Class 5: Language processing over a noisy channel. Ted Gibson 9.59J/24.905J

Similar documents
Problems. Speech Perception Facts and things. Talker Normalization. Lack of Invariance Problem. Why the lack of invariance?

Sentence Processing. BCS 152 October

17. Semantics in L1A

Jokes and the Linguistic Mind. Debra Aarons. New York, New York: Routledge Pp. xi +272.

Lecture 18: Production & Perception

Comparison, Categorization, and Metaphor Comprehension

Families Have Rules. homework rule. family dishes. Write the words and then match them to the correct pictures.

Lecture 7. Scope and Anaphora. October 27, 2008 Hana Filip 1

The structure of this ppt. Sentence types An overview Yes/no questions WH-questions

Comprehension Lab! Comprehension Lab! Comprehension Lab! Comprehension Lab! Comprehension Lab! Comprehension Lab! e.g. I have a headache. e.g.

Two Styles of Construction Grammar Do Ditransitives

Teacher Edition. alphakids. Making Music. Written by Hannah Reed. Photography by Michael Curtain

LING/C SC 581: Advanced Computational Linguistics. Lecture Notes Feb 6th

CS 5014: Research Methods in Computer Science

Linking semantic and pragmatic factors in the Japanese Internally Headed Relative Clause

Image and Imagination

Acoustic Prosodic Features In Sarcastic Utterances

(The) most in Dutch: Definiteness and Specificity. Koen Roelandt CRISSP, KU Leuven HUBrussel

Introduction to Natural Language Processing Phase 2: Question Answering

Introduction to English Linguistics (I) Professor Seongha Rhee

Sentence Processing III. LIGN 170, Lecture 8

Comprehenders Rationally Adapt Semantic Predictions to the Statistics of the Local Environment: a Bayesian Model of Trial-by-Trial N400 Amplitudes

In the sentence above we find the article "a". It shows us that the speaker does not need a specific chair. He can have any chair.

TABLE OF CONTENTS. Free resource from Commercial redistribution prohibited. Language Smarts TM Level D.

January 11, 2015 LSA 2015

Some Basic Concepts. Highlights of Chapter 1, 2, 3.

Three Minute Review. validity of IQ tests some predictive use, but not great. Other types of intelligence

Linguistics 001 Midterm 1 Fall 2016 October 24, 2016

LESSON TWELVE VAGUITY AND AMBIGUITY

About the Author. Support. Transcript Learn English Article 118

EZ-220 Page Turner Owner s Manual

COMMON GRAMMAR ERRORS. By: Dr. Elham Alzoubi

Score Criterion Criterion Date of Birth Third Person Singular. Chronological Age Past Tense Be/Do (Be) Elicited Grammar Composite Be/Do (Do)

Semantics and Generative Grammar. Conversational Implicature: The Basics of the Gricean Theory 1

What s New in the 17th Edition

SPEED DRILL WARM-UP ACTIVITY

The structure of this ppt. Structural and categorial (and some functional) issues: English Hungarian

PRONOUNS (4) Personal Pronouns vs Object Pronoun (01)

ENGLISH ENGLISH AMERICAN. Level 1. Tests

(Refer Slide Time 1:58)

BIO + OLOGY = PHILEIN + ANTHROPOS = BENE + VOLENS = GOOD WILL MAL + VOLENS =? ANTHROPOS + OLOGIST = English - Language Arts Step 6

GOING OUT (05) At the movies (04) - Buying tickets (2)

Code : is a set of practices familiar to users of the medium

Making psycholinguistics musical: Self-paced reading time evidence for shared processing of linguistic and musical syntax

Toward Computational Recognition of Humorous Intent

PEER REVIEW HISTORY ARTICLE DETAILS TITLE (PROVISIONAL)

A picture of the grammar. Sense and Reference. A picture of the grammar. A revised picture. Foundations of Semantics LING 130 James Pustejovsky

Meaning 1. Semantics is concerned with the literal meaning of sentences of a language.

Lesson 17: Giving an Apology/Explanation (20-25 minutes)

Mind, Thinking and Creativity

How to edit syntax trees on the surface

interpreting figurative meaning

ELECTROPHYSIOLOGICAL INSIGHTS INTO LANGUAGE AND SPEECH PROCESSING

Network Working Group. Category: Informational Preston & Lynch R. Daniel Los Alamos National Laboratory February 1998

When Do Vehicles of Similes Become Figurative? Gaze Patterns Show that Similes and Metaphors are Initially Processed Differently

Introduction to In-Text Citations

Back and forth: real-time computation of linguistic dependencies. Wing-Yee Chow (University College London)

7. The English Caused-Motion Construction. Presenter: 林岱瑩

KANT S TRANSCENDENTAL LOGIC

Western School of Technology and Environmental Science First Quarter Reading Assignment ENGLISH 10 GT

Basic Natural Language Processing

10 Steps To Effective Listening

For Big Kids. Idioms. Jen Bengels

Exploring the Monty Hall Problem. of mistakes, primarily because they have fewer experiences to draw from and therefore

Manuel Bremer University Lecturer, Philosophy Department, University of Düsseldorf, Germany

Commas - 1. Name: The comma will put a PAUSE in your sentence. The comma allows you to combine 2 IDEAS into one sentence.

The Syntax and Semantics of Traces Danny Fox, MIT. How are traces interpreted given the copy theory of movement?

Note for Applicants on Coverage of Forth Valley Local Television

Fountas-Pinnell Level J Fantasy. by Rob Arego

The Effect of Context on the Interpretation of Noun-Noun Combinations: Eye Movement and Behavioral Evidence

Incommensurability and Partial Reference

Novel Units Single-Classroom User Agreement for Non-Reproducible Material

Prepped & Polished, LLC 14 SAT Sentence Improvement No Problems Questions, Answers, Detailed Explanations

WRITING FOLDER BOOKLET

The structure of this ppt

Clusters and Correspondences. A comparison of two exploratory statistical techniques for semantic description

The ACL Anthology Network Corpus. University of Michigan

Music Performance Panel: NICI / MMM Position Statement

Lecture 13: Chapter 10: Semantics

Vagueness & Pragmatics

Curriculum Map: Academic English 11 Meadville Area Senior High School English Department

Simple passive GRAMMAR

Fry Instant Phrases. First 100 Words/Phrases

Lecture 10 Popper s Propensity Theory; Hájek s Metatheory

February 16, 2007 Menéndez-Benito. Challenges/ Problems for Carlson 1977

Interplay between Syntax and Semantics during Sentence Comprehension: ERP Effects of Combining Syntactic and Semantic Violations

What is Character? David Braun. University of Rochester. In "Demonstratives", David Kaplan argues that indexicals and other expressions have a

I-language Chapter 8: Anaphor Binding

organise (dis- is a prefix and ed is a suffix.) What is the root word in disorganised?

Fountas-Pinnell Level L Realistic Fiction. by Claire Daniel

Michigan Arts Education Instructional and Assessment Program Michigan Assessment Consortium. MUSIC Assessment

Preparing a Paper for Publication. Julie A. Longo, Technical Writer Sue Wainscott, STEM Librarian

! Japanese: a wh-in-situ language. ! Taroo-ga [ DP. ! Taroo-ga [ CP. ! Wh-words don t move. Islands don t matter.

S. 2 English Revision Exercises. Unit 1 Basic English Sentence Patterns

On Recanati s Mental Files

WHEN AND HOW DO WE DEAL

The HKIE Outstanding Paper Award for Young Engineers/Researchers 2019 Instructions for Authors

Semantic Analysis in Language Technology

Digital Filmmaking For Kids

Face-threatening Acts: A Dynamic Perspective

Transcription:

Class 5: Language processing over a noisy channel Ted Gibson 9.59J/24.905J

Review from last time: Mahowald et al. 2013 Words with a long/ short form (e.g., math, mathematics) are preferred as short in a supportive context. Question: is this because of audience design: the desire to help out our conversation participants? Answer: it s impossible to tell based purely on corpus data. Evidence for audience design: Clark (1996): Asking for directions: Speakers use words that are appropriate to listeners background knowledge. But maybe this difference reflects different lexical knowledge? Wilkes-Gibbs & Clark (1992): participants coordinating over names for objects of tangrams, moving them around. Directors who talk to one listener first and then have to describe the same tangrams to a naïve listener use more words with the naïve person. (Probably not an effect of lexicon.)

Language for communication? More controversial than some might think... The natural approach has always been: Is it well designed for use, understood typically as use for communication? I think that s the wrong question. The use of language for communication might turn out to be a kind of epiphenomenon.... If you want to make sure that we never misunderstand one another, for that purpose language is not well designed, because you have such properties as ambiguity. If we want to have the property that the things that we usually would like to say come out short and simple, well, it probably doesn t have that property. (Chomsky, 2002, p. 107) Portrait of Noam Chomsky removed for copyright restrictions.

Ambiguity Syntax: Frank shot the hunter with the shotgun. Lexicon: run (polysemy); two/to/too (homophony) Referential: He said that we should give it to them.

Ambiguity: A communicative benefit Ambiguity is only a problem in theory Ambiguity is not a problem in normal language use, because context disambiguates (Wasow & Arnold, 2003;Wasow et al., 2005; Jaeger, 2006; Roland, Elman, & Ferreira, 2006; Ferreira, 2008; Jaeger, 2010). Piantadosi,Tily & Gibson (2012): An information-theoretic proof that efficient communication systems will necessarily be globally ambiguous when context is informative about meaning ambiguity potentially allows for re-use of easy linguistic elements: John wanted to run. John went to school. John wanted two dollars. Sam wanted some money too.

Ambiguity: A communicative benefit Because context disambiguates, we don t have to say so much: When language is constructed to be as unambiguous as possible, with no other possible interpretations, what you get is legalese: EXCEPT FOR THE LIMITED WARRANTY ON MEDIA SET FORTH ABOVE AND TO THE MAXIMUM EXTENT PERMITTED BY APPLICABLE LAW,THE APPLE SOFTWARE AND SERVICES ARE PROVIDED AS IS AND AS AVAILABLE,WITH ALL FAULTS AND WITHOUT WARRANTY OF ANY KIND,AND APPLE AND APPLE'S LICENSORS (COLLECTIVELY REFERRED TO AS APPLE FOR THE PURPOSES OF SECTIONS 8 and 9) HEREBY DISCLAIM ALL WARRANTIES AND CONDITIONS WITH RESPECT TO THE APPLE SOFTWARE AND SERVICES, EITHER EXPRESS, IMPLIED OR STATUTORY, INCLUDING, BUT NOT LIMITED TO,THE IMPLIED WARRANTIES AND/OR CONDITIONS OF MERCHANTABILITY, OF SATISFACTORY QUALITY, OF FITNESS FOR A PARTICULAR PURPOSE, OF ACCURACY, OF QUIET ENJOYMENT,AND NON-INFRINGEMENT OF THIRD PARTY RIGHTS.

Language as efficient communication: Shorter words are more ambiguous Piantadosi,Tily & Gibson (2012) Courtesy of Elsevier, Inc., http://www.sciencedirect.com. Used with permission. Source: Piantadosi, Steven T., Harry Tily, and Edward Gibson. "The communicative function of ambiguity in language." Cognition 122, no. 3 (2012): 280-291. Number of additional meanings each phonological form has, as a function of length. Shorter phonological forms having more homophones / meanings.

Ambiguity: a communicative benefit The existence of ambiguity out of context in human language (which is disambiguated by context) is explained by information theory. In other approaches, the existence of ambiguity out of context is an unexplained accident.

Noisy-channel models of comprehension The Morning Bulletin. All rights reserved. This content is excluded from our Creative Commons license. For more information, see http://ocw.mit.edu/help/faq-fair-use/

Source Unknown. All rights reserved. This content is excluded from our Creative Commons license. For more information, see http://ocw.mit.edu/help/faqfair-use/ Thirty sows and pigs in a river Thirty thousand pigs in a river

Noisy-channel models of language comprehension: Mondegreens Wikipedia: American writer Sylvia Wright coined the term in her essay "The Death of Lady Mondegreen", published in Harper's Magazine in November 1954. 17th-century ballad "The Bonnie Earl o' Moray": Ye Highlands and ye Lowlands, Oh, where hae ye been? They hae slain the Earl o' Moray, And laid him on the green. Wright misheard the last line as And Lady Mondegreen In unsupportive contexts, more frequent words and phrases are sometimes perceived instead

Mondegreens in songs Creedence Clearwater Revival, Bad Moon Rising There's a bathroom on the right

Mondegreens in songs Creedence Clearwater Revival, Bad Moon Rising There's a bathroom on the right Manfred Mann, Blinded by the light wrapped up like a douche

Mondegreens in songs Creedence Clearwater Revival, Bad Moon Rising There's a bathroom on the right Manfred Mann, Blinded by the light wrapped up like a douche Jimi Hendrix, Purple Haze Excuse me while I kiss this guy

Mondegreens in songs Creedence Clearwater Revival, Bad Moon Rising There's a bathroom on the right Manfred Mann, Blinded by the light wrapped up like a douche Jimi Hendrix, Purple Haze Excuse me while I kiss this guy Rush, Limelight living in a fish island

Rational inference in language: Noisy-channel models of language thirty sows and pigs thirty thousand pigs Language for communication: The rational integration of noise and prior lexical, syntactic and semantic expectation: Maximize P(si sp) by maximizing P(si) * P(si sp) All linguistic measures (e.g., reading times, acceptability ratings) reflect: the prior expectation of what might be produced the likelihood of noise changing si into sp

Noisy-channel models of comprehension Classic assumption in sentence processing: input to the parser is an error-free sequence of words (e.g., Frazier & Fodor, 1978; Gibson, 1991, 1998; Jurafsky, 1996; Hale, 2001; Levy, 2008a). This assumption is problematic (e.g., Levy, 2008b). Many sources of noise: (a) perception errors (mis-hearing/mis-reading); the environment can be noisy (b) production errors (mis-speaking/mis-typing) Classic issue in signal processing (e.g., Shannon, 1948) Previous work: Speech (Jelinek, 1975; Clayards,Tanenhaus,Aslin & Jacobs, 2008); Memory (Botvinick, 2005); Reading (Levy et al., 2009)

Noisy-channel models of comprehension General prediction for sentence interpretation: The ultimate interpretation of a sentence should depend on the proximity of plausible alternatives under the noise model. A plausible noise model (cf. Levenshtein distance): some cost for deletions, insertions (maybe swaps?) (Gibson, Bergen & Piantadosi, 2013, PNAS)

Noisy-channel models of comprehension Testing the predictions: syntactic alternations: More changes leads to lower likelihood of inferring the alternative (cf. MacWhinney & Bates, 1989; Ferreira, 2003) Minor change alternations: PO-goal è DO-goal (1 deletion): The mother gave the candle to the daughter. è The mother gave the candle the daughter. DO-goal è PO-goal (1 insertion): The mother gave the daughter the candle. è The mother gave the daughter to the candle. Major change alternations: Passive è Active (2 deletions): The ball was kicked by the girl. è The ball kicked the girl. Active è Passive (2 insertions): The girl kicked the ball. è The girl was kicked by the ball.

Noisy-channel models of comprehension Design: manipulate plausibility (using role reversals) examine interpretation Interpretation was assessed with comprehension questions. Examples: a. Sentence: The ball kicked the girl. Question: Did the ball kick something/someone? b. Sentence: The mother gave the candle the daughter. Question: Did the daughter receive something/someone? E.g., in (a) a yes answer indicates that the reader relied on syntax (surface form) to interpret the sentence; a no answer indicates that the reader relied on semantics. The reverse holds for (b). (Gibson, Bergen & Piantadosi, 2013)

Results 1a. Passive -> Active: 1b. Active -> Passive: The ball was/ kicked by/ the girl. The girl /was kicked /by the ball. 2 deletions 2 insertions 2a. Subj-loc -> Obj-loc: deletion 2b. Obj-loc -> Subj-loc: insertion /Onto The cat jumped onto/ a table. 1 insertion, 1 Onto/ the table jumped /onto a cat. 1 deletion, 1 3a. Intrans ->Trans: The tax law benefited /from the businessman. 1 insertion 3b. Trans -> Intrans: The businessman benefited from/ the tax law. 1 deletion 4a. DO -> PO-goal: The mother gave the daughter /to the candle. 1 insertion 4b. PO -> DO-goal: The mother gave the candle to/ the daughter. 1 deletion 5a. DO -> PO-benef: The cook baked Lucy /for a cake. 1 insertion 5b. PO -> DO-benef: The cook baked a cake for/ Lucy. 1 deletion Courtesy of Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences. Used with permission. Source: Gibson, Edward, Leon Bergen, and Steven T. Piantadosi. "Rational integration of noisy evidence and prior semantic expectations in sentence interpretation." Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences 110, no. 20 (2013): 8051-8056. More changes lead to a greater reliance on syntax: major changes (93.4%) vs. minor changes: (56.1%) Deletions are perceived to be more likely than insertions, leading to lower likelihood of literal meaning for deletions: single insertions (66.1%) vs. single deletions (46.0%)

Results 1a. Passive -> Active: The ball was/ kicked by/ the girl. 2 deletions 1b. Active -> Passive: The girl /was kicked /by the ball. 2 insertions 2a. Subj-loc -> Obj-loc: /Onto The cat jumped onto/ a table. 1 insertion, 1 deletion 2b. Obj-loc -> Subj-loc: Onto/ the table jumped /onto a cat. 1 deletion, 1 insertion 3a. Intrans ->Trans: The tax law benefited /from the businessman. 1 insertion 3b. Trans -> Intrans: The businessman benefited from/ the tax law. 1 deletion 4a. DO -> PO-goal: The mother gave the daughter /to the candle. 1 insertion 4b. PO -> DO-goal: The mother gave the candle to/ the daughter. 1 deletion 5a. DO -> PO-benef: The cook baked Lucy /for a cake. 1 insertion 5b. PO -> DO-benef: The cook baked a cake for/ Lucy. 1 deletion Prediction: more noise should lead to greater reliance on likely meaning Courtesy of Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences. Used with permission. Source: Gibson, Edward, Leon Bergen, and Steven T. Piantadosi. "Rational integration of noisy evidence and prior semantic expectations in sentence interpretation." Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences 110, no. 20 (2013): 8051-8056. Manipulation: add noise to 30 of the 60 fillers 10 - extra function word; 10 - missing function word; 10 - local transpositions

Results expectations Courtesy of Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences. Used with permission. Source: Gibson, Edward, Leon Bergen, and Steven T. Piantadosi. "Rational integration of noisy evidence and prior semantic in sentence interpretation." Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences 110, no. 20 (2013): 8051-8056. 1a. Passive -> Active: The ball was/ kicked by/ the girl. 2 deletions 1b. Active -> Passive: The girl /was kicked /by the ball. 2 insertions 2a. Subj-loc -> Obj-loc: /Onto The cat jumped onto/ a table. 1 insertion, 1 deletion 2b. Obj-loc -> Subj-loc: Onto/ the table jumped /onto a cat. 1 deletion, 1 insertion 3a. Intrans ->Trans: The tax law benefited /from the businessman. 1 insertion 3b. Trans -> Intrans: The businessman benefited from/ the tax law. 1 deletion 4a. DO -> PO-goal: The mother gave the daughter /to the candle. 1 insertion 4b. PO -> DO-goal: The mother gave the candle to/ the daughter. 1 deletion 5a. DO -> PO-benef: The cook baked Lucy /for a cake. 1 insertion 5b. PO -> DO-benef: The cook baked a cake for/ Lucy. 1 deletion More syntactic errors decreased the reliance on syntax: 56.1% vs. 42.7 for the minor-change alternations

Noisy-channel models of comprehension Manipulations of semantic / plausibility prior: Plausibility prior: how likely it is that an implausible utterance will be generated Leon Expt 1a - 1e: Each was run with 60 plausible fillers. Implausible ratio = 1/8 (10 implaus + 70 plaus) Expt 3a - 3e: Each was run with 60 plausible fillers plus the materials in the other experiments. Implausible ratio = 5/16 (50 implaus + 110 plaus) Steve

Results prior Courtesy of Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences. Used with permission. Source: Gibson, Edward, Leon Bergen, and Steven T. Piantadosi. "Rational integration of noisy evidence and semantic expectations in sentence interpretation." Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences 110, no. 20 (2013): 8051-8056. 1a. Passive -> Active: The ball was/ kicked by/ the girl. 2 deletions 1b. Active -> Passive: The girl /was kicked /by the ball. 2 insertions 2a. Subj-loc -> Obj-loc: /Onto The cat jumped onto/ a table. 1 insertion, 1 deletion 2b. Obj-loc -> Subj-loc: Onto/ the table jumped /onto a cat. 1 deletion, 1 insertion 3a. Intrans ->Trans: The tax law benefited /from the businessman. 1 insertion 3b. Trans -> Intrans: The businessman benefited from/ the tax law. 1 deletion 4a. DO -> PO-goal: The mother gave the daughter /to the candle. 1 insertion 4b. PO -> DO-goal: The mother gave the candle to/ the daughter. 1 deletion 5a. DO -> PO-benef: The cook baked Lucy /for a cake. 1 insertion 5b. PO -> DO-benef: The cook baked a cake for/ Lucy. 1 deletion More implausible materials increased the reliance on syntax: 56.1% vs. 72.6 for the minor-change alternations

Noisy-channel models of comprehension Summary: Evidence for a noise model: 1. People are more likely to infer the plausible alternative if it involves inferring fewer errors. Leon 2. People are more likely to infer the plausible alternative if it is one deletion away compared to one insertion. 3. Increasing the noise increases the reliance on plausibility. Steve Evidence for priors: 1. Plausibility Prior: Increasing the likelihood of implausible events decreases the reliance on semantics. (Gibson, Bergen & Piantadosi, 2013, PNAS)

Agreement errors: the result of noisy-channel in comprehension? (Bergen & Gibson, 2012) A classic finding in the sentence production literature (Bock & Miller, 1991) and comprehension (Pearlmutter, Garnsey & Bock, 1999): Agreement error asymmetry: 1.The key to the cabinets was / were on the table. (Many errors for plural local noun) 2.The keys to the cabinet were /??was on the table. (Very few errors for singular local noun) Standard explanation: there is a markedness difference between singular vs. plural nouns, in memory retrieval / sentence planning. Stipulation

Agreement errors: the result of noisy-channel in comprehension? (Bergen & Gibson, 2012) Note it is currently unclear if either kind of attraction error is more common in natural speech / text. It is easy to find examples of both plural and singular attraction errors in people s speech / writing: Singular attractions: The stairwells on the BCS Headquarters side of the building is in the process of being painted. (email to BCS department April 2013) The consequences of that is... (talk at MIT, Oct, 2013) Leon

Agreement errors: the result of noisy-channel in comprehension? (Bergen & Gibson, 2012) Our claim: Agreement errors result from rational misidentification of the preamble. The asymmetry between singular and plural head-nouns is explained by 2 factors: Deletions are much more likely than insertions (Gibson et al, 2013). Thus agreement errors will occur more often when the head noun is singular. Prior distribution of NP sequences: the singular-singular is much the most common sequence. Thus there will be few errors confusing sing-sing as plural-sing. Plural-head/Singular-local The keys to the cabinet Given the plural head noun, it is unlikely that the comprehender will infer that the plural-marking was produced by mistake, so unlikely to be pulled to the sing-sing. Singular-head/Plural-local The key to the cabinets... Given the singular head noun, it is possible that the comprehender will think that the producer intended a plural / plural, hence producing an error.

9.59J/24.905J Lab in Psycholinguistics Spring 2017 For information about citing these materials or our Terms of Use, visit: https://ocw.mit.edu/terms.