Virtues o f Authenticity: Essays on Plato and Socrates Republic Symposium Republic Phaedrus Phaedrus), Theaetetus

Similar documents
7AAN2026 Greek Philosophy I: Plato Syllabus Academic year 2015/16

Plato s work in the philosophy of mathematics contains a variety of influential claims and arguments.

The Parmenides. chapter 1

Are There Two Theories of Goodness in the Republic? A Response to Santas. Rachel Singpurwalla

PHILOSOPHY PLATO ( BC) VVR CHAPTER: 1 PLATO ( BC) PHILOSOPHY by Dr. Ambuj Srivastava / (1)

Care of the self: An Interview with Alexander Nehamas

The Place of Doctrines in Platonic Philosophy

Forms and Causality in the Phaedo. Michael Wiitala

Guide to the Republic as it sets up Plato s discussion of education in the Allegory of the Cave.

PHIL 260. ANCIENT GREEK PHILOSOPHY. Fall 2017 Tuesday & Thursday: (Oddfellows 106)

GORDON, J. (2012) PLATO S EROTIC WORLD: FROM COSMIC ORIGINS TO HUMAN DEATH. CAMBRIDGE, CAMBRIDGE UNIVERSITY PRESS.

Doctoral Thesis in Ancient Philosophy. The Problem of Categories: Plotinus as Synthesis of Plato and Aristotle

Kent Academic Repository

Julie K. Ward. Ancient Philosophy 31 (2011) Mathesis Publications

Overcoming Attempts to Dichotomize the Republic

Myth and Philosophy in Plato s Phaedrus

Riccardo Chiaradonna, Gabriele Galluzzo (eds.), Universals in Ancient Philosophy, Edizioni della Normale, 2013, pp. 546, 29.75, ISBN

Plato s Forms. Feb. 3, 2016

Philosophy 405: Knowledge, Truth and Mathematics Spring Russell Marcus Hamilton College

Aristotle s Modal Syllogistic. Marko Malink. Cambridge Harvard University Press, Pp X $ 45,95 (hardback). ISBN:

Lecture 12 Aristotle on Knowledge of Principles

Predication and Ontology: The Categories

124 Philosophy of Mathematics

Philosophy 451 = Classics 451 Wilson 213 Fall 2007 Monday and Wednesday, 11-12, Wilson Description

Plato s dialogue the Symposium takes

Special Issue on Ideas of Plato in the Philosophy of the 21st Century : An Introduction

Philosophy of Art. Plato

1/8. The Third Paralogism and the Transcendental Unity of Apperception

Plato on Metaphysical Explanation: Does Participating Mean Nothing?

Course Syllabus. Ancient Greek Philosophy (direct to Philosophy) (toll-free; ask for the UM-Flint Philosophy Department)

Types of perceptual content

The Origin of Aristotle's Metaphysical Aporiae

Bas C. van Fraassen, Scientific Representation: Paradoxes of Perspective, Oxford University Press, 2008.

A Note on Analysis and Circular Definitions

Practical Intuition and Rhetorical Example. Paul Schollmeier

Introduction. Cambridge University Press Plato on the Rhetoric of Philosophers and Sophists Marina McCoy Excerpt More information

Naïve realism without disjunctivism about experience

PLATO ON JUSTICE AND POWER

Republic Of Plato By Out Of Print READ ONLINE

PHL 317K 1 Fall 2017 Overview of Weeks 1 5

WITHOUT QUALIFICATION: AN INQUIRY INTO THE SECUNDUM QUID

A COMBINED DOCTRINE OF KNOWLEDGE FOR PLATO

It can be very tempting indeed to suppose that Plato, in the Republic, wanted us

web address: address: Description

In order to enrich our experience of great works of philosophy and literature we will include, whenever feasible, speakers, films and music.

Chapter 1. The Power of Names NAMING IS NOT LIKE COUNTING

LYCEUM A Publication of the Philosophy Department Saint Anselm College

Martin, Gottfried: Plato s doctrine of ideas [Platons Ideenlehre]. Berlin: Verlag Walter de Gruyter, 1973

Aristotle on the Human Good

NI YU. Interpreting Memory, Forgetfulness and Testimony in Theory of Recollection

VIRTUE ETHICS-ARISTOTLE

Humanities 116: Philosophical Perspectives on the Humanities

ARISTOTLE. PHILO 381(W) Sec. 051[4810] Fall 2009 Professor Adluri Monday/Wednesday, 7:00-8:15pm

A New Approach to the Paradox of Fiction Pete Faulconbridge

Image and Imagination

Aristotle's Stoichiology: its rejection and revivals

Verity Harte Plato on Parts and Wholes Clarendon Press, Oxford 2002

Conclusion. One way of characterizing the project Kant undertakes in the Critique of Pure Reason is by

The Strengths and Weaknesses of Frege's Critique of Locke By Tony Walton

Reframing the Knowledge Debate, with a little help from the Greeks

Look Who Is Talking Now: Plato or Socrates? Yvonne Ying-Ya Wen. University of Taipei, Taipei, Taiwan; National Formosa University, Yunlin, Taiwan

The Object Oriented Paradigm

The Philosophy of Language. Frege s Sense/Reference Distinction

On Sense Perception and Theory of Recollection in Phaedo

Cambridge University Press Plato s Erotic World: From Cosmic Origins to Human Death Jill Gordon Excerpt More information

Plato s Enlightenment, History of Philosophy Quarterly, Vol 14, No 2, April 1997, pp

Plato s Absolute and Relative Categories at Sophist 255c14

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

In Defense of the Contingently Nonconcrete

Necessity in Kant; Subjective and Objective

Aristotle s Metaphysics

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

Cyclic vs. circular argumentation in the Conceptual Metaphor Theory ANDRÁS KERTÉSZ CSILLA RÁKOSI* In: Cognitive Linguistics 20-4 (2009),

Mind Association. Oxford University Press and Mind Association are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Mind.

Aristotle The Master of those who know The Philosopher The Foal

International Journal of Advancements in Research & Technology, Volume 4, Issue 11, November ISSN

Colonnade Program Course Proposal: Explorations Category

Contemporary virtue ethics has largely avoided the Platonic dialogues as sources of insight for

Ed. Carroll Moulton. Vol. 1. New York: Charles Scribner's Sons, p COPYRIGHT 1998 Charles Scribner's Sons, COPYRIGHT 2007 Gale

Manuel Bremer University Lecturer, Philosophy Department, University of Düsseldorf, Germany

Do Universals Exist? Realism

Penultimate draft of a review which will appear in History and Philosophy of. $ ISBN: (hardback); ISBN:

An Aristotelian Puzzle about Definition: Metaphysics VII.12 Alan Code

The Doctrine of the Mean

Aesthetics Mid-Term Exam Review Guide:

Charles Taylor s Langue/Parole and Alasdair MacIntyre s Networks of Giving and Receiving as a Foundation for a Positive Anti-Atomist Political Theory

Aristotle. By Sarah, Lina, & Sufana

Working BO1 BUSINESS ONTOLOGY: OVERVIEW BUSINESS ONTOLOGY - SOME CORE CONCEPTS. B usiness Object R eference Ontology. Program. s i m p l i f y i n g

PURE REALISM: PLATONISM AS A SERIOUS CONTEMPORARY ALTERNATIVE. Keywords: pure realism, Platonism, metaphysics, natures

In The Meaning of Ought, Matthew Chrisman draws on tools from formal semantics,

Philosophy of Science: The Pragmatic Alternative April 2017 Center for Philosophy of Science University of Pittsburgh ABSTRACTS

What is Postmodernism? What is Postmodernism?

Sidestepping the holes of holism

Theory or Theories? Based on: R.T. Craig (1999), Communication Theory as a field, Communication Theory, n. 2, May,

Objective vs. Subjective

EROS AND SOCRATIC POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY

History of Ancient Philosophy

Why Pleasure Gains Fifth Rank: Against the Anti-Hedonist Interpretation of the Philebus 1

Truth and Tropes. by Keith Lehrer and Joseph Tolliver

Z.13: Substances and Universals

Transcription:

ALEXANDER NEHAMAS, Virtues o f Authenticity: Essays on Plato and Socrates (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1998); xxxvi plus 372; hardback: ISBN 0691 001774, $US 75.00/ 52.00; paper: ISBN 0691 001782, $US 19.95/ 13.95. Here we have a collection of articles, unrevised, ranging over twentyfive years, from a prominent professional philosopher writing mainly in debate with his intellectual mentor Gregory Vlastos, to whose memory the book is dedicated. It divides into four coherent sections, five essays on Socrates (1985-92), six on Platonic metaphysics (1975-84), two on the treatment of art in the Republic (1982, 1988), and introductions reprinted from recent translations of three dialogues (Symposium [1989], Republic [1992] and Phaedrus [1995]). In the nineteen-seventies and at least until the early eighties Nehamas imagined Plato as writing metaphysical dialogues to publish current developments in his thinking like a modem academic (xvi; cf. xvii-xviii). Thereafter Nehamas seems to have begun paying attention to the literary form of the dialogue (see especially the introduction to the Phaedrus), and even proposes that Plato in the Theaetetus for pedagogical reasons did not reveal his full current theory of knowledge (239), yet he never abandons the developmental hypothesis, in the mid eighties following Vlastos interest back from Plato to Socrates. Nehemas sets out in his introduction his interpretive principles (xix-xxiii), and applies them to justify his approach to Plato s dialogues (xv-xvi, xxviii-xxxii). Nehamas thinking about Socrates circles round Vlastos work that led to Socrates, Ironist and Moral Philosopher (Cambridge, 1991), but he rejects Vlastos use of Xenophon and Aristotle to confirm evidence in Plato for the historical Socrates, on the grounds that the former are not independent witnesses (91-2). Nevertheless Nehamas pursues his own interpretation of Socrates as distinct from Plato, criticising Vlastos for failing to capture the philosopher s mysteriousness and making him into a dogmatist (96-104). His own Socrates is ignorant of the definitions of virtues (37), and so of answers to all the important debated moral questions that follow from definitional knowledge (32, 35). Unlike Terence Irwin s Socrates, he has some incidental knowledge, not merely true belief (18-19), about virtues (thus avoiding the Socratic fallacy, 31-2, cf. 160-3), but (unlike Vlastos Socrates) he does not consider himself a 196

teacher, since this knowledge does not encompass anything important (31, 46, 63-4, 70-5). Neither is this Socrates an intellectualist, believing action depends on thought alone, since on the analogy of virtue to a craft, expertise would also require practical habituation (46); his intellectualist appearance is well explained by the fact that the people he talks to are generally those with intellectual pretensions (75). His method of refutation is distinguished from sophistry only by its aim: truth, not victory (112, with Vlastos and Kerford). The paradox that his criterion of truth is precisely dialectical victory is resolved on the same principle: not teaching, Socrates only aims to work out in each case which argument should win (116, cf. Gorgias 458a). Yet Nehamas Socrates consistently displays virtue, and so his Plato, by contrast, interprets Socrates as indeed a teacher (49-50, cf. 13), and also adopts this role himself. See 62 for Nehamas attempt to state his distinction between, firstly, Plato s depiction of Socrates selfunderstanding and, secondly, Plato s own interpretation of Socrates function: this is justified not by any analysis of the literary structure of the dialogues, but only, implicitly, by appeal to the developmental hypothesis. His Plato recognises in Socrates virtuous ignorance a knowledge identical with virtue and happiness, that is, philosophy (117). Notwithstanding the fact that this would render the historical Socrates implausibly and perhaps ridiculously self-ignorant, Nehamas Plato in the Meno interprets the knowledge that Socrates is unaware he has as being the result of recollection (49-50), and (in the Republic) his dialectic as the reliable path to it, on the basis of the distinction between appearance and reality that the theory of Forms introduces (117). According to Nehamas the theory of Forms, prior to the dialogue Parmenides, is based on a principle attributed to the historical Parmenides (133, 181-2): that all predication is properly essential, i.e., that to say that something is such-and-such is understood as meaning that that thing is what it is to be such-and-such (thus Socrates is just would mean, in effect, Socrates is what it is to be just, cf. 168). This is proposed as the common assumption of the time (172). Answering to the oddity of sentences such as the example above, Platonic Forms are interpreted as the 197

perfect exemplars that such predicates truly name: is just only properly identifies the Form Justice. Self-predications ( Justice is just ) turn out then to be merely a description of the Form s nature (178-9), and trivially true. Contra Vlastos, what is at issue in such dialogues is never primarily the abstractness (i.e., universality) of Forms as definienda (xxv-xxviii), but their uniqueness (170, cf. 172). Sensible instances corresponding to Forms are distinguished not by a lack of exactitude, but by being characterised only accidentally, relative to a certain context (152-4). Thus in the Phaedo and Republic 5-7 Forms are introduced only to explain the primary referents of relative and comparative terms when taken absolutely ( incomplete predicates, 143), and are limited to these predicates. The theory of Forms is thus the consequence of a linguistic error. Nehamas denies that the doctrine of participation of sensibles in Forms is meant to explain this relation, given that no sensible is properly subject to the relevant predicate, but he doesn t justify this claim (182-83), and subsequently seems to contradict it (194 n.41 cont d, 186, 187). Nehamas limitation of the range of Forms and his denial of epistemic weight to the concept of participation both seem designed to reduce the degree of Plato s commitment to the complete ontological subordination of all sensible phenomena, with the aim that the change in the conception of Forms claimed for the late period, from perfect exemplars to logically constitutive genera, does not seem too question-begging. He is similarly motivated to adopt Owen s controversial early dating of the Timaeus (218 n.6), but even so the universal distinction there between being and becoming would support a more metaphysically oriented interpretation of Phaedo, Symposium and Republic 5-7. For Nehamas Plato s late period, beginning with the Parmenides, is characterised by the rejection of the conception of essential predication. As a result, Forms are no longer excluded, by their radical difference from all participants, from themselves participating one in another, and sometimes even in themselves (212-17). The latter is necessary, since on Nehamas view now Forms no longer essentially exemplify the attribute they are responsible for, and would not otherwise now be subject to selfpredication. Nehamas does not explain how the inference is supposed to 198

proceed, from the claim that each Form (in the middle period) differs ontologically from sensibles that participate in it, to the claim (not in the dialogues) that a Form may not participate in other Forms. Without that step secured it would not seem necessary for Plato to change the theory to allow for the interweaving of Forms, nor, consequently, to make a special case for self-participation. Indeed the account of dialectic in the divided line (Republic 511 be) positively requires predicating one Form of another (or so it seems to me). The two papers on Plato s views on art involve an analysis of the metaphysics of art in Republic 10, and a comparison of Plato s criticisms with contemporary criticism of television. Of the appended introductions to dialogues, the first two are short, and while that on the Symposium offers a sketch of a plausible account of its dramatic structure (see esp. 312-14), that to the Republic is popular and superficial, which raises the question why these introductions were included at all: they are neither comprehensive nor representative of the dialogues, and do not connect with the previous thematic essays well. Perhaps the best that can be said for them, especially that to the Phaedrus, is that they demonstrate how Nehemas has recently contributed to the dawning recognition among analytically trained Plato scholars that they cannot ignore the literary form of a dialogue in explaining its philosophical achievement or meaning. The discussion of the Phaedrus, the most recent piece in the collection, is a substantive contribution to the debate on its unity, which Nehamas finds in the topic of rhetoric. The speeches on eros are explained as examples of rhetoric, and their subject, once again, in terms of Plato s development: he revises the simple account of motivation from the Symposium by incorporating the tripartite soul in the doctrine of eros (348-9), taking the opportunity to provide another erotic protreptic to philosophy. Yet the metaphysics, that of the middle period, cannot be meant literally, since the Phaedrus applies the method of collection and division, a signature of the late period. Thus the metaphysics of the speech is an adaptation to the complexity of Phaedrus own soul, to convert him to philosophy (350). But this tortuous effort to preserve the developmental hypothesis (quite apart from the incoherence of taking the psychology literally, but the metaphysics not) effectively fails by letting the cat out of the bag. If the middle period metaphysics here is to be 199

explained rhetorically, then why not similarly in the Phaedo, where Socrates talks to Pythagoreans, in the Symposium, which positively reeks of rhetoric, or in Republic 5, in a protreptic passage distinguishing philosophers from non-philosophers? And ifnehamas account of Plato s metaphysics unravels here, then so does his effort to distinguish between Plato and Socrates, and his grounds for finding any Platonic doctrine in the dialogues. In any case, the essay on the Phaedrus concludes that this dialogue should not be read for doctrine (353-4). I have sought to discuss this book as a book, since it is so presented. But the reading is hard going, given that nearly every chapter is a tightly argued journal article and so the central planks ofnehamas positions and their interconnections are not laid out systematically, while despite the not infrequent overlaps there are also some inconsistencies and changes of mind, as noted above. Given the evolution of his own approach to Plato (if not his interpretation), the author might have profitably revised these papers to make a better and more coherent book. I should also note that the format suffers from some defects, despite the useful indices. There is no bibliography, notes are placed at the end of each essay, but without page headers indicating their connections, and even within essays there seems to be little consistency in when Greek is transliterated and when not. I found twenty-three typographical errors, and an ungrammatical and apparently mistaken translation of Republic 435a7-8 (208: read in that respect in which it is called the same ). Dougal Blyth University of Auckland 200