should coincide and that, in spite of the fact that, in respect of everything which may be expressed by means of characteristic marks intelligible to the mind through speech, they could be substituted for one another. It is, therefore, clear that in these cases the difference, namely the incongruity, can only be apprehended by a certain pure intuition. (Kant 1992b, 396) 7.4.2 A relational account of handedness (Compare: Earman 1989, Ch. 7, 2; Gardner 1990, Ch. 17; Huggett 1999, 209 12; Hoefer 2000, 3; and Saunders 2000, 3.3.) 1. Incongruent counterparts are intrinsically identical. 2. Their incongruence can be understood (pace Kant) in terms of the spatial relations that hold between them. 3. Each set of handed objects of a particular type is partitioned into two sets by the equivalence relation of congruence. 4. Left and right are proper names for members of one or other partition: we recognise objects as being of one or another handedness by recognising its (in)congruence with similar objects that we have learned through ostension are left(/right)-handed. 7.4.3 The Kantian Hypothesis and the Ozma Problem Jonathan Bennett dubs the claim that the difference between left and right (in a which is which sense) can be explained only by showing and not by telling the Kantian Hypothesis (Bennett 1970). Suppose that we are in radio contact with some extra-galactic civilization: Is there any way to communicate the meaning of left by a language transmitted in the form of pulsating signals? By the terms of the problem we may say anything we please to our listeners, ask them to perform any experiment whatever, with one proviso: There is to be no asymmetric object or structure that we and they can observe in common. (Gardner 1990, 167) 5

7.4.4 Outstanding problems for the reductive relationalist Recall Nerlich s challenge. The relational account offered has exploited various constraints on the relative distances (specifically embeddability in Euclidean of space of a fixed dimension and determinate orientability). Can the relationalist do any better? (See Brighouse 1999; Pooley 2002, Ch. 6; Huggett 2003.) 6

References Bennett, J. (1970), The difference between right and left, American Philosophical Quarterly 7, 175 91. Reprinted in (Van Cleve & Frederick 1991, 97 130). Brighouse, C. (1999), Incongruent counterparts and modal relationism, International Studies in Philosophy of Science 13, 53 68. Dainton, B. (2001), Time and Space, Acumen, Chesham. Earman, J. (1971), Kant, incongruous counterparts, and the nature of space, Ratio 13, 1 18. Reprinted in (Van Cleve & Frederick 1991, 131 149). Earman, J. (1989), World Enough and Space-Time: Absolute versus Relational Theories of Space and Time, MIT Press, Cambridge MA. Frederick, R. E. (1991), Introduction to the argument of 1768, in J. Van Cleve & R. E. Frederick, eds, The Philosophy of Right and Left, Kluwer, Dordrecht, pp. 1 14. Gardner, M. (1990), The New Ambidextrous Universe, revised edn, W. H. Freeman and Company, New York. Hoefer, C. (2000), Kant s hands and Earman s pions: Chirality arguments for substantival space, International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 14, 237 56. Huggett, N. (1999), Space from Zeno to Einstein: Classic Readings with a Contemporary Commentary, MIT Press, Cambridge, MA. Huggett, N. (2003), Mirror symmetry: What is it for relational space to be orientable?, in K. Brading & E. Castellani, eds, Symmetries in Physics: Philosophical Reflections, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge. E-print: PITT-PHIL-SCI00000767. Kant, I. (1992a), Concerning the ultimate ground of the differentiation of directions in space, in D. Walford & R. Meerbote, eds, The Cambridge Edition of the Works of Immanuel Kant. Theoretical Philosophy, 1755 1770, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp. 365 72. Kant, I. (1992b), On the form and principles of the sensible and the intelligible world [inaugural dissertation], in D. Walford & R. Meerbote, eds, The Cambridge Edition of the Works of Immanuel Kant. Theoretical Philosophy, 1755 1770, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp. 377 416. Leibniz, G. W. (1969), Studies in a geometry of situation, in L. E. Loemker, ed., Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz: Philosophical Papers and Letters, second edn, Reidel, Dordrecht, pp. 249 53. Nerlich, G. (1994), The Shape of Space, second edn, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge. Pooley, O. (2002), The Reality of Spacetime, PhD thesis. Available from: http://users.ox.ac.uk/ ball0402/research/. 7

Remnant, P. (1963), Incongruent counterparts and absolute space, Mind 62, 393 399. Reprinted in (Van Cleve & Frederick 1991, 51 9). Saunders, S. W. (2000), Incongruent counterparts; a Leibnizian approach. manuscript. Van Cleve, J. (1991), Introduction to the arguments of 1770 and 1783, in J. Van Cleve & R. E. Frederick, eds, The Philosophy of Right and Left, Kluwer, Dordrecht, pp. 15 26. Van Cleve, J. & Frederick, R. E., eds (1991), The Philosophy of Right and Left, Kluwer, Dordrecht. 8