Forms and Causality in the Phaedo. Michael Wiitala

Similar documents
7AAN2026 Greek Philosophy I: Plato Syllabus Academic year 2015/16

THE CATHOLIC UNIVERSITY OF AMERICA. Forms as Active Causes in Plato s Phaedo and Timaeus A DISSERTATION. Submitted to the Faculty of the

Naïve realism without disjunctivism about experience

Virtues o f Authenticity: Essays on Plato and Socrates Republic Symposium Republic Phaedrus Phaedrus), Theaetetus

Aristotle on the Human Good

Plato s work in the philosophy of mathematics contains a variety of influential claims and arguments.

Verity Harte Plato on Parts and Wholes Clarendon Press, Oxford 2002

The Human Intellect: Aristotle s Conception of Νοῦς in his De Anima. Caleb Cohoe

Are There Two Theories of Goodness in the Republic? A Response to Santas. Rachel Singpurwalla

The Parmenides. chapter 1

web address: address: Description

Why Pleasure Gains Fifth Rank: Against the Anti-Hedonist Interpretation of the Philebus 1

PHIL 260. ANCIENT GREEK PHILOSOPHY. Fall 2017 Tuesday & Thursday: (Oddfellows 106)

Resemblance Nominalism: A Solution to the Problem of Universals. GONZALO RODRIGUEZ-PEREYRA. Oxford: Clarendon Press, Pp. xii, 238.

GORDON, J. (2012) PLATO S EROTIC WORLD: FROM COSMIC ORIGINS TO HUMAN DEATH. CAMBRIDGE, CAMBRIDGE UNIVERSITY PRESS.

Riccardo Chiaradonna, Gabriele Galluzzo (eds.), Universals in Ancient Philosophy, Edizioni della Normale, 2013, pp. 546, 29.75, ISBN

SUMMARY BOETHIUS AND THE PROBLEM OF UNIVERSALS

PHL 317K 1 Fall 2017 Overview of Weeks 1 5

Do Universals Exist? Realism

Creative Actualization: A Meliorist Theory of Values

Philosophy 451 = Classics 451 Wilson 213 Fall 2007 Monday and Wednesday, 11-12, Wilson Description

Aristotle s Metaphysics

An Aristotelian Puzzle about Definition: Metaphysics VII.12 Alan Code

ARISTOTLE AND THE UNITY CONDITION FOR SCIENTIFIC DEFINITIONS ALAN CODE [Discussion of DAVID CHARLES: ARISTOTLE ON MEANING AND ESSENCE]

On Sense Perception and Theory of Recollection in Phaedo

Image and Imagination

Conclusion. One way of characterizing the project Kant undertakes in the Critique of Pure Reason is by

Plato s Forms. Feb. 3, 2016

Guide to the Republic as it sets up Plato s discussion of education in the Allegory of the Cave.

Instantiation and Characterization: Problems in Lowe s Four-Category Ontology

PURE REALISM: PLATONISM AS A SERIOUS CONTEMPORARY ALTERNATIVE. Keywords: pure realism, Platonism, metaphysics, natures

Plato on Metaphysical Explanation: Does Participating Mean Nothing?

Plato s Enlightenment, History of Philosophy Quarterly, Vol 14, No 2, April 1997, pp

The Value of Mathematics within the 'Republic'

PHI 3240: Philosophy of Art

Perceptions and Hallucinations

The identity theory of truth and the realm of reference: where Dodd goes wrong

Varieties of Nominalism Predicate Nominalism The Nature of Classes Class Membership Determines Type Testing For Adequacy

Predication and Ontology: The Categories

ARISTOTLE S METAPHYSICS. February 5, 2016

ABELARD: THEOLOGIA CHRISTIANA

Pleasure, Pain, and Calm: A Puzzling Argument at Republic 583e1-8

Care of the self: An Interview with Alexander Nehamas

Lecture 12 Aristotle on Knowledge of Principles

Aristotle's Stoichiology: its rejection and revivals

NI YU. Interpreting Memory, Forgetfulness and Testimony in Theory of Recollection

Social Mechanisms and Scientific Realism: Discussion of Mechanistic Explanation in Social Contexts Daniel Little, University of Michigan-Dearborn

observation and conceptual interpretation

Plato s. Analogy of the Divided Line. From the Republic Book 6

A Puzzle about Hume s Theory of General Representation. According to Hume s theory of general representation, we represent generalities by

Rational Agency and Normative Concepts by Geoffrey Sayre-McCord UNC/Chapel Hill [for discussion at the Research Triangle Ethics Circle] Introduction

Aesthetics Mid-Term Exam Review Guide:

TEST BANK. Chapter 1 Historical Studies: Some Issues

The Third Kind: An Analysis of the Receptacle in Plato s Timaeus

Overcoming Attempts to Dichotomize the Republic

Tropes and the Semantics of Adjectives

Composition, Counterfactuals, Causation

PHILOSOPHY PLATO ( BC) VVR CHAPTER: 1 PLATO ( BC) PHILOSOPHY by Dr. Ambuj Srivastava / (1)

Book Reviews Department of Philosophy and Religion Appalachian State University 401 Academy Street Boone, NC USA

International Journal of Advancements in Research & Technology, Volume 4, Issue 11, November ISSN

The Introduction of Universals

Categories and Schemata

To link to this article:

Practical Intuition and Deliberation in the Ethics of Aristotle. Word Count: 3,962 (With Notes, Header, and Abstract: 5,111)

206 Metaphysics. Chapter 21. Universals

PAUL REDDING S CONTINENTAL IDEALISM (AND DELEUZE S CONTINUATION OF THE IDEALIST TRADITION) Sean Bowden

LANGUAGE THROUGH THE LENS OF HERACLITUS'S LOGOS

Unity and Primary Substance for Aristotle

Z.13: Substances and Universals

Colonnade Program Course Proposal: Explorations Category

Thomas Szanto: Bewusstsein, Intentionalität und mentale Repräsentation. Husserl und die analytische Philosophie des Geistes

Humanities 116: Philosophical Perspectives on the Humanities

1. Physically, because they are all dressed up to look their best, as beautiful as they can.

Perception and Judgment in Plato's Theaetetus

dialectica The Place of Subjects in the Metaphysics of Material Objects

Aristotle s Modal Syllogistic. Marko Malink. Cambridge Harvard University Press, Pp X $ 45,95 (hardback). ISBN:

Scientific Philosophy

Université Libre de Bruxelles

This paper is a near-exact replica of that which appeared in S. Laurence and C. Macdonald

ships sailing past each other in the night. Delcomminette serves scholarship well, therefore, by drawing together these many discussions of the

ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY. Parmenides on Change The Puzzle Parmenides s Dilemma For Change

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at

ON ARISTOTELIAN UNIVERSALS AND INDIVIDUALS: THE VINK THAT IS IN BODY AND MAY BE IN ME. Irena Cronin

Course Syllabus. Ancient Greek Philosophy (direct to Philosophy) (toll-free; ask for the UM-Flint Philosophy Department)

UNIT SPECIFICATION FOR EXCHANGE AND STUDY ABROAD

Dabney Townsend. Hume s Aesthetic Theory: Taste and Sentiment Timothy M. Costelloe Hume Studies Volume XXVIII, Number 1 (April, 2002)

On Happiness Aristotle

Greek Ontology and the 'Is' of Truth MOHAN MATTHEN

What do our appreciation of tonal music and tea roses, our acquisition of the concepts

Lecture 10 Popper s Propensity Theory; Hájek s Metatheory

Is There Something in Common? Forms and the Theory of Word Meaning *

The erratically fine-grained metaphysics of functional kinds in technology and biology

KINDS (NATURAL KINDS VS. HUMAN KINDS)

Intensional Relative Clauses and the Semantics of Variable Objects

II. Aristotle or Nietzsche? III. MacIntyre s History, In Brief. IV. MacIntyre s Three-Stage Account of Virtue

WHAT IS WRONG WITH THE RELATIONAL THEORY OF CHANGE? Gonzalo Rodriguez-Pereyra Hertford College, Oxford

Accidental Beings in Aristotle s Ontology 1

Martin, Gottfried: Plato s doctrine of ideas [Platons Ideenlehre]. Berlin: Verlag Walter de Gruyter, 1973

The Doctrine of the Mean

Transcription:

1 Forms and Causality in the Phaedo Michael Wiitala Abstract: In Socrates account of his second sailing in the Phaedo, he relates how his search for the causes (αἰτίαι) of why things come to be, pass away, and are led him to posit the forms as causes. The sense in which the forms are causes, however, is not obvious. Consider some object, x, that has some property, F. Socrates asks, Why is x F? He claims that the safe answer to questions of this sort is that x is F because x participates in the form F. Given Socrates claim that x is F because it participates in form F, what must a form be on his account and what sort of causal power must it possess? In this paper, I will argue that the forms in the second sailing account are best understood as norms. By asking why x is F, Socrates is searching for the norm to which object x must conform in order to be an F object. Object x is F insofar as it conforms to that norm. That norm itself is form F. In the Phaedo, Socrates relates his search for the causes (αἴτιαι) of why things come to be, pass away, and are (96a5 ff.). He explains how this search eventually led him to posit the forms as the causes that answered the sort of why-questions with which he was concerned. The sense in which the forms are causes, however, is not as obvious to we contemporary readers as it apparently was to Phaedo and Echecrities, who claim that Socrates account of the way forms are causes was wonderfully clear to anyone of even small intelligence (102a4-5). 1 Consider some object, x, that has some characteristic, F. Object x is F. Socrates wants to know the cause of x s being F. So he asks, Why is x F? Socrates claims that the safe answer to questions of this sort is that x is F because x participates in the F itself form F. Say x is something beautiful, for example. Socrates claims that the safe answer to Why is x beautiful? is that x is beautiful because it participates in the form beautiful (100c3-e3). Given Socrates claim that x is F because it participates in form F, what must a form be on his account and what sort of causal power must it possess? In this paper, I will argue that the forms in the second sailing account 1 G. M. A. Grube and John M. Cooper, trans., Phaedo, in Plato: Complete Works, ed. John M. Cooper (Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company, 1997). I use Cooper s revised version of Grube s translation throughout, making modifications of my own when necessary.

2 are best understood as norms. By asking why x is F, Socrates is searching for the norm to which object x must conform in order to be an F object. Object x is F insofar as it conforms to that norm. That norm itself is the form F. I will support this thesis by considering three alternative ways of thinking about the causal power of forms. The first I will call the Property Reading. According to the Property Reading, x is F because it has the property F. Form F, on this reading, is property F. The second way of thinking about the causality of the forms is what I will call the Logical Reading. This sort of reading is proposed by Gregory Vlastos. 2 According to the Logical Reading, x is F because it satisfies the definition of F. A third way of understanding the causality of the forms is what I will call the Structuring-Causes Reading. A version of this reading has been proposed by Fiona Leigh and is suggested by some of Gail Fine s criticisms of Vlastos Logical Reading. 3 While each of these readings has merits, I argue that my own Forms as Norms Reading better explains Socrates claims about causality in Phaedo 96a5-102d4. 1. The Property Reading One way to understand Socrates safe answer is to think of forms as properties. This reading does not have much support among scholars of the Phaedo because it renders Socrates view as fundamentally confused. It is worth briefly thinking through, however, in order to get a sense of what is at stake in Socrates claims. Socrates says that beautiful things are beautiful because they participate in the beautiful itself (100c3-e3). The Property Reading glosses participate in the beautiful itself as have the property beautiful. There is even some textual 2 Gregory Vlastos, Reasons and Causes in the Phaedo, The Philosophical Review 78, no. 3 (1969): 291 325. 3 Gail Fine, Forms as Causes: Plato and Aristotle, in Mathematik Und Metaphysik Bei Aristoteles, ed. A. Graeser (Bern; Stuttgart: Haupt, 1987), 69 112; Fiona Leigh, Restless Forms and Changeless Causes, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 112, no. 2 (2012): 239 261.

3 justification for this gloss: Socrates claims that he does not insist on any specific way of speaking about how the form beautiful makes things beautiful (100d4-7). In fact, he explicitly lists the presence (100d5; παρουσία) of the form beautiful in beautiful things as one way of describing how the form beautiful makes things beautiful. Hence, one could argue that perhaps Socrates himself would be comfortable glossing beautiful things participate in the beautiful as the property beautiful is present in beautiful things. 4 The Property Reading claims that what Socrates is calling the beautiful itself is what we call the property beautiful. If so, then Socrates claim is that beautiful things are beautiful because they have the property beautiful. And generally, x is F because it has the property F. While this reading has some plausibility, the reason most commentators on the Phaedo reject it is that it does not account for the explanatory or causal power Socrates attributes to the forms. Properties have some of the characteristics typically attributed to the forms. For example, one and the same property can be in many different entities. Yet properties do not explain why the entities that have them have them. To have the property F typically just means to be F. In other words, x is F and x has the property F are typically thought of as two ways of saying the same thing. Hence, if Socrates is claiming that x is F because it has the property F, his claim is in no way explanatory, since it amounts to x is F because x is F. Having property F does not explain why x is F; whereas according to Socrates, sharing in form F does. The principle of charity, therefore, dictates that we should only accept the Property Reading if it is impossible to offer an interpretation of Socrates claims that is equally or more plausible. And there certainly are such interpretations. I now turn to some of those. 4 For why Socrates would not be comfortable with this gloss see Fiona Leigh, Being and Power in Plato s Sophist, Apeiron 43, no. 1 (2010): 78n29.

4 2. The Logical Reading Gregory Vlastos proposes what I will call the Logical Reading. 5 According to the Logical Reading, x is F because it satisfies the definition of F. Beautiful things are beautiful, for example, because they satisfy the definition of beautiful. Likewise, large things are large because they satisfy the definition of large. In the same way, squares are squares because they satisfy the definition of squareness. The sort of causality here is logical, according to Vlastos. Object x is F because it meets the logical conditions for being F. 6 As Vlastos points out, however, the F that explains why x is F is not a form. Rather, the F that explains why x is F is a definition. While Vlastos acknowledges that for Plato the forms are that which make definitions true, he argues that the causal power Socrates attributes to the forms in the second sailing passage belongs properly to definitions. Definition F explains why x is F regardless of one s theory about what makes definitions true. Squares are squares because they are plane figures with four equal straight sides and four right angles. Even a nominalist could agree to that. Hence Vlastos concludes that Plato s Squareness has no more causal efficacy than has the nominalist s. 7 The Logical Reading certainly has some advantages over the Property Reading. Definitions seem to answer the sort of why-questions Socrates asks in a way that properties do not. Yet the Logical Reading still renders a number of Socrates claims confused and misleading. First, on the Logical Reading, definitions, rather than forms, are the true causes. Socrates, however, speaks as if forms are the true causes. Second, while definitions answer certain sorts of why-questions, they do not answer the sorts of why-questions with which Socrates is concerned. Socrates is not asking Why are the things we call beautiful called 5 Vlastos, Reasons and Causes in the Phaedo. 6 Ibid., 305ff. 7 Ibid., 307.

5 beautiful? Rather, he is asking Why are beautiful things beautiful? The thing to be explained is not why we label things the way we do, but rather why things are the way they are. In other words, Socrates why-questions are metaphysical questions, not terminological ones. Granted, certain terminological consequences may follow from Socrates answers to these metaphysical questions. As Phaedo remarks at 102b1-3, things other than the forms receive their names from the names of the forms. Yet the why-questions Socrates asks are metaphysical. A nominalist or conventional definition explains nothing about why things come to be, why they pass away, and why they are. 8 If the Logical Reading is correct, Socrates questions are poorly stated. He should be asking Why is x called F? not Why is x F? Again, the principle of charity dictates we reject the Logical Reading if another reading with equal or greater plausibility can be found. 3. The Structuring-Causes Reading A third way to interpret Socrates safe answer to the why-questions he asks is to understand the forms as the structures according to which the entities that participate in them are structured. This sort of reading has been suggested in different ways by Fiona Leigh and Gail Fine, although not to my knowledge fully developed by either. 9 Fine suggests that what makes beautiful things beautiful, for Plato, is not something like bright colors or other material constituents. Rather, what makes beautiful things beautiful are more abstract features, such as structure or arrangement, to which any material constituents must conform. 10 Leigh goes further and proposes that the forms are structuring-causes. Consider the form justice. Leigh argues that the form justice specifies the structure that entities must have if they are to possess the property justice. The structure that belongs to the Form Justice as its nature, Leigh writes, 8 Cf. Fine, Forms as Causes, 95 96. 9 Leigh, Restless Forms and Changeless Causes ; Fine, Forms as Causes, 97. 10 Fine, Forms as Causes, 97.

6 and specifies what it is to have the property, being just, is a certain harmonious relation between the parts (of soul or city), each performing its own function. 11 The forms, according to the Structuring-Causes Reading, are the structures that specify the way that entities that possess the corresponding properties must be structured. Form F is the structure that specifies the way that x must be structured if x is to be F. If we apply this way of understanding the causal power of the forms to the sort of whyquestions Socrates asks as he relates his second-sailing, we get the following. Socrates claim that x is F because it participates in form F can be glossed as x is F because it is structured according to structure F. Consider the form justice again. The structure that simply is the form justice explains why just things are just. Just things are just because they are structured according to the structure that simply is the form justice. We can, of course, articulate that structure in language by means of a definition. In contrast to the Logical Reading, however, the definition is not what explains why just things are just. Rather the structure that just things instantiate explains why they are just. That structure, considered without reference to any specific instance of it, is the form justice. On the Structuring-Causes Reading, therefore, both the causal and the ontological asymmetry between form and participant is maintained. 12 The structure that is the form justice is intelligible regardless of whether there are any instances of that structure; whereas an instance of the structure that is the form justice is unintelligible without that structure. Why is x F? The safe answer, according to the Structuring-Causes Reading, is that x is F because it is an instance of the structure that form F simply is. How the Structuring-Causes Reading works in the case of the form justice, understood along the lines of Socrates account in the Republic, is relatively intuitive, since justice specifies 11 Leigh, Restless Forms and Changeless Causes, 257. 12 Cf. ibid., 255n25.

7 the way that parts of a structured whole (a city or soul) are to interact. Yet what about the sorts of forms Socrates uses as examples in the second sailing passage? As Fine s comments above suggest, it is not implausible to think of the form beautiful as a certain structure or arrangement. In the case of forms like large and small, they can be characterized as relational structures. Large, for instance, is the structure according to which one thing is in the relationship of exceeding another in size. 13 Simmias instantiates the structure large, for example, insofar as he is taller than Socrates, that is, insofar as his height exceeds the height of Socrates. The structure here is relational. Simmias is not larger than Socrates because he is Simmias (102c1-2). Nothing about the structure of Simmias himself, including his specific height, causes him to be larger than Socrates. Simmias specific height cannot be the cause of his being large because it no more explains his tallness in relation to Socrates than his shortness in relation to Phaedo. Rather the structure of the relationship between Simmias and Socrates respective heights a structure in which Simmias height exceeds and Socrates height is exceeded is what explains why Simmias is large when compared to Socrates. In other words, the largeness Simmias has when compared to Socrates is a result of Simmias participation in the form large in relation to Socrates (100e5-101b2, 102b3-d4). The Structuring-Causes Reading can make sense not only of forms that structure individual entities, like justice or beauty, but also forms like large and small that structure relations between entities. With the Structuring-Causes Reading, therefore, we have a reading that accounts for all of Socrates claims about the causality of the forms in the second sailing passage. The structure that simply is form F explains why entities that are F are F. Since structure F explains why entities insofar as they are structured according to it are structured in an F way, while entities insofar as they are structured in an F way do not explain why structure F itself is the way 13 Cf. Plato, Hippias Major, 294b2-4; Parmenides 150c7-d2.

8 it is, the Structuring-Causes Reading, unlike the Property Reading, maintains the causal priority of the form over participant. Likewise, in contrast to the Logical Reading, the Structuring- Causes Reading explains why x is F ontologically, instead of merely explaining why we call x F. Furthermore, since there could be no entities structured in an F way without structure F, whereas structure F is intelligible whether or not any spatio-temporal entities instantiate it, the Structuring-Causes Reading maintains the ontological priority of form over participant. Granting that the Structuring-Causes Reading has these strengths, in what follows I will argue that the Forms as Norms Reading is nevertheless superior in that it more clearly articulates both what a structuring-cause is and what a form is ( 4); and in that it more closely ties Socrates discussion of the causality of the forms to his claims about causality in the account of his first sailing (97b8-99c8) ( 5). 4. The Forms as Norms Reading Building on the Structuring-Causes Reading, the Forms as Norms Reading characterizes the forms as norms and claims that their causal power is their normativity. Structures, considered apart from the entities structured according to them, are norms. The structure that is the form justice, for example, is a norm that specifies that the parts of any entity that is to be just must each do their own proper work (ἔργον) (Republic, 433b2-4). Similarly, the structure that is the form squareness is a norm dictating that any entity that is to be a square must be a plane figure that has four equal straight sides and four right angles. Likewise, the structure that is the form large is a norm specifying that whatever is large must exceed something else in size. Simmias is large when compared to Socrates because, when compared to Socrates, Simmias conforms to the norm that the form large simply is. In this way, the norm that the form large

9 simply is makes Simmias a large thing in comparison to Socrates. Why is x F? According to the Forms as Norms Reading, x is F because it conforms to norm F. To participate in form F is to conform to norm F. The Forms as Norms Reading, therefore, is fully compatible with the Structuring-Causes Reading. All structuring-causes are norms and all forms are both structuring-causes and norms. The Forms as Norms Reading, however, has the advantage of identifying what precisely a structuring-cause is in a way that makes the distinction between form and participant more clear. Forms are norms that exact a structure in their participants; 14 while participants are objects structured according to those norms. Since norms are neither causally nor ontologically dependent on the objects that conform to them, forms are neither causally nor ontologically dependent on their participants. Norms explain why the entities that conform to them are the way they are and norms are intelligible whether or not there are any spatio-temporal entities that conform to them. The Forms as Norms Reading, therefore, offers all the benefits of the Structuring-Causes Reading but does so with more clarity. 5. Causes as Norms in the First Sailing A further benefit of the Forms as Norms Reading is that it better connects the second sailing account of the forms to Socrates discussion of his first sailing that immediately precedes it. Of the various things he discusses while narrating his search for the causes of why things come to be, pass away, and are, the only things Socrates identifies as exhibiting genuine causality are intelligence (νοῦς), opinion (δόξα), and the forms. That the forms are causes is of course the central claim of the second sailing account (99d1 ff.). Yet immediately preceding his retelling of the second sailing, he also identifies intelligence as the cause of his decision to 14 Mitchell Miller suggested this way of wording things after hearing me present an earlier version of this essay.

10 sit in prison talking to his friends (98c-99b, esp. 99a8). Likewise, he claims that if he had held the opinion that escaping from prison was best, that opinion could have been the cause of his fleeing to Megara or Boeotia (99a1-2). Similarly, he discusses Anaxagoras cosmic Intelligence (νοῦς) as a candidate for genuine causality (97b8-99c8). Having already argued that the forms in the second sailing account are best understood as norms, I will now provide further support for the Forms as Norms Reading by showing that intelligence and opinion as Socrates presents them in his discussion of Anaxagoras are best understood as norms. While introducing the sort of causality he goes on to attribute to the forms, Socrates asks his interlocutors to consider the cause of his sitting in prison and talking to them. One sort of explanation for why he is sitting in prison is that he has bones and sinews that are arranged in a sitting position (98c2-d6). Socrates claims that this sort of explanation is absurd (99a4-5). He argues that bones and sinews are not the cause of his sitting in prison, but rather that without which the cause would not be able to act as a cause (99b3-4). He explains that the true cause of his sitting in prison is that he thought it was better, given his circumstances, to remain in prison and obey the laws of Athens, than to attempt an escape to another city (98d6-99b4). Crito had offered Socrates a chance to flee Athens. Socrates, however, decided to remain in prison, and, on the day of his execution, to sit and talk with his friends. He claims that his decision to remain was the best because it was made on the basis of intelligence (99a8; ταῦτα νῷ πράττων). 15 Intelligence, he believes, was the cause of his remaining in prison and is now the cause of his sitting and talking to his friends. In other words, intelligence or we could say reason itself is the norm that he believes is guiding his action. Since intelligence is the norm, the course of action he has chosen is the best (99a8-b1). Of course, intelligence is not the only possible cause 15 The νῷ at 99a8 is a causal dative. The way these things are done by intelligence parallels the way that all things are beautiful by the beautiful [itself] (τῷ καλῷ πάντα τὰ καλὰ καλά) at 100d7-8. For the use of causal datives in the second sailing passage see David Sedley, Platonic Causes, Phronesis 43, no. 2 (1998): 114 132.

11 of action. Mere opinion can be a cause as well. Socrates acknowledges he could long ago have been in Megara or among the Boeotians, carried there by the opinion that it was best (ὑπὸ δόξης φερόμενα τοῦ βελτίστου) (99e8-99a2). In that case, Socrates opinion that it was best to flee Athens would have been the norm guiding his action. Socrates account of his sitting in prison, therefore, represents the cause of deliberate action as the norm that guides it. In some cases that norm may be intelligence, while in other cases that norm may be a mere opinion. 16 Material conditions, such as bones and sinews, however, can never be the cause of deliberate actions. Rather they are only the conditions without which the norms dictating certain actions for example, sitting could not operate as norms. The way Socrates characterizes his response to hearing about Anaxagoras cosmic Intelligence further confirms that the sort of causes that interest him are norms. After recalling his dissatisfaction with various materialist accounts of causality, he tells how he was initially enthused when he heard someone reading a passage from Anaxagoras saying that it is Intelligence (νοῦς) that directs and is the cause of all things (97b8-c2). As we have seen in Socrates account of his sitting in prison, he characterizes intelligence as a norm that specifies what is best. When applied to the various courses of action one could take in a given situation, intelligence will specify which course of action is the best. On Socrates interpretation, Anaxagoras claim that Intelligence is the cause of all things amounts to the claim that all things conform to the norm that specifies what is best. Thus, from the claim that Intelligence is the cause of all things, Socrates infers that if one wished to know the cause of each thing... one had to find what was the best way for it to be (97c6-d1). If we understand intelligence as a norm that specifies what is best, the hypothesis that intelligence is the cause of all things is the 16 I am grateful to Paul DiRado for pointing out to me the distinction between the causality of intelligence and that of opinion in this passage.

12 hypothesis that all things conform to the norm that specifies what is best. Hence, if one, granting that hypothesis, wanted to show that a claim such as the earth is in the middle of the universe were true, one would show why it was best for the earth to be in the middle of the universe (97e3-98a1). From all this I think we should conclude that Socrates was originally excited about Anaxagoras because Socrates initially thought that by identifying Intelligence as the cause of all, Anaxagoras had, in contrast to the materialist philosophers, identified a norm as the cause of all. Anaxagoras cosmic Intelligence, the intelligence that guided Socrates decision to remain in prison, and the opinion that could have led him to attempt an escape are all best understood as norms. The Forms as Norms Reading, therefore, not only best explains the sort of causality attributed to the forms in the second sailing account, but also enables us to see Socrates employing a continuous notion of causality as he recounts his search for true causes, in both the first and second sailings of that search. 6. Conclusion The Forms as Norms Reading explains what is compelling in each of the other readings I discussed in this paper. Structures, considered apart from the entities that instantiate them, are norms. Since all structures are norms, the Forms as Norms Reading is fully compatible with and does all the work of the Structuring-Causes Reading. The Forms as Norms Reading, however, has the further benefit of highlighting that a structure apart from the entities that instantiate it is a norm. Moreover, it better connects the causes in the second sailing with those in the first. Similarly, the Forms as Norms Reading can explain what appeared plausible in the Logical Reading. According to the Logical Reading, x is F because it satisfies the definition of F. A definition of the sort Plato has in mind a real definition as opposed to a nominal one

13 identifies the norm that is the form being defined. Finally, the Forms as Norms Reading explains what seems at first blush plausible in the Property Reading. To have a property F is to conform to the norm that is the form F. Property F is conformity to norm F, and is unintelligible apart from norm F. The fact that a property is unintelligible apart from the norm to which it conforms is what sometimes leads people to want to reduce form to property, as is done in the Property Reading. Property F is different from form F, however, because form F is a norm, while property F is the conformity of an entity other than that norm to that norm.