Contexts of Nature I. and Descartes

Similar documents
1. What is Phenomenology?

Phenomenology Glossary

Conclusion. One way of characterizing the project Kant undertakes in the Critique of Pure Reason is by


THE ECOLOGICAL MEANING OF EMBODIMENT

Conception of nature as foundation of a non-fundamental ontology Merleau-Ponty between the Nature lectures and The Visible and the Invisible

Necessity in Kant; Subjective and Objective

REVIEW ARTICLE IDEAL EMBODIMENT: KANT S THEORY OF SENSIBILITY

Kant: Notes on the Critique of Judgment

Cultural Specification and Temporalization An exposition of two basic problems regarding the development of ontologies in computer science

Habit, Semeiotic Naturalism, and Unity among the Sciences Aaron Wilson

Truth and Method in Unification Thought: A Preparatory Analysis

Are There Two Theories of Goodness in the Republic? A Response to Santas. Rachel Singpurwalla

Verity Harte Plato on Parts and Wholes Clarendon Press, Oxford 2002

Goldie on the Virtues of Art

INFLUENCE OF MUSICAL CONTEXT ON THE PERCEPTION OF EMOTIONAL EXPRESSION OF MUSIC

Natika Newton, Foundations of Understanding. (John Benjamins, 1996). 210 pages, $34.95.

What do our appreciation of tonal music and tea roses, our acquisition of the concepts

Tishreen University Journal for Research and Scientific Studies - Arts and Humanities Series Vol. (31) No. (1) 2009.

The Human Intellect: Aristotle s Conception of Νοῦς in his De Anima. Caleb Cohoe

Architecture is epistemologically

A Confusion of the term Subjectivity in the philosophy of Mind *

WHITEHEAD'S PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE AND METAPHYSICS

Steven E. Kaufman * Key Words: existential mechanics, reality, experience, relation of existence, structure of reality. Overview

KINDS (NATURAL KINDS VS. HUMAN KINDS)

1/8. The Third Paralogism and the Transcendental Unity of Apperception

NOTES ON COLLINGWOOD S PRINCIPLES OF ART

Book Reviews Department of Philosophy and Religion Appalachian State University 401 Academy Street Boone, NC USA

The Spell of the Sensuous Chapter Summaries 1-4 Breakthrough Intensive 2016/2017

Ontological and historical responsibility. The condition of possibility

The Observer Story: Heinz von Foerster s Heritage. Siegfried J. Schmidt 1. Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2011

Research Projects on Rudolf Steiner'sWorldview

The Aesthetic Idea and the Unity of Cognitive Faculties in Kant's Aesthetics

Jacek Surzyn University of Silesia Kant s Political Philosophy

The phenomenological tradition conceptualizes

Introduction SABINE FLACH, DANIEL MARGULIES, AND JAN SÖFFNER

SocioBrains THE INTEGRATED APPROACH TO THE STUDY OF ART

Philosophical Background to 19 th Century Modernism

Martin, Gottfried: Plato s doctrine of ideas [Platons Ideenlehre]. Berlin: Verlag Walter de Gruyter, 1973

1/9. Descartes on Simple Ideas (2)

The Senses at first let in particular Ideas. (Essay Concerning Human Understanding I.II.15)

Chapter 3. Phenomenological Concept of Lived Body

PHL 317K 1 Fall 2017 Overview of Weeks 1 5

Heideggerian Ontology: A Philosophic Base for Arts and Humanties Education

(Ulrich Schloesser/ Humboldt-Universität zu Berlin)

Prephilosophical Notions of Thinking

Caught in the Middle. Philosophy of Science Between the Historical Turn and Formal Philosophy as Illustrated by the Program of Kuhn Sneedified

By Tetsushi Hirano. PHENOMENOLOGY at the University College of Dublin on June 21 st 2013)

HERMENEUTIC PHILOSOPHY AND DATA COLLECTION: A PRACTICAL FRAMEWORK

Ontological Categories. Roberto Poli

observation and conceptual interpretation

Aristotle. Aristotle. Aristotle and Plato. Background. Aristotle and Plato. Aristotle and Plato

PHD THESIS SUMMARY: Phenomenology and economics PETR ŠPECIÁN

Kant IV The Analogies The Schematism updated: 2/2/12. Reading: 78-88, In General

It is from this perspective that Aristotelian science studies the distinctive aspects of the various inhabitants of the observable,

The Doctrine of the Mean

Aristotle (summary of main points from Guthrie)

Immanuel Kant Critique of Pure Reason

What is the Object of Thinking Differently?

TEST BANK. Chapter 1 Historical Studies: Some Issues

1/10. Berkeley on Abstraction

Intersubjectivity and Language

The Mind's Movement: An Essay on Expression

Pierre Hadot on Philosophy as a Way of Life. Pierre Hadot ( ) was a French philosopher and historian of ancient philosophy,

MAURICE MANDELBAUM HISTORY, MAN, & REASON A STUDY IN NINETEENTH-CENTURY THOUGHT THE JOHNS HOPKINS PRESS: BALTIMORE AND LONDON


The Baroque Formulation of Consciousness Bridging the Unbridgeable Gap through Indicational Representation

The Influence of Chinese and Western Culture on English-Chinese Translation

Scientific Philosophy

PHILOSOPHY PLATO ( BC) VVR CHAPTER: 1 PLATO ( BC) PHILOSOPHY by Dr. Ambuj Srivastava / (1)

Perceptions and Hallucinations

1/6. The Anticipations of Perception

THE SOCIAL RELEVANCE OF PHILOSOPHY

Scientific Revolutions as Events: A Kuhnian Critique of Badiou

The Concept of Nature

Intelligible Matter in Aristotle, Aquinas, and Lonergan. by Br. Dunstan Robidoux OSB

KANTIAN CONCEPTUALISM

«Only the revival of Kant's transcendentalism can be an [possible] outlet for contemporary philosophy»

Imagination Becomes an Organ of Perception


COMPUTER ENGINEERING SERIES

The Polish Peasant in Europe and America. W. I. Thomas and Florian Znaniecki

Forms and Causality in the Phaedo. Michael Wiitala

Incommensurability and Partial Reference

Aristotle's Stoichiology: its rejection and revivals

Brandom s Reconstructive Rationality. Some Pragmatist Themes

AESTHETICS. PPROCEEDINGS OF THE 8th INTERNATIONAL WITTGENSTEIN SYMPOSIUM PART l. 15th TO 21st AUGUST 1983 KIRCHBERG AM WECHSEL (AUSTRIA) EDITOR

Keywords: semiotic; pragmatism; space; embodiment; habit, social practice.

Review of Krzysztof Brzechczyn, Idealization XIII: Modeling in History

Action Theory for Creativity and Process

Chapter 2: The Early Greek Philosophers MULTIPLE CHOICE

CHAPTER IV RETROSPECT

Hans-Georg Gadamer, Truth and Method, 2d ed. transl. by Joel Weinsheimer and Donald G. Marshall (London : Sheed & Ward, 1989), pp [1960].

6. The Cogito. Procedural Work and Assessment The Cartesian Background Merleau-Ponty: the tacit cogito

What is (an) emotion?

Doctoral Thesis in Ancient Philosophy. The Problem of Categories: Plotinus as Synthesis of Plato and Aristotle

Image and Imagination

In Search of the Totality of Experience

Philosophy 405: Knowledge, Truth and Mathematics Spring Russell Marcus Hamilton College

Kant Prolegomena to any Future Metaphysics, Preface, excerpts 1 Critique of Pure Reason, excerpts 2 PHIL101 Prof. Oakes updated: 9/19/13 12:13 PM

Transcription:

Contexts of Nature I Froin the point of view of the history and philosophy ofscience. the relationship of Descartes' Co Aristotle's concept of according t0 Aristotle nature has not been grasped in an entirely salisiactory way. In this article, the two concepts will be subjected to a and Descartes comparative analysls. beginning with the outstanding feature that both concepts of nature are characterized by a contradistinction to the non-natural: Gregor Schiemann Aristotle separates nature and technology: Descartes opposes nature to thlnking. My thesis is that these meanings have found privileged application in specific contexts of experience: the field of appllcation especially suitable for the Aristotelian concept 1s the experience of everyday life. while for the Cartesian concept it is subjective experience. Historically. the relationship between nieaning and experience is of help in understanding the conditions in which the two concepts aiose. The topical relevante of the concepts to modern society is a consequence of the continued exlstence of the favored contexts of experience. Roughly stated, we sometiines still perceive in an Aristotelian way and at other times think in a Cartesian way. The replacement of the Aristotelian concept of nature by the Cartesian one is a characteristic feature of modern science. Until the end of the Middle Ages the Aristotelian concept of nature was a guiding idea of scholastic philosophy of nature. In the Course of the renaissance of Thomistic philosophy in the second half of the 16th century its infiuence increased considerably. Descartes then formulated a contrary position which represented the rationalist conception of modern science. From the point of view of the history and philosophy of science, the relationship of Descartes' concept of nature to Aristotle's has not been grasped in an entirely satisfactory way [cf. for the history of science Dennis Des Chene, Physiologia. Natural Philosophy in Late Aristotelian and Cartesian Thought (Ithacal London: Cornell University Press, 1996) and Marleen Rozemond, Descartes' Dualism (CarnbridgeILondon: Harvard University Press, 1998); for the philosophy of science Ansgar Beckermann, "Aristoteles, Descartes und die Beziehungen zwischen Philoso-phischer Psychologie und Künstlicher Intelligenz-Forschung", in Ernst Pöppel (ed.). Gehirn und BewuJtsein [Weinheim: VCH, 19891. One of the things that have not been settled is the scope of Descartes' break with basic Aristotelian views, and the extent to which he relied on or adopted them. Neither has it been satisfactorily explained why the two concepts still enjoy such currency today.

Contexts of Nature according to Aristotle and Descartes In this article, the two concepts will be subjected to a comparative analysis. beginning with the outstanding feature that both concepts of nature are characterized by a contradistinction to the non-natural: Aristotle separates nature and technology; Descartes opposes nature to thinking. In forming a contrast, the concepts divide a large portion of reality into a natural and a non-natural part. My thesis is that these meanings have found privileged application in specific contexts of experience: the field of application especially suitable for the Aristotelian concept is experience of everyday life. while for the Cartesian concept it is subjective experience. Historically, the relationship between meaning and experience is of help in understanding the conditions in which the two concepts arose. The topical relevance of the concepts to modern society is a consequence of the continued existence of the favored contexts of experience. (I elaborate upon the connection between concepts of nature and experiences using the example of the applicability of Aristotle's and Descartes' concepts in Natur, Technik, Geist. Kontexte der Natur nach Aristoteles und Descartes in lebensweltlicher und subjektiver Erfahrung (BerlinINew York: Walter De Gruyter, 2005).) Aristotle's distinction between physis and techne Aristotle distinguishes between physis (nature) and techne (technologylart). For him, techne is not a subject for research in nature. Techne is "against nature" and allows for the mastery of nature (Pseudo-Aristotle, Mechanical Problems. 847a14 and 21f., in Aristotle, Minor Works, trans. W. S. Hett (Cambridge, MAILondon: Harvard University Press. 1936)). This separation corresponds to the fact that, in Aristotle, the study of nature depends above all on the observation of phenomena but not on technical means. The main criterion for applying Aristotle's distinction is the criterion of self-movement. The classical place for its definition is the second book of the Physics, where Aristotle admits only those things in nature which "have within themselves a principle of motion and of staying unchanged" (Aristotle, Physics 192b13f.). On the other hand, techne applies to those things which might exist on account of "other causes" (ibid., 192b8f.). The indefiniteness of the causal properties of non-natural things contrasts with the fured characteristics of the natural ones. Following Wolfgang Wieland (Die aristotelische Physik. (Göttingen: Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht, 1962)). I would like to interpret the singular in the definition of natural things as a minirnum condition: what has only one inner principle permanently in itself must be reckoned within the natural realm. The self-movement of natural things can be activated from the outside. The dependence of organic life on sunlight

Gregor Schiemann may be an example of this. Consequently. both a wild flower and a cultivated flower are natural plants. Aristotle's characterization of self-moving nature is based on a contradistinction to the productions of handicrafts. Man-made constructions have an inner principle only because they consist of self-moving elements. However, this self-movement is not the cause of the artificial form of crafted things. Artificial forms arise only because human beings have effects on natural substances. The unshaped material naturalness of crafted things is opposed to their artificial form. Nevertheless, this is not the only difference between natural and artificial forms. The technical, above all the product of handicraft, is also distinguished from plants and animals in terms of the forms of growth and lively movement. So the difference between having an inner principle and not having one is deeply related to the form that is essential to the specific thing. The distinction outlined so far is still very incomplete. Many irnportant questions, such as the poietic and teleological structure of nature, are not even mentioned. My reconstruction of the Aristotelian concept assumes that these aspects are only to a certain extent implied in the criteria for the difference of nature and technology. This rudimentary characterization of the Aristotelian distinction is neverlheless sufficient for preliminary comparison with the Cartesian concept. Descartes' dualism between res extensa and res cogitans Descartes' concept of nature can be understood as a counterproposition to the Aristotelian one. Descartes revokes the classical opposition of physis and techne by assuming, instead, a dualism between res extensa (nature) and res cogitans (thinking). The earth is now subordinated to this dualism. As the criterion for distinguishing between the two spheres, Descartes introduces the clear and distinct recognition of res extensa in its difference from res cogitans (Descartes. Meditationes de prima philosophia, Meditation VI, paragraph 9. in CEuures de Descartes, ed. Charles Adam and Paul Tannery (Paris: J. VrinICNRS, 1964-7 1). vol. VII, p. 78). Remarkably, for Descartes res cogitans has neither extension nor place. By contrast, all other things are in a spatial relationship and subsist in nothing else than in their extension. All the qualities which we observe in natural things - their hardness, their colors and so forth - have their origin in differences of shape. Descartes turns the relationship between Aristotelian physis and techne almost upside down. Techne [technology) is not merely a part of nature: rather, it is that part which is best suited for the exploration

Contexts of Nature according to Aristotle and DescarCes of nature (Descartes. Principia Philosophiae, Book IV, article 203, in CEuures, vol. VIII- 1). This additional feature results from the mathematical character of res extensa. In Aristotle the living represent the paradigm of natural investigation. Now artificial devices take their place. This reversal of techne is the most important consequence of the Cartesian concept of nature. Res cogitans has priority over res extensa insofar as it is the origin of knowledge about the principles of natural science. The extended is not able to recognize itself. The basis for this lies in the circumstance that extension is a category to which nothing corresponds in perception - as Descartes remarks in the Meditationes (Descartes, Meditationes, Meditation 11, paragraph 12, in CEuures. vol. VII, p. 31). Only by thinking do we realize the essence of extension. We can acquire this knowledge most distinctly without receiving any information from the outside world, if we withdraw into isolation and reflect on our own thinking. Comparison of the two definitions The concept of thinking characterizes the position of the subject in modern rationalism. In Aristotle we find no related definition. Nevertheless. the extensions of the two concepts of nature can be compared as lists. Both concepts share the extraterrestrial viewpoint, from which they count the following as belonging to nature: corporal substances, their combinations, the stars and planets. the plants and the animals as well as human beings in all the qualities they share with animals. Differences occur in the assignment of human beings and artificial objects to a list. Aristotle conceives of human beings essentially as natural beings who create non-natural artificial objects. Descartes splits the essence of the human being into a non-natural and a natural part and adds artificial objects to the natural. Now thinking is the non-natural, which has the ability to create artificial objects that count as natural. The definitions are related positively only to nature and not to the part of reality which is separated from it: self-movement in Aristotle and extension in Descartes. They are necessary and sufficient conditions for assigning an object to nature. But only Aristotle ascribes to nature both its features and the knowledge of those features. Descartes, on the other hand, strictly distinguishes between the two: the ability to recognize extension as the essence of nature is the ability of non-natural thinking. I would like to note that both authors maintain more than one concept of nature. Different meanings of the term "nature" are present in their works. The concepts I refer to here indeed play a central role in the

Gregor Schiemann natural philosophy of the two authors, but they make up only a lirnited part of the meaning of the whole concept of nature. After having presented a minimal reconstruction of the main distinctions between nature and non-nature, I would like to discuss the privileged contexts of experience to which the two distinctions are related. By "experience" I mean not so much the cultural contexts of the origin of the distinction, but rather the conditions of their plausibility over a long historical period - that is, the processes of gaining knowledge and the forms of the secure possession of ordered content. 1s it possible to find types of experience that are as distinct from each other as these two concepts of nature? What sort of empirical knowledge is necessary to identify the criteria of the natural, as suggested by Aristotle and Descartes? Experience of everyday life as the context for the Aristotelian distinction As Descartes himself notes, Aristotle's concept of nature is mainly concerned with everyday experience (Descartes. CEuvres, vol. 111. pp. 420 and 692; vol. VI, p. 13; vol. VIII-1, p. 351. Descartes distinguishes this experience from scientific experience. which mainly consists in determining the movements of particles so small as to be invisible. Compared with this, the objects of everyday experience have the characteristic feature of perceptibility. Indeed Aristotle clarifies his distinction by means of illustrative examples. Primarily. perceptible living beings and materials which underlie technology are a part of nature. The essential meaning of his concept of techne arises mainly from man-made products (e.g. beds. clothing or houses), from their fabrication and their use in human life. Obviously the natural and the artificial are distinguished from each other by differences in their manner of movement and their outer form. Adopting a distinction that is social-phenomenological and idealtypical. I conceive of everyday life. to which Aristotle's nature concept is properly applicable, as a limited realm of experience of direct perception. In everyday life. awareness is focused on dealing practically with familiar things and persons as they are outwardly perceptible. Everyday-life experience can be defined by reference to a catalogue of criteria that are necessary and jointly sufficient. These include (a normal adult's) attention focused in perception. an unprofessional manner of action and an integrally structured background knowledge (cf. Edmund Husserl, Die Krisis der europäischen Wissenschaften und die transzendentale Phänomenologie (Den Haag: Nijhoff, 1976); Alfred

Contexls of Nature according to Aristotle and Descartes Schütz and Thomas Luckmann, The Structures of the LiJeworld (Evanston, IL: Heinemann. 197311. As Stephen Toulmin put it, the essential features of the Aristotelian concept of nature may be understood as the "generaiization of everydaylife experience" (Voraussicht und Verstehen (Frankfurt a.m.: Suhrkamp, 1981). p. 62). Subjectivity as the context for the Cartesian Dualism By contrast, the privileged context of experience for Descartes' concept of nature is one's own inner self experience. From the point of view of cultural history, this approach reflects the initial release of the individual from preordained frames of reference. The individual turns away from everyday life toward her or his inner world, which is present only mentally. The inner world is the domain of more or less conscious thoughts, sensations, feelings and moods - a field of experience in which the bodily, the mental. and their combinations occur. I call this context of experience "subjectivity" and define it by the criterion that only the Person concerned can have privileged access to it (cf. e.g. William Alston, "Varieties of Privileged Access", in American Philosophical Quarterly 8 (1971) 223-241 ). It is very typical that for the purpose of investigating this subjective experience. Descartes not only turns away from the everyday-life world but also from all practical matters. I would like to argue that Descartes does not contrast the whole of subjective experience with nature. Only clear and distinct conceptuai thinking, which refers to something else or reflexively to itself, is unreservedly non-natural. By contrast, one's consciously experienced perceptions and sensations and some of one's feelings and moods form, in Descartes, a mixture of nature and thinking. From the viewpoint of subjectivity pure nature appears to be above all an external object of perception. Cartesian Dualism divides the human being into two parts. One part consists mainly in physiological processes. Insofar as they are independent of thinking they do not differ from the mechanics of the life processes of animals. On the one hand, thinking can produce deiiberate actions and act on the body (via the pineal gland). Hence the world of nature does not form a closed system, but is Open to mental influences. On the other hand, human nature affects thinking (e.g. feelings of hunger and thirst, emotions of rage, joy or sadness). I contend that Descartes effects a partition which is formally the same as that of Aristotle: the corresponding contexts of experience are divided into a natural part, a non-natural part, and a part in which the division is not clear.

Conclusion Gregor Schiemann Let me summarize the two main differences found so far. Roughly speaking, the two different extensional definitions of nature follow from two different features of objects against specific experiential backgrounds. Perceptual experience, found in experience of everyday life, is a favored condition for recognizing self-movement. In order to be classified. Aristotelian objects must be present and visible. For Descartes. by contrast, thinking defines nature as being extended in the context of subjective experience. One must turn away from every external perception in order to recognize Cartesian nature. These two contexts of experience are not entirely separate. But in spite of the relationships existing between them, the contrast between them is sufficiently clear. Normally neither context leaves room for the other, and thus we cannot normally participate in both ways of experiencing at once. In conclusion, let me make a comment on the contemporary applicability of both concepts of nature. It is still possible today to differentiate between the experience of everyday life and subjective experience. In my opinion, the two concepts of nature are still frequently used in those contexts. Of course, in a growing number of cases it is useless and often impossible to differentiate between technology and nature. But we are usualiy not indifferent to these cases in the perceptible world of everyday life, provided we take note of them. On the other hand, Cartesian dualism is of course almost completely out of fashion. Nevertheless, it is possible to distinguish between the thinking mind and the extended body without sharing the presuppositions of the Cartesian ontological system. The Cartesian problem of the relation of mind and body is not so much ridiculous as unresolved. To put it crudely, we sometimes still perceive in an Aristotelian way and at other times think in a Cartesian way. Were this not so, it might be impossible for us to acquire even a rudimentary understanding of the two authors' historical texts. Conversely. a closer look at the writings of these authors can still improve our understanding of our own concepts of nature. Address: Prof. Dr. Greyor Schiemann, Philosophisches SeminarlFB A, Bergische Universität Wuppertal. GaiiJstr. 20. 0-421 19 Wuppertal, Germany. E-mail: gregor.schiemannfuuni-tiiebingen.de: wehsite: www.iini-tuebingen.deluni/ f07/schiemannl.

THE PROCEEDINGS OF THE TWENTY-FIRST WORLD CONGRESS OF PHILOSOPHY VOLUME 5 Logic and Philosophy of the Sciences EDITORS Stephen Voss, Berna Kzlznq, and Gürol Imzk Bogazi~i University, lstanbul Philosophical Society of Turkey Ankara 2007