Dabney Townsend. Hume s Aesthetic Theory: Taste and Sentiment Timothy M. Costelloe Hume Studies Volume XXVIII, Number 1 (April, 2002)

Similar documents

REVIEW ARTICLE IDEAL EMBODIMENT: KANT S THEORY OF SENSIBILITY

Necessity in Kant; Subjective and Objective

MAURICE MANDELBAUM HISTORY, MAN, & REASON A STUDY IN NINETEENTH-CENTURY THOUGHT THE JOHNS HOPKINS PRESS: BALTIMORE AND LONDON

RESEMBLANCE IN DAVID HUME S TREATISE Ezio Di Nucci

Review of Hume, Hegel and Human Nature. Hume Studies Volume IX, Number 2 (November, 1983) H. S. Harris

WHITEHEAD'S PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE AND METAPHYSICS

Hume on Responsibility. Hume Studies Volume XIV, Number 1 (April, 1988) Lloyd Fields

Hume s Sentimentalism: What Not Who Should Have The Final Word Elisabeth Schellekens


SUMMARY BOETHIUS AND THE PROBLEM OF UNIVERSALS

Feeling, Impulse and Changeability: The Role of Emotion in Hume's Theory of the Passions

that would join theoretical philosophy (metaphysics) and practical philosophy (ethics)?



The Polish Peasant in Europe and America. W. I. Thomas and Florian Znaniecki

J.S. Mill s Notion of Qualitative Superiority of Pleasure: A Reappraisal

Locke and Berkeley. Lecture 2: Primary and Secondary Qualities

Kant: Notes on the Critique of Judgment

BOOK REVIEW. William W. Davis

A Puzzle about Hume s Theory of General Representation. According to Hume s theory of general representation, we represent generalities by

Hume Studies Volume XXIV, Number 1 (April, 1998)

Sidestepping the holes of holism

Edward Winters. Aesthetics and Architecture. London: Continuum, 2007, 179 pp. ISBN

Emotions from the Perspective of Analytic Aesthetics

1) Three summaries (2-3 pages; pick three out of the following four): due: 9/9 5% due: 9/16 5% due: 9/23 5% due: 9/30 5%

The Logic of Taste: The Second Fifty Years

Hume on Resemblance, Relevance, and Representation

Review of Krzysztof Brzechczyn, Idealization XIII: Modeling in History

Review of Carolyn Korsmeyer, Savoring Disgust: The foul and the fair. in aesthetics (Oxford University Press pp (PBK).

Bas C. van Fraassen, Scientific Representation: Paradoxes of Perspective, Oxford University Press, 2008.

University of Alberta

Writing an Honors Preface

Truth and Tropes. by Keith Lehrer and Joseph Tolliver

The Chinese University of Hong Kong Department of Philosophy. PHIL 2050 History of Western Philosophy II Course Outline

PART ONE: PHILOSOPHY AND THE OTHER MINDS

Object Oriented Learning in Art Museums Patterson Williams Roundtable Reports, Vol. 7, No. 2 (1982),

SOCIAL AND CULTURAL ANTHROPOLOGY

The Shimer School Core Curriculum

HUME'S POSITIVE THEORY OF PERSONAL IDENTITY. Bradley M. Porath Citrus College

Philosophical Background to 19 th Century Modernism

UNIT SPECIFICATION FOR EXCHANGE AND STUDY ABROAD

(as methodology) are not always distinguished by Steward: he says,

Emotion, an Organ of Happiness. Ruey-Yuan Wu National Tsing-Hua University

Current Issues in Pictorial Semiotics

A Letter from Louis Althusser on Gramsci s Thought

Thomas Szanto: Bewusstsein, Intentionalität und mentale Repräsentation. Husserl und die analytische Philosophie des Geistes

WHY STUDY THE HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY? 1

Sight and Sensibility: Evaluating Pictures Mind, Vol April 2008 Mind Association 2008

Objectivity and Perfection in Hume s Hedonism. Dale Dorsey

In his essay "Of the Standard of Taste," Hume describes an apparent conflict between two

Marina Frasca-Spada. Space and Self in Hume s Treatise Lorne Falkenstein Hume Studies Volume XXV, Number 1 and 2 (April/November, 1999)

Forms and Causality in the Phaedo. Michael Wiitala

Adam Smith and The Theory of Moral Sentiments

Naïve realism without disjunctivism about experience

Why Pleasure Gains Fifth Rank: Against the Anti-Hedonist Interpretation of the Philebus 1

Plato s work in the philosophy of mathematics contains a variety of influential claims and arguments.

How Semantics is Embodied through Visual Representation: Image Schemas in the Art of Chinese Calligraphy *

Cognition and Sensation: A Reconstruction of Herder s Quasi-Empiricism

Tradition and the Individual Poem: An Inquiry into Anthologies (review)

Phenomenology and Non-Conceptual Content

Hegel's Absolute: An Introduction to Reading the Phenomenology of Spirit

KONG Zhong-min. South China Business College of Guangdong University of Foreign Studies (GDUFS), Guangzhou, China. Introduction

The Dramatic Nature of Our Selves: David Hume and the Theatre Metaphor

Hume s First Principle, His Missing Shade, and His Distinctions of Reason Karann Durland Hume Studies Volume XXII, Number 1 (April, 1996)

What do our appreciation of tonal music and tea roses, our acquisition of the concepts

Anyon, Jean (2009). Theory and Educational Research: Toward Critical Social Explanation. New York and London: Routledge.

Culture, Space and Time A Comparative Theory of Culture. Take-Aways

PHIL 480: Seminar in the History of Philosophy Building Moral Character: Neo-Confucianism and Moral Psychology

Practical Intuition and Rhetorical Example. Paul Schollmeier

Introduction to The Handbook of Economic Methodology

AESTHETICS. Key Terms

The Psychology of Justice

What counts as a convincing scientific argument? Are the standards for such evaluation

Part IV Social Science and Network Theory

Alistair Heys, The Anatomy of Bloom: Harold Bloom and the Study of Influence and Anxiety.

TEST BANK. Chapter 1 Historical Studies: Some Issues

Hypatia, Volume 21, Number 3, Summer 2006, pp (Review) DOI: /hyp For additional information about this article

Poetics (Penguin Classics) PDF

What Can Experimental Philosophy Do? David Chalmers

observation and conceptual interpretation

The Singapore Copyright Act applies to the use of this document.

Subjectivity and Truth review

Date Inferred Table 1. LCCN Dates

Conclusion. One way of characterizing the project Kant undertakes in the Critique of Pure Reason is by

Published in: International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 29(2) (2015):

Guide to the Republic as it sets up Plato s discussion of education in the Allegory of the Cave.

Normative and Positive Economics

PHILOSOPHY. Grade: E D C B A. Mark range: The range and suitability of the work submitted

Kant IV The Analogies The Schematism updated: 2/2/12. Reading: 78-88, In General

Narrative Case Study Research

SAMPLE COURSE OUTLINE PHILOSOPHY AND ETHICS GENERAL YEAR 12

Rethinking the Aesthetic Experience: Kant s Subjective Universality

Book Reviews Department of Philosophy and Religion Appalachian State University 401 Academy Street Boone, NC USA

Objective vs. Subjective

Could Hume Save His Account of Personal Identity? On the Role of Contiguity in the Constitution of Our Idea of Personal Identity 1

Book Review. John Dewey s Philosophy of Spirit, with the 1897 Lecture on Hegel. Jeff Jackson. 130 Education and Culture 29 (1) (2013):

On Recanati s Mental Files

The interest in exploring fame and the

Creative Actualization: A Meliorist Theory of Values

Transcription:

Dabney Townsend. Hume s Aesthetic Theory: Taste and Sentiment Timothy M. Costelloe Hume Studies Volume XXVIII, Number 1 (April, 2002) 168-172. Your use of the HUME STUDIES archive indicates your acceptance of HUME STUDIES Terms and Conditions of Use, available at http://www.humesociety.org/hs/about/terms.html. HUME STUDIES Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in the HUME STUDIES archive only for your personal, non-commercial use. Each copy of any part of a HUME STUDIES transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission. For more information on HUME STUDIES contact humestudies-info@humesociety.org http://www.humesociety.org/hs/

HUME STUDIES Volume 28, Number 1, April 2002, pp. 168-171 DABNEY TOWNSEND. Hume s Aesthetic Theory: Taste and Sentiment. Routledge Studies in Eighteenth Century Philosophy. New York: Routledge, 2001. Pp. x + 258. ISBN 0415233968, cloth, $85.00. Although one might reasonably ask whether the explicit references to taste, beauty, and deformity, scattered through Hume s writings really amount to an aesthetic theory, both the ubiquity of the language and the apparently unself-conscious way in which Hume employs it, provide good food for philosophical thought. Perhaps, one might speculate, there are systematic connections between the aesthetic dimension of Hume s thinking and his approach to epistemology and morals for which he is better known. While many have gestured towards such a possibility, and a substantial body of work has grown around Hume s celebrated essay Of the Standard of Taste, it is only with Dabney Townsend s Hume s Aesthetic Theory: Taste and Sentiment that a book-length study has been devoted specifically to this theme. The work should thus be of great interest to Hume scholars, aestheticians, and students of eighteenth-century thought more generally. As is clear from the outset, the relative dearth of inquiry into the place of aesthetics in Hume s overall system does not deter Townsend from proposing a strikingly bold thesis. Townsend claims not only that there is substantial aesthetic material embedded in Hume s major philosophical works, but that this implicit aesthetic is crucial to a better understanding of the way that Hume deals with those central philosophical problems that occupy him (1). As a bonus, the reader is promised a needed corrective to Hume being read as a problem-poser or proto-naturalist, and an example of how to make a historical figure like Hume relevant to our time (2). All this is to be accomplished, Townsend assures the reader, by taking a middle way between a sensitivity to the eighteenth century context of Hume s work, and acceptance of the unavoidably anachronistic tendencies embedded in our knowledge of the subsequent history of aesthetics (2-3). Townsend sets out on the historical part of this adventure in the company of Shaftesbury. This union is advertised as the most suitable way to understand how Hume breaks with the past and comes to make sentiment evidential, bringing beauty and taste, that is, within the purview of his epistemology (13). One would have thought of Addison and Hutcheson as more natural brothers-in-arms, but Townsend opts for Shaftesbury since (presumably) in the latter s Characteristics he sees a way of illustrating both Hume s debt to his predecessors (an emphasis on the place of the passions ) as well HUME STUDIES

BOOK REVIEWS 169 as a contrast for his radical departure from them ( only passions can move us to action [18; see 25, 331). The historical jaunt continues in chapter two where the theme of Hume s specific intellectual debts gives way to a lively and informative history of taste. The reader follows the term from its Aristotelian roots as a modification of touch (49), through its development under Renaissance tutelage into a way of apportioning praise and blame (SZff.), to life as an eighteenth-century term of art. Via the pens of Shaftesbury, Berkeley, Hume, and Du Bos, Townsend shows how taste forged conceptual ties to diversity, individuality, and personality, maturing finally into a fullblown metaphor for approving judgments that display delicacy and discrimination, and condemning their opposites (62ff.). In chapter three- Hume s Appeal to Sentiment -Townsend crosses from the historical side of his middle way to the more contentious claims concerning the implicit aesthetics without which, the reader is informed, Hume s philosophy fragments into a series of problems, none of which can be understood consistently (87). Townsend attempts to support this thesis by bringing Hume s aesthetics into the same philosophical universe as his epistemology: Hume s theory of ideas is central, Townsend urges, because both knowledge and the appreciation of beauty reduce to the same fundamental problem, namely, how a psychological entity-the mind-through its own actions construes a world (87). Forging a link in this way, Townsend sees impressions and ideas as a foundation for the aesthetics of art by linking the felt, emotional nature of ideas to their representational function (87). The crucial question, of course, is whether one can really move, in a Humean idiom, from an impression of something beautiful to an idea about it. Townsend s response to the most obyious objection-that Hume neither thinks of beauty in these terms nor ever speaks of aesthetic impressions -is to claim that an epistemologized aesthetic is implicit in his scheme. Incorporating sentiment into reason implies an aesthetic more or less explicitly, Townsend maintains (121), such that from Hume s treatment of sympathy and imagination (99ff.), pleasure and pain (108ff.), and the passions (116ff.), a genuine (though non-extant) component of Hume s approach can be extrapolated. In chapter four, Townsend turns to the intriguing analogy between beauty and morals. Since, on Hume s view, Townsend argues, beauty is defined by passions rather any qualities in objects, moral beauty and deformity are also not relations of ideas, but have the same sentimental basis as their aesthetic cousins (138-39). Indeed, Townsend insists that there are no specifically aesthetic sentiments, with all conceptual kin tracing back to a common lineage in a generic notion of sentiment. Morals and aesthetics are only distinguishable in terms of manner or means (147) or context and situation (145; see also Volume 28, Number 1, April 2002

170 BOOK REVIEWS 134, 139). Townsend is clearly justified in noticing a family resemblance, as he is in emphasizing how moral and other kinds of beauty are correctable by reason (151), related in similar ways to sympathy (157), partake of pleasure and pain (148), and (reahst interpretations of Hume, notwithstanding) are not qualities in the object or conduct deemed beautiful or moral (156). Yet placing such stress on sentiment glosses over a central issue: what Hume recognizes is that pleasure varies between objects of taste-wine cannot be harmonious or music of a good flavor (Treatise, 471)-and that morals in particular involve pleasure of a peculiar kind (T 3.1.2.4; SBN 471; emphasis in original). Sometimes the sentiments attached to interest are confounded with those attaching to morals, Hume remarks, but they are, in themselves, distinct (T 3.1.2.4; SBN 472). In fact, the somewhat confusing aspect of Townsend s discussion is that while he sees Hume as placing morality and aesthetic judgments on exactly the same footing (147), he also finds significant differences between the two classes of phenomena: unlike their moral counterparts, Townsend reports, aesthetic sentiments do not move one to action (139), have less effect on society (140), are tied to taste rather than to character (141, 146), fall more on the side of immediate sense (144), and, most notably, do not involve that complex double relation of ideas peculiar to the anatomy of virtues such as pride and humility (143, 149). In the penultimate chapter, Townsend turns to general rules which, if there is a link between epistemology and aesthetics, should loom large in the latter part of Hume s thought. In perhaps the most lucid discussion of the book, Townsend emphasizes how such rules are non-prescriptive principles consisting of empirical facts raised to the level of causal explanation (159-60). They at once explain uniformity in human affairs and serve a limiting function (166ff.), indicating how, on the basis of past experience, persons can be expected to act according to their most strongly held beliefs (158-60). If rules are, as Townsend emphasizes, the products of accumulated experience (159), they will play this same role in all areas of common life, whether in the realm of knowledge, morals, or the appreciation of beauty (166ff.). Given this insightful account of general rules, one might have expected Townsend to apply it to Of the Standard of Taste where Hume explicitly characterizes his search for a standard in terms of such a rule by which the various sentiments of men may be reconciled. 2 Despite Hume s own avowal, however, when Townsend considers the essay in his fifth and final chapter, he denies that a rule and a standard are one and the same (200-l), linking the latter instead to the delicacy of taste (the ability to produce rules ) (204ff.) and, ultimately, to Hume s figure of the critic or true judge. This means that the true standard is not the rules but the critics who give rise to the rules HUME STUDIES

BOOK REVIEWS 1 7 1 (210). Yet at the same time, Townsend argues that rules do exhibit models and principles, and that those who recognize the latter have their delicacy acknowledged as superior, and... as a standard of taste (207). A standard is thus an empirical fact, hardly a surprising conclusion except Townsend has already argued that general rules are empirical facts, albeit ones raised to the level of causal explanation. How, one might ask, do rules then differ from standards? And what does it mean to deny that rules differ from standards of taste when taste issues in a rule (189)? This could be little more than a terminological infelicity, though it does form part of a general tendency for the medium of Townsend s work sometimes to obscure its philosophical message. One reaches the end of the book (which comes abruptly and without a much-needed conclusion) with a sense that the bold conception behind the effort was too often hampered by its mode of execution. This might be responsible for the added problem that Townsend never really explains why Hume s thought fragments if the aesthetic dimension is ignored. Another possibility, of course, is that such a thesis is simply extreme, and that while exploring Hume s interest in beauty and deformity can shed light on other aspects of his thinking, it is unlikely that it plays the decisive role Townsend awards it. That, however, remains a matter for research and debate, and Townsend is to be commended for writing a book that will inspire just that. TIMOTHY M. COSTELLOE Department of Philosophy The College of William and Mary PO Box 8795 Williamsburg, VA 23187-8795, USA tmcost@wm.edu NOTES 1 I quote from David Hume, A Treatise of Human Nature, ed. David Fate Norton and Mary J. Norton, Oxford Philosophical Texts (Oxford: Oxford University Press, ZOOO), and provide section and paragraph number in the text, followed by page references to Hume, A Treatise of Human Nature, ed. L. A. Selby-Bigge, 2nd ed., revised by P. H. Nidditch (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1978). 2. In David Hume, Essays: Moral, Political, andliterary, ed. Eugene F. Miller (Indianapolis: LibertyCiassics, 1985), 229. Volume 28, Number 1, April 2002