Imperatives are existential modals; Deriving the must-reading as an Implicature. Despina Oikonomou (MIT)

Similar documents
Or what? Or what?: Challenging the speaker. NELS 46, Concordia. Or what questions are strategies for re-asking a big question.

The Syntax and Semantics of Traces Danny Fox, MIT. How are traces interpreted given the copy theory of movement?

Comparatives, Indices, and Scope

MONOTONE AMAZEMENT RICK NOUWEN

Possible Ramifications for Superiority

Positive vs. negative inversion exclamatives

Topics in Linguistic Theory: Propositional Attitudes

Vagueness & Pragmatics

Deriving the Interpretation of Rhetorical Questions

Review of Epistemic Modality

The Reference Book, by John Hawthorne and David Manley. Oxford: Oxford University Press 2012, 280 pages. ISBN

Negative Inversion Exclamatives

Articulating Medieval Logic, by Terence Parsons. Oxford: Oxford University Press,

Intro to Pragmatics (Fox/Menéndez-Benito) 10/12/06. Questions 1

Picture Descriptions and Centered Content

[WLG] Permission to be ironic: The case of German dürfen. Milena Sisovics. Sonderdruck aus: Wiener Linguistische Gazette (WLG) ():

Diagnosing covert pied-piping *

What is Character? David Braun. University of Rochester. In "Demonstratives", David Kaplan argues that indexicals and other expressions have a

On Meaning. language to establish several definitions. We then examine the theories of meaning

On Recanati s Mental Files

Intensional Relative Clauses and the Semantics of Variable Objects

An HPSG Account of Depictive Secondary Predicates and Free Adjuncts: A Problem for the Adjuncts-as-Complements Approach

1. PSEUDO-IMPERATIVES IN ENGLISH Characterization.

Mind Association. Oxford University Press and Mind Association are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Mind.

Degree modifiers and monotonicity

The structure of this ppt. Sentence types An overview Yes/no questions WH-questions

A critical pragmatic approach to irony

Semantics and Generative Grammar. Conversational Implicature: The Basics of the Gricean Theory 1

Reviewed by Max Kölbel, ICREA at Universitat de Barcelona

Formalizing Irony with Doxastic Logic

Speaker s Meaning, Speech Acts, Topic and Focus, Questions

Lecture 7. Scope and Anaphora. October 27, 2008 Hana Filip 1

Where are we? Lecture 37: Modelling Conversations. Gap. Conversations

The identity theory of truth and the realm of reference: where Dodd goes wrong

Non-Reducibility with Knowledge wh: Experimental Investigations

PLEASE SCROLL DOWN FOR ARTICLE

An Experiment in Methods: Speech Act Theory in the Poems of Wallace Stevens

Semantic Research Methodology

Reply to Stalnaker. Timothy Williamson. In Models and Reality, Robert Stalnaker responds to the tensions discerned in Modal Logic

Lessons from Descriptive Indexicals

Partial and Paraconsistent Approaches to Future Contingents in Tense Logic

What Can Experimental Philosophy Do? David Chalmers

CHAPTER I INTRODUCTION. language such as in a play or a film. Meanwhile the written dialogue is a dialogue

How to express yourself: On the discourse effect of wh-exclamatives

The Strengths and Weaknesses of Frege's Critique of Locke By Tony Walton

Formalising arguments

Communication Mechanism of Ironic Discourse

Answering negative questions in American Sign Language

The Role of the Imperfect in Romance Counterfactuals * Pranav Anand & Valentine Hacquard

Subjective attitudes and counterstance contingency *

The Embedding Problem for Non-Cognitivism; Introduction to Cognitivism; Motivational Externalism

Mind, Thinking and Creativity

Replies to the Critics

Jokes and the Linguistic Mind. Debra Aarons. New York, New York: Routledge Pp. xi +272.

Polysemy in the meaning of come: Two senses with a common conceptual core

Resemblance Nominalism: A Solution to the Problem of Universals. GONZALO RODRIGUEZ-PEREYRA. Oxford: Clarendon Press, Pp. xii, 238.

Can emotion-based moral disagreements be resolved?

Verity Harte Plato on Parts and Wholes Clarendon Press, Oxford 2002

Kuhn Formalized. Christian Damböck Institute Vienna Circle University of Vienna

Crosslinguistic Notions of (In)definiteness *

Nissim Francez: Proof-theoretic Semantics College Publications, London, 2015, xx+415 pages

Bas C. van Fraassen, Scientific Representation: Paradoxes of Perspective, Oxford University Press, 2008.

Linking semantic and pragmatic factors in the Japanese Internally Headed Relative Clause

Quine s Two Dogmas of Empiricism. By Spencer Livingstone

Ling 720 Implicit Arguments, Week 11 Barbara H. Partee, Nov 25, 2009

The Cognitive Nature of Metonymy and Its Implications for English Vocabulary Teaching

Background to Gottlob Frege

BBC LEARNING ENGLISH 6 Minute Grammar Adverb position 1

WINONA STATE UNIVERSITY PROPOSAL FOR GENERAL EDUCATION PROGRAM COURSES

1 Pair-list readings and single pair readings

February 16, 2007 Menéndez-Benito. Challenges/ Problems for Carlson 1977

Chapter One Beginnings of Intensional Semantics

Conclusion. One way of characterizing the project Kant undertakes in the Critique of Pure Reason is by

A New Analysis of Verbal Irony

What do our appreciation of tonal music and tea roses, our acquisition of the concepts

Narrative Dimensions of Philosophy

Lingua Inglese 3. Lecture 5. Searle s Classification of Speech Acts. Representatives: the speaker is committed in

Aristotle s Modal Syllogistic. Marko Malink. Cambridge Harvard University Press, Pp X $ 45,95 (hardback). ISBN:

Irony as Cognitive Deviation

By Tetsushi Hirano. PHENOMENOLOGY at the University College of Dublin on June 21 st 2013)

Depiction Verbs and the Definiteness Effect DRAFT 1. This paper is part of a longer project on the semantics of depiction verbs and

CAS LX 522 Syntax I. Islands. Wh-islands. Phases. Complex Noun Phrase islands. Adjunct islands

Philosophy Department Expanded Course Descriptions Fall, 2007

BOOK REVIEWS. University of Southern California. The Philosophical Review, XCI, No. 2 (April 1982)

ANALOGY, SCHEMATISM AND THE EXISTENCE OF GOD

FictionalAssert and Implicatures

ARISTOTLE AND THE UNITY CONDITION FOR SCIENTIFIC DEFINITIONS ALAN CODE [Discussion of DAVID CHARLES: ARISTOTLE ON MEANING AND ESSENCE]

CHAPTER I INTRODUCTION

A difficulty in the foundation of Analytic Philosophy

MATH 195: Gödel, Escher, and Bach (Spring 2001) Notes and Study Questions for Tuesday, March 20

A Note on Analysis and Circular Definitions

Rhetorical Questions and Scales

Singular Propositions, Abstract Constituents, and Propositional Attitudes

In Defense of the Contingently Nonconcrete

HOW TO WRITE A SEMINAR PAPER

Visual Argumentation in Commercials: the Tulip Test 1

Time and again: the intriguing life of a temporal adverb

Handout 3 Verb Phrases: Types of modifier. Modifier Maximality Principle Non-head constituents are maximal projections, i.e., phrases (XPs).

Developing a Semantic Fieldwork Project November 5, 2013

Vision and Intentional Content

Transcription:

Imperatives are existential modals; Deriving the must-reading as an Implicature Despina Oikonomou (MIT) The dual character of Imperatives with respect to their quantificational force has been a longlasting puzzle in the literature (Han 2000, Schwager 2006 / Kaufmann 2012, Portner 2007, Condoravdi & Lauer 2012, von Fintel & Iatridou 2015). The sentence in (1) gets a can-reading in a context where the Addressee wants to open the window (permission) and a must-reading in an out-of-the-blue context where a Professor asks a student to open the window (command): (1) Open the window. In this talk I argue that Imperatives involve an existential modal. The universal reading is explained on the basis of two factors; i) lack of a scalar counterpart as opposed to overt modals (cf. Deal 2011) ii) strengthening via an Implicature derived in the presence of certain Focus Alternatives (cf. Schwager 2005). First, I present an analysis of Imperatives as existential modals; Evidence for such an analysis comes from scopal ambiguities with only. Then, I provide an analysis for the emergrence of the must-reading. - 1 -

Introduction The dual character of Imperatives with respect to their quantificational force has been a long-lasting puzzle in the literature (Han 2000, Schwager 2006 / Kaufmann 2012, Portner 2007, Condoravdi & Lauer 2012, von Fintel & Iatridou 2015). The sentence in (1) gets a canreading in a context where the Addressee wants to open the window (permission) and a mustreading in an out-of-the-blue context where a Professor asks a student to open the window (command): (1) Open the window. In this talk I argue that Imperatives involve an existential modal. The universal reading is explained on the basis of two factors; i) lack of a scalar counterpart as opposed to overt modals ii) strengthening via an Implicature derived in the presence of certain Focus Alternatives (cf. Schwager 2005). First, I present an analysis of Imperatives as existential modals; Evidence for such an analysis comes from scopal ambiguities with only. Then, I provide an analysis for the emergrence of the must-reading. Finally, I draw a parallel with other covert modals which also seem to be ambiguous between an existential and a universal reading and I suggest that the present analysis can be extended in these environments as well. Imperatives as Existential modals In line with Han (2000), Schwager (2012), Condoravdi & Lauer (2012) and differently from Portner (2007) I assume that Imperatives involve a covert modal operator (Imp). However, I deviate from these analyses in treating Imp as an existential modal (see Schwager 2005) whose meaning can be formalized as in (2) following a Kratzerian analysis of modals as outlined in von Fintel & Heim (2011). (2) w, g = λr D,. λq D. w W [R imp (w)(w ) = 1 & q(w ) = 1, where w is the actual world and g is an assignment supplied by the context such that g(r imp ) = λw. λw. the s wishes/desires/moral beliefs in w with respect to the s actions are satisfied in w. The modal base is given by the context and it represents the set of the worlds which are compatible with the wishes/desires/moral beliefs of the Speaker in the actual world w regarding the actions of the Addressee in a possible world w. The performative character of Imperatives can be explained assuming that Imp has certain felicity conditions/presuppositions which force performativity (pace Kaufmann 2012, Condoravdi & Lauer 2012). Based on (2), we derive the meaning in (3) for the sentence in (1) that there is a world compatible with the s desires in which opens the window, which captures our intuition about the can-reading of the Imperative: (3) h w,g = = w W. the s desires in w are satisfied in w the opens the window in w Before considering the derivation of the must-reading, I present data from Greek suggesting that the Imp operator is existential. - 2 -

Evidence for the existential character of Imp Haida & Repp (2011) observe that an Imperative containing only (4) is ambiguous; in context A, we get the reading that should paint the round table but he is allowed to not paint the other tables whereas in context B, is allowed to paint the round table but he is not allowed to paint the other tables: Context A: You've asked me to paint those tables but I'm really tired and don't feel like doing something really useful today. (4) Only paint the round table. - 3 - Context B: Oh, I feel like doing something really useful today. I think I'll paint the tables over there. Building on H&R s example I show that the ambiguity of (4) is in fact scopal (footnote (1) in H&R 2011) and can be explained only if we treat Imp as an existential modal; in context A only is interpreted below Imp whereas in Context B above Imp. The scopal nature of the ambiguity becomes clear in Greek where there is overt focus movement which has been shown to resolve scope ambiguities in general. In (5a) the only-dp remains in situ and both readings are available. On the contrary, in (5b) where the only-dp undergoes focus movement only the reading that A is not allowed to paint the other tables survives: (5) a. Vapse [mono to strogilo trapezi]. Paint only the round table. > only / only > b. [mono to strogilo trapezi] vapse. Only the round table paint * > only / only > Only takes as its argument p; it presupposes that p and negates all non-weaker alternatives of p (Horn (1969). Following Rooth (1992), the alternatives of p are computed by substituting the focused constituent ROUND with the relevant alternatives (i.e. SQUARE/TRIANGLE): (6) Focus value of (4/5): 5, = { w W. s desires in w are satisfied in w paints the RND table in w w W. s desires in w are satisfied in w paints the } table in w Therefore when only takes scope below the existential modal (Context A) we get the meaning in (7a). When only takes scope above the existential modal (Context B) we get (7b): (7) a. w W. the s desires in w are satisfied in w [ paints the SQR/TRG table in w ]. b. w W. the s desires in w are satisfied in w paints the SQR/TRG table in w. In (5b) the only-dp cannot reconstruct after overt focus movement, therefore the meaning in (7a) becomes inaccessible. Crucially, treating Imp as a universal modal (Kaufmann 2012) derives the wrong reading for (5b); the interpretation we would get is that is not required to paint the other tables whereas the intended interpretation would be that is required not to paint the other tables. In Portner s (2007) analysis of Imperatives in which there is no modal operator in semantics we should make some additional assumption regarding the scope of only (i.e. scoping over or below speech acts). Here I focus on showing that under an existential analysis of imperatives the must-reading can be derived by mechanisms that are independently motivated. G

Deriving the must-reading I argue that the must-reading is possible because there is no stronger scalar counterpart to Imp. An overt existential modal like can has a stronger scalar counterpart must. Following Magri (2011), I take the scalar Implicature in (8) to be blind to the context and therefore obligatory: (8) You can open the window. It s not the case that you must open the window. On the contrary, I argue that there is no counterpart to the covert existential operator in Imperatives and therefore no scalar implicature is derived. This allows Imp to be interpreted as universal (similarly to what is argued in Deal 2011 for the modal suffix in Nez Perce). Now the question is what forces a universal interpretation of Imp in the command-reading. Building on Kaufmann s idea of Imperatives as Exhaustive Possibilities in Schwager (2005), I suggest that the must-reading is the result of an implicature derived when the complement p of Imp is broadly focused. Following Rooth (1992) the alternatives of p can be any proposition of type <st>. When an Imperative is uttered in an out-of-the-blue context I take the only contextually salient proposition to be p, thus deriving the alternatives in (9) for the sentence in (1): (9) 1, ={ w W. s desires in w are satisfied in w opens the window in w. w W. s desires in w are satisfied in w [ opens the window in w ] } The Focus Alternatives are then evaluated by an EXH operator (10) (Chierchia, Fox & Spector 2012) and all non-weaker alternatives are negated, thus deriving the Implicature in (11): (10) EXH AL S w = 1 iff S w = 1 and φ ALT φ w = 1 S φ (11) w W. the s desires in w are satisfied in w & [the opens the window in w ] By exhaustifying the alternatives we get the interpretation that there is no world that is compatible with s desires in which does not open the window. This is equivalent to saying that the must open the window, thus capturing our intuition about the must-reading of (1) in the professor context. Under this analysis it is expected that an Imperative which occurs in an out-of-the-blue context is interpreted as a command; the relevant alternatives to [Imp p] will be of the form [Imp p], therefore deriving the implicature that [Imp p]. Moreover, we expect when that under a marked prosodic pattern, we will get a non-command/request reading. Indeed preliminary results from a prosodic study of Imperatives shows that permissions are realized with focus on the verb followed by deaccenting whereas narrow-focus imperatives pattern both with commands and permissions depending on the context. Beyond Imperatives The ambiguity between a universal and an existential interpretation is also present in other environments of covert modality (i.e. matrix subjunctives, wh-infinitival questions - Bhatt 2002, dispositional middles - Condoravdi 1989, Lekakou 2002). I suggest that these covert modals can be analyzed as existential and that the universal reading can be accounted for in a similar way as in Imperatives, providing a way to unify different patterns of covert modality as being existential. The question which arises is whether there is an explanation - 4 -

for the existential character of Imperatives and other covert modals. I suggest to explore the idea that covert modals simply lack quantificational force and that existential force comes via Existential Closure. Selected References Condoravdi, C. & S. Lauer. 2012. Imperatives: Meaning and illocutionary force. Empirical Issues in Syntax and Semantics 9. Chierchia, G., F. Danny & B.Spector. 2012. Scalar implicature as a grammatical phenomenon. In Semantics: An International Handbook of Natural Language Meaning, ed. Claudia Maienborn, Klaus von Heusinger, and Paul Portner, volume 3, 2297 2332. Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter Deal, A.R. 2011. Modals without scales. Language 87(3) on Fintel, K. & S. Iatridou. A modest proposal for the meaning of imperatives. To appear in Modality Across Categories, Oxford University Press Haida, A.& S. Repp. 2012. 'Only' in imperatives. Proceedings of Sinn und Bedeutung 16. MITWPL. Kaufmann, M. 2012. Interpreting Imperatives. Springer. Portner, P. 2007. Imperatives and Modals. NLS 15 Rooth, M. 1992. A theory of focus interpretation. NLS 1. Schwager, M. 2005. Exhaustive Imperatives. Proceedings of the 15th Amsterdam Colloquium. Wilson, D. & D. Sperber. 1988. Mood and the analysis of non-declarative sentences. In Jonathan Dancy, J.M.E. Moravcsik & C.C.W. Taylor (eds.), Human agency: Language, duty and value: Philosophical essays in honor of J.O. Urmson, 77 101. Stanford University Press. - 5 -