Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at

Similar documents
What counts as a convincing scientific argument? Are the standards for such evaluation

The topic of this Majors Seminar is Relativism how to formulate it, and how to evaluate arguments for and against it.

INTRODUCTION TO NONREPRESENTATION, THOMAS KUHN, AND LARRY LAUDAN

Hypatia, Volume 21, Number 3, Summer 2006, pp (Review) DOI: /hyp For additional information about this article

Interpretive and Critical Research Traditions

Truth and Method in Unification Thought: A Preparatory Analysis

Mind Association. Oxford University Press and Mind Association are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Mind.

Sidestepping the holes of holism

A Letter from Louis Althusser on Gramsci s Thought

GV958: Theory and Explanation in Political Science, Part I: Philosophy of Science (Han Dorussen)

THE RELATIONS BETWEEN ETHICS AND ECONOMICS: A COMPARATIVE ANALYSIS BETWEEN AYRES AND WEBER S PERSPECTIVES. By Nuria Toledano and Crispen Karanda

Simulated killing. Michael Lacewing

Objectivity and Diversity: Another Logic of Scientific Research Sandra Harding University of Chicago Press, pp.

What Can Experimental Philosophy Do? David Chalmers

Philip Kitcher and Gillian Barker, Philosophy of Science: A New Introduction, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2014, pp. 192

Kęstas Kirtiklis Vilnius University Not by Communication Alone: The Importance of Epistemology in the Field of Communication Theory.

COURSE SYLLABUS. 1. Information about the programme

Any attempt to revitalize the relationship between rhetoric and ethics is challenged

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at

Normative and Positive Economics

These are some notes to give you some idea of the content of the lecture they are not exhaustive, nor always accurate! So read the referenced work.

CRITICAL CONTEXTUAL EMPIRICISM AND ITS IMPLICATIONS

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at

Caught in the Middle. Philosophy of Science Between the Historical Turn and Formal Philosophy as Illustrated by the Program of Kuhn Sneedified

Kant, Peirce, Dewey: on the Supremacy of Practice over Theory

Lecture 3 Kuhn s Methodology

PHILOSOPHY OF SOCIAL SCIENCE INTS 4522 Spring Jack Donnelly and Martin Rhodes -

Scientific Philosophy

Practical Intuition and Rhetorical Example. Paul Schollmeier

Quine s Two Dogmas of Empiricism. By Spencer Livingstone

Brandom s Reconstructive Rationality. Some Pragmatist Themes

Ithaque : Revue de philosophie de l'université de Montréal

Action, Criticism & Theory for Music Education

Mixed Methods: In Search of a Paradigm

Aristotle on the Human Good

The Epistemological Status of Theoretical Simplicity YINETH SANCHEZ

By Rahel Jaeggi Suhrkamp, 2014, pbk 20, ISBN , 451pp. by Hans Arentshorst

Kuhn and coherentist epistemology

Hoyningen Symposium Systematicity: The Nature of Science

Communication Studies Publication details, including instructions for authors and subscription information:

Action, Criticism & Theory for Music Education

Seven remarks on artistic research. Per Zetterfalk Moving Image Production, Högskolan Dalarna, Falun, Sweden

Public Administration Review Information for Contributors

Arnold I. Davidson, Frédéric Gros (eds.), Foucault, Wittgenstein: de possibles rencontres (Éditions Kimé, 2011), ISBN:

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

Kent Academic Repository

Social Mechanisms and Scientific Realism: Discussion of Mechanistic Explanation in Social Contexts Daniel Little, University of Michigan-Dearborn

ALIGNING WITH THE GOOD

Society for the Study of Symbolic Interaction SSSI/ASA 2002 Conference, Chicago

The Beauty of Understanding: Aesthetic Methods of Theory Evaluation

On Meaning. language to establish several definitions. We then examine the theories of meaning

3. The knower s perspective is essential in the pursuit of knowledge. To what extent do you agree?


DOES THEOLOGY NEED A PARADIGM? LEARNING FROM ORGANIZATION SCIENCE AND MANAGEMENT RESEARCH

Mitchell ABOULAFIA, Transcendence. On selfdetermination

The Observer Story: Heinz von Foerster s Heritage. Siegfried J. Schmidt 1. Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2011

Challenging the View That Science is Value Free

Department of Philosophy Florida State University

Edward Winters. Aesthetics and Architecture. London: Continuum, 2007, 179 pp. ISBN

Qualitative Design and Measurement Objectives 1. Describe five approaches to questions posed in qualitative research 2. Describe the relationship betw

PHIL/HPS Philosophy of Science Fall 2014

Are There Two Theories of Goodness in the Republic? A Response to Santas. Rachel Singpurwalla

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at

Culture, Space and Time A Comparative Theory of Culture. Take-Aways

TROUBLING QUALITATIVE INQUIRY: ACCOUNTS AS DATA, AND AS PRODUCTS

UNIT SPECIFICATION FOR EXCHANGE AND STUDY ABROAD

Course Description: looks into the from a range dedicated too. Course Goals: Requirements: each), a 6-8. page writing. assignment. grade.

Theories and Activities of Conceptual Artists: An Aesthetic Inquiry

Visual Argumentation in Commercials: the Tulip Test 1

บทปร ท ศน หน งส อ The Three Cultures: Natural Sciences, Social Sciences, and the Humanities in the 21 st Century

Author Directions: Navigating your success from PhD to Book

HISTORY ADMISSIONS TEST. Marking Scheme for the 2015 paper

George Levine, Darwin the Writer, Oxford University Press, Oxford 2011, 272 pp.

Guidelines for Seminar Papers and BA/MA Theses

In Search of Mechanisms, by Carl F. Craver and Lindley Darden, 2013, The University of Chicago Press.

Ashraf M. Salama. Functionalism Revisited: Architectural Theories and Practice and the Behavioral Sciences. Jon Lang and Walter Moleski

REFERENCES. 2004), that much of the recent literature in institutional theory adopts a realist position, pos-

Published in: International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 29(2) (2015):

MODULE 4. Is Philosophy Research? Music Education Philosophy Journals and Symposia

SUMMARY BOETHIUS AND THE PROBLEM OF UNIVERSALS

PAUL REDDING S CONTINENTAL IDEALISM (AND DELEUZE S CONTINUATION OF THE IDEALIST TRADITION) Sean Bowden

GUIDE TO WRITING SCIENTIFIC PAPERS (BACHELOR- AND MASTER THESES, SEMINAR PAPERS)

A Handbook for Action Research in Health and Social Care

that would join theoretical philosophy (metaphysics) and practical philosophy (ethics)?

Creative Actualization: A Meliorist Theory of Values

Bas C. van Fraassen, Scientific Representation: Paradoxes of Perspective, Oxford University Press, 2008.

GUIDELINES FOR THE PREPARATION OF A GRADUATE THESIS. Master of Science Program. (Updated March 2018)

Penultimate draft of a review which will appear in History and Philosophy of. $ ISBN: (hardback); ISBN:

Phenomenology and Non-Conceptual Content

ENVIRONMENTAL EXPERIENCE: Beyond Aesthetic Subjectivism and Objectivism

Logic and Philosophy of Science (LPS)

University of Huddersfield Repository

observation and conceptual interpretation

uniformity and individual uniqueness

INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY AND HEGELIAN JUSTIFICATION

Normal Science and Normal Kuhn.

PHI 3240: Philosophy of Art

KINDS (NATURAL KINDS VS. HUMAN KINDS)

Conceptual Change, Relativism, and Rationality

Texas Southern University. From the SelectedWorks of Anthony M Rodriguez Ph.D. Michael A Rodriguez, Ph.D., Texas Southern University

Transcription:

Response: Divergent Stakeholder Theory Author(s): R. Edward Freeman Source: The Academy of Management Review, Vol. 24, No. 2 (Apr., 1999), pp. 233-236 Published by: Academy of Management Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/259078 Accessed: 11-09-2017 11:43 UTC REFERENCES Linked references are available on JSTOR for this article: http://www.jstor.org/stable/259078?seq=1&cid=pdf-reference#references_tab_contents You may need to log in to JSTOR to access the linked references. JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org. Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at http://about.jstor.org/terms Academy of Management is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to The Academy of Management Review

? Academy of Management Review 1999, Vol. 24, No. 2, 233-236. RESPONSE DIVERGENT STAKEHOLDER THEORY R. EDWARD FREEMAN University of Virginia There is much that is useful in Jones and Wicks' proposal for a "convergent stakeholder theory." First of all, they detail a wide spectrum of agreement by those who are stakeholder theorists. Second, they rightly emphasize so-called instrumental stakeholder theory as the most promising candidate for theoretical development. Finally, they link stakeholder theory to broader areas of management scholarship. Using convergent stakeholder theory as a grand concept for integrating the many strands of stakeholder thinking is a natural idea given the current state-of-the-art of management theory and its penchant for consensus and agreement, and given the usually divergent poles of positivism and relativism (Wicks & Freeman, 1998). Nonetheless, I argue that their attempt at grand theorizing goes awry on two separate grounds. Their analysis is built on the following two propositions: 1. The Donaldson-Preston typology of "normative-instrumental-descriptive" stakeholder theories is useful. 2. The linkage between instrumental theory and ethics consists of the nature of the means and ends that are linked together. I suggest that each of these claims is at best dubious and that, together, they lead "theorists" such as Jones and Wicks in precisely the wrong direction. Furthermore, what we need is not more theory that converges but more narratives that are divergent-that show us different but useful ways to understand organizations in stakeholder terms. PROPOSITION 1: THE DONALDSON-PRESTON TYPOLOGY Jones and Wicks claim that Donaldson and Preston (1995) have provided "considerable coherence to the stakeholder concept as theory" (p. 206) by dividing it into descriptive, instrumental, and normative parts. This idea is rooted in a centuries-old philosophy of science, in which descriptive theory tells us the way that the world really is (in some sense of "really is"), normative theory prescribes how the world should be, and instrumental theory links means and ends. Donaldson and Preston argue that stakeholder theory would be more precise, more formal, or more scientific if we distinguished these three senses. Descriptive stakeholder theory would describe how organizations manage or interact with stakeholders, normative stakeholder theory would prescribe how organizations ought to treat their stakeholders, and instrumental theory would include such statements as "If you want to maximize shareholder value, you should pay attention to key stakeholders." Jones and Wicks actually note that the idea that there is a value-free science, much less a value-free social science, is a holdover from the days of positivism and the philosophical view that language can represent the world as it "really is." Likewise, the existence of a "normative world" in isolation from actual human values and conventions is a fiction that has long outlived its usefulness. Wicks himself (Wicks & Freeman, 1998) argues that such a positivism contrasted with relativism needs to be replaced by modern pragmatism. Nonetheless, Jones and Wicks seem to countenance the Donaldson-Preston typology as useful. It is worth pointing out that many ethical theorists indeed do accept this distinction, but they rarely address the underlying philosophical views about the language on which the distinction rests. Philosophers, not necessarily known as ethical theorists, such as Quine (1953), Goodman (1955), White (1956), Rudner (1966), Kuhn (1970), Feyerabend (1975), Rorty (1989), and a host of others, have argued for the better part of four decades that there is no way to have a 233

234 Academy of Management Review April meaningful distinction between normative and descriptive without relying on the distinction itself. In her recent analysis, Catherine Elgin (1998) traces the attempts to uphold these philosophical dualisms post Quine and Goodman and relies on a reinterpretation of Rawls (1971, 1993). I have suggested (Freeman, 1994) that relying heavily on the fact-value-or descriptivenormative-distinction is a form of the separation thesis: the view that it is meaningful to separate the discourse of business from the discourse of ethics. Now, if we drop the tripartite typology of Donaldson and Preston, then plainly there is no need for anything like convergent stakeholder theory. There is nothing to converge-no separate contributions for philosophers and management theorists. There are just narratives about stakeholders and narratives about these narratives-that is, theory. The overwhelming logic to drop this distinction is pretty simple. By choosing to call groups "stakeholders," rather than "interest groups," "constituencies," or "publics," we have already mixed up "fact" and "value." Stakeholder is an obvious literary device meant to call into question the emphasis on "stockholders." The very idea of a purely descriptive, value-free, or valueneutral stakeholder theory is a contradiction in terms. Why, then, should Jones and Wicks claim that the Donaldson-Preston tripartite typology is useful, when plainly it relies on an outmoded, nonpragmatist method (Wicks & Freeman, 1998) of understanding management theory? The answer is that instrumental theory is clearly extremely interesting. PROPOSITION 2: LINKING INSTRUMENTAL THEORY AND ETHICS Strategic Management: A Stakeholder Approach (Freeman, 1984) is built on instrumental premises. It suggests that if organizations want to be effective, they will pay attention to all and only those relationships that can affect or be affected by the achievement of the organization's purposes. That is, stakeholder management is fundamentally a pragmatic concept. Regardless of the content of the purpose of a firm, the effective firm will manage the relationships that are important. Later works (see Freeman & Gilbert, 1988, and Freeman, 1994) go on to suggest a typology of various "enterprise strategies" or "normative cores" that relate to the variety of purposes that business firms actually use. Contrary to Donaldson and Preston's analysis, and Jones and Wicks' seconding of that analysis, such normative cores are always dependent on the instrumentality built into the idea of stakeholder management. Although such an approach may seem trivial, it masks an important difference in the argument among social scientists and philosophers, who Jones and Wicks take to represent the two competing strands of stakeholder theory: the difference between deontologists and consequentialists in moral theory. Most philosophers are Kantians or deontologists who believe that the morality of an action is not solely a function of the consequences generated by that action. The rightness of an action may depend on the intent of the actor or the generalizability of the rule, principle, or maxim that led to the action. Certainly, philosophers like Donaldson (Donaldson, 1994), who see a separate normative realm, unrelated logically to the actual world we live in, believe that some actions may be wrong or right regardless of the resulting consequences. In contrast, consequentialists believe that what makes an action right or wrong depends on the consequences generated by that action. Utilitarianism is the most famous consequentialist theory, whereby an action is right if it generates, on balance, the best consequences for all. The debate between deontologists and consequentialists is long, historical, and tedious, and it depends on more philosophical dualisms that are not terribly useful. The point is that "moral" in the business ethics literature is often associated with "deontological," precisely because philosophers need a separate realm for their own analysis, much in the way that social scientists need a separate realm of facts to distinguish their own expertise. Instrumental theory lays claim to another space in the discourseone that mixes up both views and leaves no room for purely philosophical or purely scientific analysis. Jones and Wicks (and Jones, 1995) have articulated a version of stakeholder theory that is purely instrumental-that combines and jumbles up the normative and the empirical. They claim that "instrumental stakeholder theorists can explicitly embrace the addition of norma-

1999 Freeman 235 tive soundness to their theorizing without abandoning any of the criteria of 'good' theory in the organizational sciences" (p. 213). Instrumental theory, like any good narrative, depends on criteria such as usefulness, simplicity, and clarity in distinguishing "good" from "bad" theory. Yet, Jones and Wicks claim that instrumental theory of the form "if A then B" must accept only fully moral A's and B's. According to Jones and Wicks, the moral work of convergent stakeholder theory must be done from some independent moral realm to evaluate whether or not A is a good worth pursuing and whether B is a morally acceptable means. Otherwise, why would they claim that each theory in the class of convergent stakeholder theory would have a normative core, and "its normative foundation ('core') is explicitly and unabashedly moral and has to be explicitly defended in moral terms; instrumental means are not either (a) applied to immoral behavioral standards or (b) used to pursue immoral ends" (p. 215). Such a view defeats the purpose of instrumental stakeholder theory. Instrumental stakeholder theory is not value free precisely because it claims that consequences count. Because consequences count, statements of the form "if A then B" tell us how to produce certain kinds of consequences. By framing the discussion in terms of these consequences, one explicitly is making both a descriptive and normative statement at the same time. Consider the following theses: values and instrumental relationships. * The instrumental thesis of stakeholder theory: To maximize shareholder value over an Suppose we had 100 theories like the one uncertain time frame, managers ought to illustrated in the Jones and Wicks' Appendix. pay attention to key stakeholder relationshipstives, would be accounts of the role of such These theories, which I prefer to call narra- a The normative thesis of stakeholder theory: Managers ought to pay attention to key stakeholder relationships. The normative thesis needs more argument, and it is hard to see how such an argument can be connected to real firms and real stakeholders without some kind of instrumental claim. The instrumental thesis needs no more backup if you think that consequences count in general and that shareholder value consequences count in particular. We could have an argument about which consequences, but, ultimately, that argument would lead to a discussion of the nature of a business, how a business survives, the role of stakeholders in such an argument, and so on. In short, we would naturally embed the instrumental analysis in the real world. Instrumental theses need backup and justification, but not exclusively moral backup and justification, precisely because they are instrumental: only consequences count. Such a lesson is an important one for business ethicists, and they would do well to explore Jones and Wicks, whereas Jones and Wicks would do well to simply give up the vestigial limbs of the separation thesis. TOWARD A DIVERGENT STAKEHOLDER THEORY We need more instrumental theories-that is, we need more studies of the kinds of linkages postulated in the instrumental thesis-and fewer of the kind of studies that simply declare "managerial oughts" from general principles. Russell Hardin (1988) has argued persuasively that if we take bounded rationality and a thoroughgoing uncertainty about the world seriously enough, consequences may be all that our moral apparatus can handle. Jones and Wicks seem in sympathy with such a view, especially in their Appendix, where they give an example of a convergent stakeholder theory. It is clear that the instrumental relationship is doing the heavy lifting. "Firms whose managers... will achieve competitive advantage" is all that needs to be said if one adopts a capitalism that, like Adam Smith's, is built on concepts as trust, enactment, sustainability, hierarchy, and so on, and their instrumental relationships to organizational and stakeholder performance. There is no reason to suppose that these narratives would converge or that it would be good if they did. What we would have would be divergent accounts of organization and stakeholder relationshipshappily, for surely there is more than one way to be effective in stakeholder management. Surely there is more than one vision for creating value or for what consequences count as valuable. What we need is a conversation that encourages such divergent views, but one that quickly throws out those views that are not

236 Academy of Management Review April useful, not simple, and that do not show us how it is possible to live better. Toss out the Donaldson and Preston typology, and you do not need convergent stakeholder theory. Understand the central role of instrumental claims, and you do need a kind of philosophical pragmatism laid out by Wicks and Freeman (1998) that avoids the old distinctions between "true by definition" and "true by experience," between normative and descriptive, and between deontological and consequentialist. Instrumental stakeholder theory per Jones (1995) is here to stay-if we do not try to fit together narratives that are better understood when they are left alone. REFERENCES Donaldson, T. 1994. When integration fails. Business Ethics Quarterly, 2: 157-170. Donaldson, T., & Preston, L. 1995. The stakeholder theory of the modern corporation: Concepts, evidence, implications. Academy of Management Review, 20: 65-91. Elgin, C. Z. 1998. Reflective equilibrium. Boston: Harvard Feyerabend, P. 1975. Against method. New York: Shocken Books. Freeman, R. E. 1984. Strategic management: A stakeholder approach. Boston: Pitman Publishing. Freeman, R. E. 1994. The politics of stakeholder theory: Some future directions. Business Ethics Quarterly, 4: 409-422. Freeman, R. E., & Gilbert, D. R., Jr. 1988. Corporate strategy and the search for ethics. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice- Hall. Goodman, N. 1955. Fact, fiction and forecast. New York: Bobbs Merrill. Hardin, R. 1988. Morality within the limits of reason. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Jones, T. M. 1995. Instrumental stakeholder theory: A synthesis of ethics and economics. Academy of Management Review, 20: 404-437. Kuhn, T. 1970. The structure of scientific revolutions (2nd ed.). Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Quine, W. V. 1953. Two dogmas of empiricism. In From a logical point of view: 20-46. Cambridge, MA; Harvard Rawls, J. 1971. A theory of justice. Cambridge, MA: Harvard Rawls, J. 1993. Political liberalism. New York: Columbia University Press. Rorty, R. 1989. Contingency, irony, and solidarity. Cambridge, England: Cambridge Rudner, R. 1966. Philosophy of social science. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall. White, M. 1956. Toward reunion in philosophy. Cambridge, MA: Harvard Wicks, A. C., & Freeman, R. E. 1998. Organization studies and the new pragmatism: Positivism, anti-positivism, and the search for ethics. Organization Science, 9: 123-140. R. Edward Freeman is the Olsson Professor of Business Administration and the Director of The Olsson Center for Ethics, The Darden School, University of Virginia. He has a B.A. in mathematics and philosophy from Duke University and a Ph.D. in philosophy from Washington University.