Lorraine Daston, Max Planck Institute for the History of Science Berlin

Similar documents
Guide to the Republic as it sets up Plato s discussion of education in the Allegory of the Cave.

Plato s work in the philosophy of mathematics contains a variety of influential claims and arguments.

Conclusion. One way of characterizing the project Kant undertakes in the Critique of Pure Reason is by

The Shimer School Core Curriculum

Corcoran, J George Boole. Encyclopedia of Philosophy. 2nd edition. Detroit: Macmillan Reference USA, 2006

A Euclidic Paradigm of Freemasonry

that would join theoretical philosophy (metaphysics) and practical philosophy (ethics)?

Cover Photo: Burke/Triolo Productions/Brand X Pictures/Getty Images

A Comprehensive Critical Study of Gadamer s Hermeneutics

Why Pleasure Gains Fifth Rank: Against the Anti-Hedonist Interpretation of the Philebus 1

Philosophy 405: Knowledge, Truth and Mathematics Spring Russell Marcus Hamilton College

1/9. Descartes on Simple Ideas (2)

Nicomachean Ethics. p. 1. Aristotle. Translated by W. D. Ross. Book II. Moral Virtue (excerpts)

The Value of Mathematics within the 'Republic'

Glossary alliteration allusion analogy anaphora anecdote annotation antecedent antimetabole antithesis aphorism appositive archaic diction argument

Ed. Carroll Moulton. Vol. 1. New York: Charles Scribner's Sons, p COPYRIGHT 1998 Charles Scribner's Sons, COPYRIGHT 2007 Gale

The Philosophy of Language. Frege s Sense/Reference Distinction

History Admissions Assessment Specimen Paper Section 1: explained answers

Necessity in Kant; Subjective and Objective

Learning Objectives Lower Grammar Stage. Kindergarten: The Cradle of Civilization Year First Grade: The Greek Year Second Grade: The Roman Year

Introduction and Overview

How to Write a Paper for a Forensic Damages Journal

Categories and Schemata

Culture, Space and Time A Comparative Theory of Culture. Take-Aways

MIRA COSTA HIGH SCHOOL English Department Writing Manual TABLE OF CONTENTS. 1. Prewriting Introductions 4. 3.

Architecture is epistemologically

Japan Library Association

Virtues o f Authenticity: Essays on Plato and Socrates Republic Symposium Republic Phaedrus Phaedrus), Theaetetus

The Strengths and Weaknesses of Frege's Critique of Locke By Tony Walton

REVIEW ARTICLE IDEAL EMBODIMENT: KANT S THEORY OF SENSIBILITY

The Greatest Invention in the World. Marshall High School Mr. Cline Western Civilization II Unit TWO JA

WHY STUDY THE HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY? 1

The Doctrine of the Mean

The Debate on Research in the Arts

Are There Two Theories of Goodness in the Republic? A Response to Santas. Rachel Singpurwalla

124 Philosophy of Mathematics

The Object Oriented Paradigm

Aristotle. Aristotle. Aristotle and Plato. Background. Aristotle and Plato. Aristotle and Plato

Bas C. van Fraassen, Scientific Representation: Paradoxes of Perspective, Oxford University Press, 2008.

The Human Intellect: Aristotle s Conception of Νοῦς in his De Anima. Caleb Cohoe

Logical Foundations of Mathematics and Computational Complexity a gentle introduction

Publishing a Journal Article

Euler s Art of Reckoning 1

Rethinking the Aesthetic Experience: Kant s Subjective Universality

Cover Page. The handle holds various files of this Leiden University dissertation.

Guidelines for Manuscript Preparation for Advanced Biomedical Engineering

Module 11. Reasoning with uncertainty-fuzzy Reasoning. Version 2 CSE IIT, Kharagpur

Edward Winters. Aesthetics and Architecture. London: Continuum, 2007, 179 pp. ISBN

Object Oriented Learning in Art Museums Patterson Williams Roundtable Reports, Vol. 7, No. 2 (1982),

PHI 3240: Philosophy of Art

In retrospect: The Structure of Scientific Revolutions

Impact of the Fundamental Tension between Poetic Craft and the Scientific Principles which Lucretius Introduces in De Rerum Natura

Dabney Townsend. Hume s Aesthetic Theory: Taste and Sentiment Timothy M. Costelloe Hume Studies Volume XXVIII, Number 1 (April, 2002)

ARISTOTLE AND THE UNITY CONDITION FOR SCIENTIFIC DEFINITIONS ALAN CODE [Discussion of DAVID CHARLES: ARISTOTLE ON MEANING AND ESSENCE]

High School Photography 1 Curriculum Essentials Document

Writing Course for Researchers SAMPLE/Assignment XX Essay Review

TERMS & CONCEPTS. The Critical Analytic Vocabulary of the English Language A GLOSSARY OF CRITICAL THINKING

Claim: refers to an arguable proposition or a conclusion whose merit must be established.

Aristotle on the Human Good

Humanities Learning Outcomes

Jacek Surzyn University of Silesia Kant s Political Philosophy

The Influence of Chinese and Western Culture on English-Chinese Translation

Misc Fiction Irony Point of view Plot time place social environment

Foundations in Data Semantics. Chapter 4

College and Career Readiness Anchor Standards K-12 Montana Common Core Reading Standards (CCRA.R)

2 nd Grade Visual Arts Curriculum Essentials Document

Formalizing Irony with Doxastic Logic

On The Search for a Perfect Language

We read a story in class from Whootie Owl's Test Prep Storytime Series for Level 2

Kant IV The Analogies The Schematism updated: 2/2/12. Reading: 78-88, In General

KINDS (NATURAL KINDS VS. HUMAN KINDS)

There is an activity based around book production available for children on the Gothic for England website which you may find useful.

THESIS MIND AND WORLD IN KANT S THEORY OF SENSATION. Submitted by. Jessica Murski. Department of Philosophy

Scientific Philosophy

Wincharles Coker (PhD Candidate) Department of Humanities. Michigan Technological University, USA

13th International Scientific and Practical Conference «Science and Society» London, February 2018 PHILOSOPHY

Champions of Invention. by John Hudson Tiner

SAMPLE COURSE OUTLINE PHILOSOPHY AND ETHICS GENERAL YEAR 12

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at

This text is an entry in the field of works derived from Conceptual Metaphor Theory. It begins

The Product of Two Negative Numbers 1

1/8. Axioms of Intuition

Objects and Things: Notes on Meta- pseudo- code (Lecture at SMU, Dec, 2012)

The First Hundred Instant Sight Words. Words 1-25 Words Words Words

Why Music Theory Through Improvisation is Needed

Sight and Sensibility: Evaluating Pictures Mind, Vol April 2008 Mind Association 2008

Cambridge International Examinations Cambridge International Advanced Subsidiary and Advanced Level. Published

What is Character? David Braun. University of Rochester. In "Demonstratives", David Kaplan argues that indexicals and other expressions have a

Reflections on Kant s concept (and intuition) of space

Student Guide for SOLO-TUNED HARMONICA (Part II Chromatic)

On Language, Discourse and Reality

What is Rhetoric? Grade 10: Rhetoric

Rousseau on the Nature of Nature and Political Philosophy

General Standards for Professional Baccalaureate Degrees in Music

Reviel Netz, The Shaping of Deduction in Greek Mathematics: A Study in Cognitive History

Section 1 The Portfolio

Aristotle's theory of price formation and views on chrematistics. Failing to confirm the law of demand and supply

Kansas Standards for English Language Arts Grade 9

12th Grade Language Arts Pacing Guide SLEs in red are the 2007 ELA Framework Revisions.

Peircean concept of sign. How many concepts of normative sign are needed. How to clarify the meaning of the Peircean concept of sign?

Transcription:

The Premodern Rule: History of an Epistemic Category Lorraine Daston, Max Planck Institute for the History of Science Berlin DRAFT: References are still incomplete; please don t cite or circulate without the author s permission. Introduction: Rules and Paradigms; Synonyms and Antonyms In summer 1962, West German postal workers paralyzed the country by doing exactly what they were supposed to and I do mean exactly. Forbidden by law as civil servants to go out on strike, the participants in Operation Hedgehog didn t ignore the rules; instead, they followed them, all of them, to the letter. This being Germany, there were quite a few rules, so this sly industrial action was peculiarly effective in laming all communication nation-wide. This kind of labor protest allegedly invented by the Italians in the 1920s and sometimes called an Italian strike in their honor exists in many countries and languages: work-to-rule in English, Dienst nach Vorschrift in German, faire la grève du zèle in French. By taking rules to their extreme, by making them as literal as algebra, as binding as fate, and as rigid as cast iron, work-to-rule drives a wedge between rules and reasonableness. The rules that were meant to guarantee good order end up wreaking havoc not because the rules have collapsed but because they have been upheld, with a vengeance. Work-to-rule is emblematic of a quintessentially modern quandary. In the form of everything from traffic regulations and government directives to etiquette manuals and parliamentary procedures, rules structure almost every human interaction. Increasing use of computers has intensified a trend that began in the eighteenth century of ever more, 1

ever more stringent rules for ever more domains of public and private life, as we intuitively adapt our behavior and perhaps also our thinking to the algorithms of search engines, stock market trading, social media, and myriad other online activities. We moderns cannot live without rules. But we also cannot live with them, at least not comfortably. We chafe at their complexity, their inflexibility, their inefficiency, their sheer prolixity all vices dramatized by the work-to-rule scenario. Imaginative literature has given us adjectives like kafka-esque ; social theory, images like Max Weber s iron cage and who among us has not cursed, well knowing we curse in vain, the obdurate stupidity of a computer program? At a more abstract level, many of the fault lines that run through the landscape of modern thought oppose rules to some other elusive desideratum, such as interpretation, judgment, creativity, discretion, or simple common sense. Yet these oppositions are lopsided, with intellectual respectability almost always on the side of rules the more literal, explicit, general, and rigid, the better. To take just a few examples at random: mathematicians since the early twentieth century have equated rigorous proof with specification by rules, as in the case of David Hilbert s Entscheidungsproblem; cognitive scientists consider a mental process to be explained when it can be modeled algorithmically; legislators attempt to curb judicial discretion by sentencing rules; philosophers apply the rules of Bayesian probability to decisions to accept or reject scientific hypotheses. We are all by now veterans of the algorithms used to assess academic achievement -- citation indices, Hirsch factors, number of articles in Class A journals. To gesture in the direction of all that cannot be cashed out in rules judgment, interpretation, case-based reasoning seems to be just that, hand-waving: mushy, murky, 2

and perhaps even sentimental. Analysis itself has come to be synonymous with reasoning by rules. To take an example closer to disciplinary home (and long at home here in Princeton): Thomas S. Kuhn s dogged but doomed attempts to explain clearly what he meant by paradigms in his hugely influential book, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions (1962). Readers of that book will recall the centrality of paradigms to Kuhn s account of what science is, how it works, and why it changes. (And even non-readers will know what a paradigm shift is, if only from New Yorker cartoons.) A science becomes worthy of the name when it acquires its first paradigm; scientists learn how to solve problems and indeed what constitutes a problem by textbook paradigms; scientific revolutions are nothing more or less than the dethronement of one paradigm by another. Just because it was such an all-purpose tool, the word paradigm notoriously had many meanings in Kuhn s book, twenty-one by one count. 1 There was, however, one sense of paradigm that Kuhn himself consistently underscored as the most important, namely paradigms as exemplars, as opposed to sets of rules. In his 1969 postscript to The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, Kuhn described this sense of paradigm as "models or examples, [that] can replace explicit rules as a basis for the solution of the remaining puzzles of normal science" as philosophically "deeper" than the others 2, even though he was at a loss to explain exactly how it worked. Forestalling charges of irrationalism and wooly-mindedness, he stoutly defended the knowledge transmitted by paradigms as genuine knowledge: "When I speak of knowledge embedded in shared exemplars, I am not referring to a mode of knowing that is less systematic or less analyzable than knowledge embedded in rules, laws, or criteria of identification." 3 But to date, neither 3

Kuhn nor anyone else has succeeded in clarifying that alternative mode of knowing, a perplexity, philosopher Ian Hacking concludes, in the nature of the beast. 4 So it comes as something of a shock to learn that for most of its history, the word rule and its cognates in ancient and modern European languages, from ancient Greece and Rome through the Enlightenment, was synonymous with paradigm. 5 Here for example is Pliny the Elder (23-79 CE), upholding the Greek sculptor Polykleitos s statue Doryphorus (The Spear-Bearer) as the canona (the Latinized version of the Greek word for rule, κανων), as the model of male beauty worthy of imitation by all artists: He also made what artists call a Canon [quem canones artifices vocant] or Model Statue, as they draw their artistic outlines from it as from a sort of standard. 6 Or Dionysius of Halicarnassus (60-7 BCE) praising the 5 th -century BCE Attic orator Lysias as the κανων of rhetoric, immediately glossed in the next sentence as the paradigm (παραδειγµα) of excellence. 7 Or, fast-forwarding almost two thousand years to Enlightenment France, the Encyclopédie s sample sentence for its first definition of the entry Règle, Modèle in the the life of Our Savior is the rule or the model for Christians. 8 In both ancient Greek and Latin grammars, the word canon or regula is used along with paradigma to denote that paradigm of paradigms, namely patterns of inflections such as verb conjugations intoned by schoolchildren over the centuries: amo, amas, amat, etc. It is worth bearing in mind that although the original meaning of the ancient Greek word paradeigma referred to an architectural model 9, it was also a philosophical term of art used by Plato in the Timaeus when he compared the eternal models of the divine craftsman and those of the human craftsmen who merely imitate them. 10 4

Your first response is likely to be the same as mine was: this is an intriguing example of the bizzarerie of languages, in which words occasionally flip-flop into their opposites, but no more than that. Once upon a time, long ago, a word meant A; now it means not-a. Rule (kanon, regula) once meant model or paradigm; now it means exactly the opposite: hence Kuhn s conundrum of how to clarify paradigms without reducing them to rules, i.e. without reducing A to not-a. But the etymology of the premodern cognates for rule is both richer and more unsettling than this developmental account from meaning A to meaning not-a would suggest: the more familiar modern associations of the word are also part of the definition of the premodern cognates of rule. The ancient Greek word kanon, for example, denoted painstaking exactitude, especially in connection with the arts of building and carpentry, but also in a figurative sense when applied to other domains such as art, politics, music, and astronomy: the same Polykleitos who fashioned the Doryphoros statue was the author of a lost treatise entitled Kanon in which he allegedly specified the exact proportions of the human body to be followed by artists; such prescriptive measurements of classical statues were still on display in the eighteenth century. 11 Via Galen s reference to Polykleitos, the word and concept of a canonical male body was taken up by Andreas Vesalius and other early modern anatomists. 12 Similarly, the mathematical doctrine of the proportions of strings yielding harmonic chords attributed to the Pythagoreans was known as the kanonike 13 ; Ptolemy refers to the tables used by astronomers to compute planetary positions as kanones. 14 The range of the Latin regula followed that of the Greek kanon closely. 15 This cluster of meanings evokes the rigor of mathematics, both as the geometric doctrine of proportions and as tool of measurement and computation meanings that happily co-existed with the 5

cluster centered on models and paradigms. In short, for several millennia, in various ancient and modern European languages, the word rule and is cognates meant, at least according to modern lights, A and not-a simultaneously. This is no longer just a curiosity; it is mind-boggling. My aim in this lecture is to explain the coherence of an epistemic category, that of the premodern rule, that seems self-contradictory to us moderns. Because my time frame stretches over almost two millennia, my lecture will of necessity hopscotch among centuries and genres. I realize that this will induce a certain queasy motion sickness in my fellow historians, accustomed for good reason to settle into one period and place, but I must crave their indulgence. Only by taking a panoramic view can I sharpen contrasts, pinpoint moments of transition, and, most important, use the resources of history to query the self-evidence of our contemporary concepts and modes of thinking. Simply put, the prototypical modern rule is the algorithm, preferably one so precise, definite, and finite that it can be executed by a machine; the prototypical premodern rule was a model. This is not because premodern cultures lacked algorithms quite the contrary, their mathematical traditions were rich in algorithms, expertly deployed. But even algorithms were taught primarily by examples rather than by explicit, step-by-step, instructions. I shall address the coherence of the category of the premodern rule using examples drawn from diverse domains: monastic rules; rules of calculation for merchants; rules of measurement for builders; rules of games; and cookbooks. These of course represent only a tiny fraction of all the potentially relevant examples, especially if the category of rule is widened to include related terms such as maxims, instructions, precepts, guidelines, methods, and laws. Moreover, I make no pretense of blanket 6

coverage over more than two thousand years and a dozen relevant languages. My examples have been chosen either because they were seminal, or because they are unusually telling, or both. I shall argue that when rules are studied in practice as well as in precept, we can begin to grasp the ways in which rules and paradigms were once so closely intertwined as to be synonyms. II. The Straight and Narrow: The History of a Word The Greek word kanon derives from the ancient Semitic languages, cognate with the Hebrew qaneh 16 ), which refers to a kind of cane (same root) plant (Arundo donax) found in Asia and the Mediterranean and used for thousands of years to make baskets, balance beams, and measuring rods. [IMAGE: Arundo donax] The earliest attested uses in archaic Greek refer to rods or wands of various kinds, and later to a straightedge, which may or may not be marked with measuring units. The word occurs in the context of all kinds of building activities: masons, carpenters, and architects all use a kanon to make sure that their constructions are straight and fit together precisely: the kanon serves akribeia, the painstaking exactitude needed to put together a solid, straight, symmetric temple, house, wall, or other structure. 17 This literal meaning of a rule as a straightedge used to enforce exactitude persists in almost every ancient and modern cognate of the Greek word kanon, including the Latin regula 18 and of course the English ruler. The rule stands for the straight and narrow, unbending and unforgiving, a meaning with which we are all too familiar. We will have occasion in all three lectures to return again and again to this Ur-meaning of rule, in both its literal and figurative uses. 7

Branching out figuratively from this literal stem, meanings ramify. I have already mentioned the use of kanon in connection with the imitation of a model or pattern; by the 5 th c. BCE, the word was also being used by the likes of Plato and Aristotle in connection with law, ethics, and politics. 19 For my purposes, Aristotle metaphorical use of rule is particularly interesting, because it hints at somewhat more supple formulations of actual rules that endured for millennia. In the opening paragraphs of the Nicomachean Ethics, Aristotle famously declared that ethics does not attain and should not aspire to the exactitude of geometry. He returns to the problem of excessive exactitude in a contrast between the rigidity of the law that treats all alike as opposed to what is equitable or mete (epieikeia), i.e. justice apportioned to each according to circumstance and moral deserts. 20 Aristotle compares meteness to a special kind of tool from the island of Lesbos, a ruler made of lead, a soft substance in comparison to rulers made of wood, stone, or iron. 21 This kind of ruler can bend to fit the object to be measured, just as the justice of what is mete and right, in contrast to the justice of laws, can bend to fit the particulars of the case. But the Lesbian ruler is still a ruler, and meteness is still a form of justice. Aristotle reins in caprice by his choice of metaphor; justice should never be arbitrary. What is mete and right corrects the lawgiver in letter but not in spirit: When the law speaks universally, then, and a case arises on it which is not covered by the universal statement, then it is right, when the legislator fails us and has erred by over-simplicity, to correct the omission to say what the legislator himself would have said had he been present, and would have put into his law had he known. The image of two rulers, one of rigid iron and the other of flexible lead, universal laws complemented by particular considerations, aptly describes the way in which actual rules were routinely formulated in many premodern 8

European contexts. IMAGE: PLAN OF LECTURE, WITH III. HIGHLIGHTED IN RED] III. The Rule and the Exception: The Rule of St. Benedict To get some sense of how this would work in a specific case, I turn to an enormously influential example of a rule 22, the Rule of St. Benedict (Regula Sancta Benedicti) formulated in the 6 th c. CE for Benedict s own monastery at Monte Cassino and for centuries thereafter the model for all subsequent monastic orders in the Christian West. 23 Cenobite monasticism (i.e. living in communities as opposed to anchorite monks, who withdrew from society) did not originate with Benedict of Nursia; nor did the idea of formal rules to govern such communities of monks and nuns. 24 But it was Benedict s Rule (in the singular), with its seventy-three detailed chapters regulating everything from what the monks wore to how they sung psalms on Sundays, which defined both the discipline of an ordered life and also furnished the foremost example of what a rule meant in the Latin West for over a thousand years. So it will repay examination in some detail. And the Rule of Saint Benedict is all about detail: in winter, the monks must rise from their beds at the eighth hour of the night to celebrate vigils; each monk sleeps in his own bed, clothed and belted, in a common dormitory in which a light burns until morning; all the monks must perform kitchen duties once a week, including washing all the towels and serving the other monks at the single meal of the day; the meal consists of two cooked dishes plus a daily ration of one pound of bread; the hours of meals are the sixth hour of the day from Easter to Pentecost and the ninth hour on Wednesdays and 9

Fridays for the rest of the summer until September 13 th ; during meals the only sound should be the reading from the bible four or five pages and not from the Heptateuch or the Book of Kings. Equally specific is the graduated scale of punishments for infractions, from being excluded from mealtimes to ejection from the monastery. If micro-managers have a patron saint, it is surely St. Benedict. Yet detailed rules are not necessarily rigid rules. Monastic life revolved around the person of the abbot, who was as it were the rule of the Rule: the living model of a holy life, mentioned one-hundred-and-twenty times in the text, and responsible for every monk and every aspect of monastery activity. The abbot, whose name derives from the New Testament Aramaic word abbas or father, is invested with vast amounts of discretion, which is praised by Benedict as the mother of all virtues (ch. 64). Discretio (not a classical Latin word) means the ability to draw distinctions (discenere) and to consider each case on its merits. 25 Over and over again the precepts of the Rule of St. Benedict are firmly and sharply enunciated, only for the abbot s discretion to be invoked in the next sentence. For example, in chapter 33 we are told in no uncertain terms: No monk may possess any property, nothing whatsoever, neither book nor writing tablet nor stylus absolutely nothing unless the abbot wills otherwise. Or, in ch. 63, concerning rank in the monastery, Benedict begins in his usual unequivocal tone: In no case may age determine rank, for did not Samuel and Daniel, albeit young, stand in judgment over the eldest? But then, in the very next sentence, comes the usual qualification: Unless the abbot after considered deliberation or for particular reasons should decide to alter the usual order defined by date of entry in the monastery. 10

The abbot s discretion, like that of Aristotle s equitable judge 26, is by no means arbitrary; rather, he is enjoined to adapt the rigor of the Rule to particular circumstances and to the individual capacities of the monks, for whom he will be held responsible in the eyes of God: He represents Jesus Christ in the monastery (ch.2). At every point, he is explicitly called upon to adjust the Rule as situation dictates, e.g. with respect to food and drink: the strict portions and mealtimes may be relaxed out of consideration for the weak (ch.39); no one may eat the flesh of four-footed animals except the sick (ch. 39); everyone must take his turn in the kitchen, but the weak may receive extra help (ch. 36); a monk who makes a mistake in his work or who breaks or loses the monastery s property and does not immediately confess his guilt should be severely punished unless it is a question of hidden sin, in which case the abbot may minister to the wounded soul without exposing the mistake (ch. 46). For almost every precept of the Rule, exceptions are foreseen; discretion is exercised; specific circumstances are weighed. Accustomed as we are to the peremptory tone of modern rules, which strongly discourage the exercise of discretion at a red light or in reporting one s taxable income or paying the subway fare, we are likely to find the characteristic diction of the Rule of St. Benedict somewhat comical, on the analogy of the pet owners who stipulate that their new puppy may under absolutely no circumstances no, never -- come sleep in their bed unless it whines or begs prettily or scratches long enough at the door. But there is nothing weak-willed or wavering about Benedict s Rule. What to modern eyes reads as a see-sawing between stringency and indulgence was to premodern sensibilities the only way to formulate a complete rule, both specific and supple. The abbot does not simply enforce the Rule; he embodies it, as the Doryphoros statue embodies the canon of male 11

beauty. More than that: the abbot s discretion is part of the Rule. He is the Lesbian leaden ruler that adjusts the straight iron ruler to the curves of individual cases. The remarkable longevity of the Rule of St. Benedict, endlessly reformed and re-introduced and still in use in monastic communities throughout the world, testifies to the resilience of this alloy of iron and lead. IV. The Rule and the Example: Commercial Arithmetic The Rule of St. Benedict shows us one way in which rule and paradigm, rigor and suppleness, could be combined. Not only are exceptions foreseen as part of the formulation of the rule; the interpreter of the rule, the abbot, is also its exemplification. Another way of putting this is that the text of the Rule is not free-standing; without an abbot worthy of his office, it remains incomplete. But however influential the Rule of St. Benedict may have been in the Latin West, it would be entirely reasonable to object that its discipline hardly compares with the rigor of mathematics. What about rules closer to the original meaning of the Greek kanon and the Latin regula, rules about exact measurement and calculation? The association of rules with exactitude, especially mathematical exactitude, stretches as far back as our sources reach and is still present indeed, omnipresent in modern reflections about what rules are and how they work. Although it may not have been the primary premodern definition of rule, it was never absent. I therefore turn to some of the best-known rules of medieval and early modern commercial arithmetic and measurement. In this domain, there is no single text that can compare in authority and 12

influence with the Rule of St. Benedict, so my evidence will be more statistical and scattershot. Some regularities do nonetheless emerge. This table shows the kinds of problems to which late medieval French manuscripts on commercial arithmetic applied the most widespread of all reckoning rules, the Rule of Three. What was the Rule of Three? Here (in the original French and in my translation) is how the Kadran aus marchans (late 15 th /early 16 th c.) explains it 27 : La reigle de troys ce nomme reigle de trois pource que tousiours y a troys nombres. C est assavoir deux semblans et ung contraire et si plus y a ilz se doyvent tous reduire a ces troys. The rule of three: called the rule of three because there are always three numbers, viz. two similars and one contrary and if there are more all must be reduced to these three. None the wiser? I suspect that the fifteenth-century merchant reading this explanation was also scratching his head. But then comes the example: Comme dire: si 3 florins d Avignon vallent 2 frans de roy, combine vaudront 20 florins d Avignon? That is to say, if 3 Avignon florins are worth 2 royal francs, how much would 20 Avignon florins be worth? Answer: (2 X 20) 3 = 13 1/3. After working the half-dozen examples of this sort provided by the text, the merchant was probably able not only to convert currencies but also to find prices: if 4 ells of silk cost 20 florins, how much would 10 ells cost? He would have needed neither algebra nor the Euclidean doctrine of proportions in order to generalize from one example to another; nor would he have been fazed by a shift in subject matter, from currency exchanges to the price of silk or the conversion of weights and measures. The generality of the rule lay not in its bare enunciation (as often as not unintelligible on its own) but rather in the enunciation plus the examples. Anyone who has recently looked at an elementary 13

mathematics textbook will recognize the format. As in the case of the Rule of St. Benedict, what we would identify as the rule proper was not free-standing: the examples were part of the rule, and the rule owed its generality to the accumulation of specifics in the various examples. Let us take another example from the realm of calculation and measurement, this time from a 1556 English treatise on measurement that promised to teach surveyors, masons, and carpenters diverse most certayne and sufficient rules, touching the measuring of all manner Superficies of timber, stone, glass, and land. 28 The author, the mathematician and surveyor Leonard Digges, reproaches heady and selfwylled craftsmen for adhering to false rules in measuring stands of timber, and wraps himself in the mantle of the infallible grounds of geometry. Yet his alternative rules are not only expressed almost entirely by means of examples; he also cautions that discretion must be exercised in order to simplify calculations: It were intolerable tediousness, yea impossible, to sette foorth the true quantities of timber measure, to all odde quantities of squares. The discrete handlynge of these, the wittye shall brynge to a sufficient exactnesse. 29 In a similar vein, the early seventeenth-century Welsh composer Elway Bevin explained how to write musical canons, the most mathematical form of what was still considered a branch of mathematics, namely the theory of musical chords. Bevin instructs the would-be composer almost entirely via examples. Canons are now considered the most rule-bound, even algorithmic, form of musical composition, but Bevin proceeds from simple examples (varying plainsong just by altering the rests) to ones so complex that he compares them to the frame of this world, for as the world doth consist of the 14

four Elements, viz. Fire, Ayre, Water and the Earth so likewise this canon consisteth and is devided into foure severall Canons. 30 Even the mathematical sciences arithmetic, measurement, harmonics were codified as much by examples as by rules. Or rather, the examples were part and parcel of the rules, a necessary supplement and sometimes even a substitute. Consider Charles Cotton s compendious 1687 treatise The Compleate Gamester, which offers instruction on billiards, chess, all manner of card games, horse racing, cock fighting, and just about any other form of what he calls the enchanting witchery of gaming might take in the more louche sections of London. Cotton is profligate in details of all kinds: descriptions of how cheats can strip a player s coat of its gold buttons while he is preoccupied with the throw of the dice; admonitions not to let sleeves drag and pipe ashes spill onto the billiard table; instructions on how to judge the courage of a fighting cock by its frequent crowing in the pen and how to encourage a horse being led to the race course to smell other Horses dung, that thereby he may be enticed to stole and empty his body as he goes. Various orders, laws, and rules, are set forth for the various games, many of which we would readily recognize as rules of the game: e.g. if you touch a chess piece, you must then play it. But Cotton warns his reader that some games can be mastered only by experience e.g. the fiendishly difficult game of Irish, which is not to be learn d otherwise than by observation and practice, or even chess, the subject of one of the book s longest chapters. Cotton toys with the idea that Chess as well as Draughts may be plaid by a certain Rule but, after some twenty pages of detailed instructions, concludes that [m]any more Observations might be here inserted for the understanding of this noble Game, which I am forced to wave to avoid prolixity. 31 15

Not only Cotton s treatise but the successive eighteenth-century editions of Edmond Hoyle s guides to whist and other card games aimed at making the reader not just competent but proficient. For that reason, the line between what we would call the rules of the game proper (e.g. how many cards each player is dealt at the beginning of a hand of whist) and tips on how to win (e.g. If you have Queen, Knave, and three small trumps, with a good suit, trump out with a small one. 32 ) is deliberately blurred. Psychology and calculation conspire to best one s opponent, even in chess. Cotton duly supplies the values of each piece, from pawn to queen, but in the next breath counsels the reader: besides you are to note, that whatsoever piece your adversary plays most or best with all, be sure, if it lie in your power, to deprive him thereof, though it be done with loss of the like, or of one somewhat better, as a Bishop for a Knight; for by this means you may frustrate your adversaries design and become as cunning as himself. 33 In the course of the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries, the rules of games were standardized, first at gambling haunts like the Parisian académies de jeu and the London Ordinaries, and later by a steady stream of handbooks such as those by Cotton and Hoyle. 34 Standardization did not however necessarily imply severing the link between rule and practice. Indeed, just as mastery of a rule in mathematics and measurement entailed working through the examples, so mastering a rule of whist or chess entailed observation and experience. Once again, the rules were not free-standing: models, examples, tips, and observation propped them up and filled them out. This is not necessarily because the rules 16

were vague or unspecific or approximate; rather, it was because no universal formulation could anticipate all the particulars with which it would be confronted in practice. The gap between universals and particulars is hardly news; what is striking about the premodern rules are the provisions they included to bridge that gap. V. Making Experience Explicit: Cookbooks There is one genre of premodern rulebook that rarely aspired to any kind of universal or even generalization: cookbooks were almost exclusively about particulars. They therefore raise a different kind of problem about applying rules in practice: how to build practice into the rules themselves. Whereas seventeenthcentury cookbooks were generally addressed to readers who had already undergone an apprenticeship in the kitchen and who were looking to improve their position in an aristocratic household by learning how to prepare the latest French sauces and sweetmeats 35, their eighteenth-century successors were increasingly pitched to the clueless scullery maid or at least her literate mistress. The latter type of cookbook explicitly aimed at free-standing rules, albeit rules rooted in the particulars of eggs, flour, sugar, and butter. Two English cookbooks, one published in 1660 and the other in 1746, will serve to make this contrast vivid. Robert May s The Accomplisht Cook, Or the Art and Mystery of Cookery is addressed To the Master Cooks, and to such young Practitioners of the Art of Cookery who had already completed their 17

apprenticeship. May set forth his own credentials at length: son of a master cook in a noble household, he had apprenticed in both London and Paris before cooking for Lord Lumley in London and various nobles in Kent, Sussex, Essex, Yorkshire when rusticated by the Civil War. May promised his readers not only the fruits of his long experience, practice, and converse with the most ablest men in their times but also new Terms of Art, mostly French, to his backwards countrymen, already woefully behind continental standards of haute cuisine. 36 May seemed just the sort of high-falutin cookbook author Mary Kettilby had in her sights when she offered her collection of some three hundred recipes as Palatable, Useful, and Intelligible, which is more than can be said of some great Masters having given us Rules in that Art so strangely odd and fantastical, that tis hard to say, Whether the Reading has given more Sport and Diversion, or the Practice more Vexation and Chagrin, by following their Directions. She was writing not for aspiring master cooks of lords and ladies but rather for Young and Unexperienc d Dames and Cook-Maids at Country-Inns. 37 Yet Kettilby also assured her readers that her culinary and medical recipes conveyed the great Knowledge, and long Experience of those Excellent Persons who had contributed them. In contrast to May, however, Kettilby was attempting to distill experience for the inexperienced, not the somewhat experienced who had already apprenticed to a master. Her rules aimed to be free-standing or, as a modern cookbook might put it, foolproof. 18

How did this alleged contrast cash out in the recipes? Here are two recipes for desserts with similar ingredients (warning: not for the lipophobic!): A boild Pudding Beat the yolks of three eggs with rose water, and half a pint of cream, warm it with a piece of butter as big as a walnut, and when it is melted mix the eggs and that together, and season it with nutmeg, sugar, and salt; then put in as much bread as will make it thick as batter, and lay on as much flour as will lie on a shilling, then take a double cloth, wet it, and flour it, tie it fast, and put it in a pot; when it is boild, serve it up on a dish with butter, verjuyce [grape vinegar], and sugar. Robert May, The Accomplished Cook (1671), p. 177. To make Fry d Cream Take a Quart of good new Cream, the Yolks of seven Eggs, a Bit of Lemon Peel, a grated Nutmeg, two Spoonfuls of Sack, as much Orange-flower Water: Butter your Sauce-pan, and put it over the Fire; stir it all the while one way with a little white Whisk, and as you stir, strew in Flour very lightly, till tis thick and smooth; then tis boil d enough, and may be pour d out upon a Cheese-plate or Mazarine; spread it with a Knife exactly even, about half an Inch thick, then cut it in Diamand-squares, and fry it in a Pan of boiling sweet Suet. Mary Kettilby, A Collection of above Three Hundred Receipts (1746), p. 61. For the sake of ready comparison, I have marked the quantitative measures in red and the procedural instructions in blue. As is clear at a glance, May and Kettilby do not differ significantly in terms of the measurements they provide (an observation confirmed by a survey of other cookbooks of this period), but rather in terms of their descriptions of techniques and how to know when the dish is done. The point here is not to deny a long-term evolution toward more and more precise measurements in recipes: the editor of a 1780 edition of a 1390 cookery 19

manuscript for example complained that the quantities of things are seldom specified, but are too much left to the taste and judgment of the cook an indication of how expectations had changed over the intervening four centuries. 38 Rather, the point of this sample comparison is to show first, that what separated the experienced from the inexperienced cook was knowledge of procedures, not amounts; and second, that this so-called tacit knowledge could be made explicit. Whether a cookbook has ever been made completely foolproof of course depends on just how foolish the fool, just as complete explicitness depends on the standardization of ingredients, cooking utensils, and ovens. But this all-or-nothing opposition between irreducibly tacit and exhaustively explicit knowledge, so characteristic of our modern debates, obscures the spectrum of possibilities illustrated by this early modern comparison. Even if no rule is completely freestanding, some are more free-standing than others. A final lesson from the early modern cookbooks: greater explicitness need not take the form of greater specificity. To take one last example of in the dessert vein, this time from Hannah Glasse s enormously popular Art of Cookery, Made Plain and Easy (first edition 1747, most recent edition 1995) addressed to every servant who can but read 39 rendering explicit the general rules for making puddings: Rules to be observed in making Puddings & c. 20

In boiled puddings, take great care that the bag or cloth be very clean, and not soapy, and dipped in hot water, and then well floured. If a bread-pudding, tie it loose; if a batter-pudding, tie it close, and be sure the water boils when you put the pudding in, and you should move your puddings in the pot now and then, for fear they stick. Hannah Glasse, Art of Cookery, Made Plain and Easy (1790) There s no need this time to highlight the procedural instructions in blue; it s all about procedure. Glasse s rules make explicit everything that May assumed his readers would know (e.g. move the pudding around from time to time to prevent sticking) and some things even Kettilby assumed went without saying (e.g. that the bag shouldn t be soapy). Note however that the rules are also general not about almond or orange or figgy pudding, but about boiled puddings per se. Increasing specificity and quantitative precision is one way of rendering the tacit explicit but it is not the only or even the most effective way to do so. On the contrary, anyone who has struggled through an instruction manual fat with prolix detail knows that too much specificity, too much exactitude converts explicit back into tacit knowledge: a variant of the work-to-rule paradox with which I began. VI. Conclusion: Nothing is Free-Standing What have we learned from this gallop through many centuries and many rule books? Recall the puzzle with which I began: how is it conceivable that from Antiquity through the Enlightenment the words for rule and paradigm could be used as synonyms? How could the Greek word kanon (or the Roman word regula or the English word rule ) be used both for a model like Polykleitos s 21

fabled Doryphoros statue and for the same sculptor s equally fabled book on the exact proportions of the human body? Or, if that example is too remote, here is Kant in the Critique of Judgment (1790) explaining the difference between talent and genius in the arts: The products of genius are models [Muster], i.e., they must be exemplary; hence, though they do not themselves arise through imitation, still they must serve others [i.e. the merely talented] for this, i.e., as a standard or rule [Richtmaße oder Regel] by which to judge. 40 This is what makes the premodern rule an epistemic category: it provides one answer to the epistemological problem of how to connect universals and particulars, as urgent in the law court as it is in the mathematics textbook. This answer lay in a more capacious sense of rule than is now presently admitted. The rule could variously encompass a model (recall the essential role of the abbot in exemplifying and interpreting the Rule of St. Benedict), foresee exceptions (Aristotle s leaden ruler), provide examples (as in the medieval books of commercial arithmetic), appeal to observation and experience (as in the case of seventeenth- and eighteenthcentury game manuals), and/or render experience explicit (as in the case of the cookbooks). In almost all of these cases, what to modern eyes looks like supplementary material models, exceptions, examples, experience is not only integral to the premodern rule; it supplies the means by which universals are applied to particulars. As Kant observes apropos of how artists learn to imitate the rule or model but not copy it (Nachahmung instead of Nachmachung), How that is possible is difficult to explain. 41 For our purposes, what is important to emphasize is that there doesn t seem to be any one single explanation. In some instances, reasoning from universal rule to particular case resembles what has been called case-based reasoning and assimilated to John Stuart 22

Mill s description of reasoning from particulars to particulars 42 : e.g. from the conduct of this particular abbot to the decision about how to handle this particular disobedient monk. But in other cases, something more like generalization over specific instances seems to be at work: e.g. from many different examples of solving problems in proportions to the Rule of Three. In still others, experience teaches how to adapt the rule to new circumstances via analogical reasoning: e.g. by the identification of legal precedents or the substitution of a local ingredient for an exotic one in a recipe. In the midst of all of this diversity, two constants nonetheless stand out: first, there is always some kind of bridge provided between universals and particulars; second, neither the universal nor the particulars are sufficient by themselves. Just as the rules are not free-standing, neither are the models or the examples. Although it may be possible to learn how to measure a stand of timber or compose a musical canon or bake a tasty pudding purely by example, the rules that subsume these activities are not superfluous. They guarantee that all the examples, models, and paradigms are exemplars of the same category the Rule of Three rather than the Rule of Company; billiards rather chess; precedents for the law prohibiting pick-pocketing rather than the law prohibiting armed robbery; canons rather than cantatas. The integrity of the category is the precondition for reasoning by analogy; it is even the precondition for the recognition of exceptions. A whale is an exception to the rule that all mammals live on land, but a whale is not even an exception to the Rule of Three. Without the boundaries defined by the universal formulations of rules, we would be lost forever in an uncharted sea of particulars. Neither the rule nor the models, examples, exceptions, and experience are free-standing. 23

This holds even for those premodern rules that resemble the quintessential modern rule most closely: algorithms. Ancient Babylonian, Egyptian, Chinese, Greek, and Indian mathematical traditions are rich in algorithms and also in material technologies with which to manipulate them from the wax tablet to counting rods to the abacus to the slide rule. There are important differences among these traditions: in some cases algorithms are explicitly proven or implicitly checked and in others apparently simply given; in some cases greatest emphasis falls upon the enunciation of a general rule and in others it is the paradigmatic example that bears the weight of representing the universal in the particular. Generalizations across epochs and traditions are therefore precarious. But one generalization holds across the board: premodern algorithms were executed by people, not machines. The mechanization of calculation was a gradual process that began in the late eighteenth century with the application of the principles of division of labor to human calculators and by no means ended when reliable, massmanufactured calculating machines like the Thomas Arithmometer became available in the mid-nineteenth century. 43 For almost a century, in astronomical observatories, insurance offices, census bureaus, and wartime weapon projects, wherever calculations had to be done on an industrial scale, humans and machines worked in tandem to apply algorithms. Only in the final quarter of the twentieth century was near-full automation of the execution of computational algorithms achieved by preprogrammed electronic devices. Yet already in the early nineteenth century, even before algorithms could be reliably executed on counting machines, much less computers, these sorts of computations began to be described as "mechanical," a word that flags a new way of 24

viewing algorithms as rules that can be followed with little or no understanding -- and followed in a completely standardized fashion, without adjustments to specific context. Thin rules in the modern sense are ideally general rules. They are unencumbered by examples and exceptions, they do not traffic in specifics, they float above context. Thick rules, as we have seen, shuttle back and forth between precept and practice, each refining and defining the other. Thin rules, in contrast, aspire to be free-standing. They wear their interpretations on their sleeves; they eschew commentary and have no need of hermeneutics. Thin rules need not be concise -- computer programs can go on for pages, ditto arithmetic calculations -- but they cannot be vague. Algebra is their native tongue, at once general yet definite. It is no accident that champions of artificial, universal languages, from the German polymath Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz in the seventeenth century to the French philosophe Étienne Bonnot de Condillac in the eighteenth century to the Italian logician and mathematician Giuseppe Peano in the late nineteenth century, have held up algebra and arithmetic as their models of maximum generality and minimum ambiguity. 44 Modern algorithms, as the Duchess of Windsor once opined in a different context, cannot be too thin. So what are we to make of the nubbly specificity of most premodern algorithms, almost always embedded first, within a particular problem text; second, within a repertoire on computation techniques and tools; third, within a pedagogical setting that presumably made explicit what is only implicit in the text; and fourth, within a broader category of step-by-step instructions that, depending on the culture, may include recipes, rituals, or how-to manuals? Can thin rules be pried out of these dense matrices, like metal extracted from ore, as the modern algebraic reformulations would suggest? The answers 25

to these questions depend on rethinking the idea of generality -- this time without the crutch of algebra. Generality comes in kinds and degrees. In the twentieth century, mathematicians recast Euclidean geometry in austerely formal terms. Some focused on Books VII-IX and rechristened them "the arithmetic books of Euclid". 45 Others speculated (especially in connection with Book II) about implicit algebraic structures underlying the geometric demonstrations 46 -- a view emphatically rejected by some historians as anachronistic, igniting a fierce controversy. 47 However debatable the historical accuracy of these reinterpretations of geometric demonstrations in terms of modern algebra and number theory (or as computer programs 48 ) may have been, such reformulations did raise the level of generality of the propositions by greatly expanding the scope of the mathematical objects to which they applied. In his Vorlesungen über neuere Geometrie (1882), German mathematician Moritz Pasch helped pave the way for these expansionist interpretations by his insistence that, in the name of ironclad deductive rigor, Euclidean geometry must free itself as completely as possible from the sense perceptions in which it had originated: "If geometry is to be really deductive, the process of inference must everywhere be independent of the meaning [Sinn] of the geometric concepts, just as [this process] must be independent of the figures". 49 Following Pasch, Hilbert pushed this generality to new heights in his Grundlagen der Geometrie (1899 and later editions), insisting that whether geometry was about points, lines, and planes or tables, chairs, and beer mugs made no difference to the logical validity of the formal relationships deduced from the axioms. 50 Generalization had ended up in abstraction. From this alpine perspective, the objects of Euclidean propositions need not even be mathematical, much less geometrical. 26

Judged by these ethereal standards of generality, even the most general of premodern algorithms, such as Euclid's propositions VII.1-2, seem myopically specific. But formalization, whether by means of algebra or logic, is not the only means of achieving generality -- and generality of mathematical objects is not the only kind of generality. The twentieth-century efforts to generalize Euclidean geometry by assimilating it to arithmetic, algebra, number theory, and logic aimed to safeguard the consistency and rigor of mathematics -- not to solve problems, the original objective of most premodern (and many modern) algorithms, and most certainly not to train students in these practices, the context of most premodern texts about algorithms. 51 So the question concerning generality must be reframed: what standards of generality suit problem solving, especially in pedagogical and practical contexts? Two striking features leap out from premodern algorithm texts, however diverse they may be in other respects: first, they are overwhelmingly about solving specific problems; and second, there are many problems involving the same algorithm. Recall the medieval French textbook on commercial arithmetic: although the Rule of Three is stated in general form, readers are expected to master it by working through problem after problem about converting currencies, pricing different lengths of cloth, dividing up profits among investors, and so on -- and on and on. This format still dominates most elementary mathematical textbooks, to the point that the specific problems form their own genres: remember all the train and bathtub problems in your introductory algebra text that taught how to solve simultaneous equations in two unknowns? Or, for those who were schooled before the affordable pocket calculator, learning to extract square roots by actually doing so from many specific numbers, over and over again? There are general 27

algebraic algorithms for all of these procedures; a computer can be programmed to perform all of them; even without algebra and computers, the general rules can be and were formulated verbally. Yet actual learning -- including learning how to generalize from one specific problem to the next, equally but differently specific problem -- occurs knee-deep in the weedy specifics, pencil (or stylus or abacus bead or counting stone) in hand. Although the process can and does yield more general rules, these are an afterthought, more a summary of what has been learned than a guide for how to learn the algorithm. What the students perform in solving problem after problem about the Rule of Three or the Rule of False Position 52 is a kind of induction: not an induction from particulars to a generalization but rather from particulars to particulars. John Stuart Mill contended that all induction proceeds from particulars to particulars, the premises of syllogisms (or mathematical axioms and postulates) being no more than the condensation of millions of particular observations made since time immemorial. 53 But for our purposes, there is no need to embrace Mill's sweeping generalization about all generalizations. It suffices to acknowledge that some sort of induction from particulars to particulars describes how beginners actually learn algorithms, from ancient Egypt to almost any elementary school classroom in the world right now. It does yield generalizations, but of a special kind, which are more akin to the classifications of natural history than to logical universals. After dutifully working through a dozen or so specific problems on converting currencies or dividing a certain number of loaves of bread among a different number of laborers or the arrival times of trains traveling at different speeds, the student will somehow recognize a new problem of this type -- even if it has nothing to do with currencies or loaves of bread or trains. Just as 28