Springer is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Theory and Society.

Similar documents
By Rahel Jaeggi Suhrkamp, 2014, pbk 20, ISBN , 451pp. by Hans Arentshorst

What counts as a convincing scientific argument? Are the standards for such evaluation

Sage Publications, Inc. is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Political Theory.

A Comprehensive Critical Study of Gadamer s Hermeneutics

Rethinking the Normative Content of Critical Theory

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at

Idealism and Pragmatism: "Transcendent" Validity Claims in Habermas's Democratic Theory

Conclusion. One way of characterizing the project Kant undertakes in the Critique of Pure Reason is by

Idealism and Pragmatism: Transcendent Validity Claims in Habermas s Democratic Theory

PRAGMATIZING CRITICAL THEORY S PROVINCE

Decolonizing Development Colonial Power and the Maya Edited by Joel Wainwright Copyright by Joel Wainwright. Conclusion

Lia Mela. Democritus University of Thrace. Keywords: modernity, reason, tradition, good, Frankfurt School, MacIntyre, Taylor

Critical Theory. Mark Olssen University of Surrey. Social Research at Frankfurt-am Main in The term critical theory was originally

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at

INTRODUCTION TO THE POLITICS OF SOCIAL THEORY

Adorno - The Tragic End. By Dr. Ibrahim al-haidari *

Habermas and the Project of Immanent Critique Titus Stahl

Habermas Discourse Ethics as the Foundation of Legitimate Laws

This is an electronic reprint of the original article. This reprint may differ from the original in pagination and typographic detail.

Kent Academic Repository

By way of an Introduction: These pages contain individual chapters from my 1990 book, Postmodern Sophistications. I have obtained the rights to the

A New Reflection on the Innovative Content of Marxist Theory Based on the Background of Political Reform Juanhui Wei

Brandom s Reconstructive Rationality. Some Pragmatist Themes

2 Rethinking the Communicative Turn

Chapter 2: Karl Marx Test Bank

Course Description. Alvarado- Díaz, Alhelí de María 1. The author of One Dimensional Man, Herbert Marcuse lecturing at the Freie Universität, 1968

Kimberly Hutchings Universalism in feminist international ethics: gender and the difficult labour of translation

Critical Political Economy of Communication and the Problem of Method

Social Theory Palmer 131C/Ext Sociology 334 Blocks 1-2/Fall 2009

PAUL REDDING S CONTINENTAL IDEALISM (AND DELEUZE S CONTINUATION OF THE IDEALIST TRADITION) Sean Bowden

A RE-INTERPRETATION OF ARTISTIC MODERNISM WITH EMPHASIS ON KANT AND NEWMAN DANNY SHORKEND

Kent Academic Repository

The Power of Ideas: Milton Friedman s Empirical Methodology

EPISTEMOLOGY, METHODOLOGY, AND THE SOCIAL SCIENCES

Towards a Conflict Theory of Recognition: On the Constitution of Relations of Recognition in Conflict

What is Postmodernism? What is Postmodernism?

Environmental Ethics: From Theory to Practice

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at

Kuhn Formalized. Christian Damböck Institute Vienna Circle University of Vienna

Critical Theory for Research on Librarianship (RoL)

Necessity in Kant; Subjective and Objective

Marx and Lukács: Reason and Revolution in the Philosophy of Praxis

A Letter from Louis Althusser on Gramsci s Thought

Theory or Theories? Based on: R.T. Craig (1999), Communication Theory as a field, Communication Theory, n. 2, May,

Hegel's Absolute: An Introduction to Reading the Phenomenology of Spirit

This thesis is protected by copyright which belongs to the author.

Philip Joseph Kain. Santa Clara University Scotts Valley, CA Santa Clara, CA fax

The Capitalist Unconscious Marx And Lacan

The Task of Dialectical Thinking in the Age of One-Dimensionality

Philosophy in the educational process: Understanding what cannot be taught

1) Review of Hall s Two Paradigms

KONSTANTINOS KAVOULAKOS. University of Crete

Theory or Theories? Based on: R.T. Craig (1999), Communication Theory as a field, Communication Theory, n. 2, May,

Sociology. Open Session on Answer Writing. (Session 2; Date: 7 July 2018) Topics. Paper I. 4. Sociological Thinkers (Karl Marx and Emile Durkheim)

Presented as part of the Colloquium Sponsored by the Lonergan Project at Marquette University on Lonergan s Philosophy and Theology

The Critical Turn in Education: From Marxist Critique to Poststructuralist Feminism to Critical Theories of Race

MARXIST LITERARY CRITICISM. Literary Theories

PH th Century Philosophy Ryerson University Department of Philosophy Mondays, 3-6pm Fall 2010

Marx, Gender, and Human Emancipation

Philosophy of History

UNIT SPECIFICATION FOR EXCHANGE AND STUDY ABROAD

Marxism and Education. Series Editor Anthony Green Institute of Education University of London London, United Kingdom

The Research on Habermas' Communicative Action Theory

postmodernism and he issues a sensible invitation to those who still don t

"History of Modern Economic Thought"

Imagination and Contingency: Overcoming the Problems of Kant s Transcendental Deduction

Theodor Adorno owes an immense debt to Immanuel Kant's Critique of Judgment. The major terms and categories of Adorno's aesthetics are informed by a

Louis Althusser s Centrism

Kant s Critique of Judgment

Normative and Positive Economics

Categories and Schemata

Review of Louis Althusser and the traditions of French Marxism

THE RELATIONS BETWEEN ETHICS AND ECONOMICS: A COMPARATIVE ANALYSIS BETWEEN AYRES AND WEBER S PERSPECTIVES. By Nuria Toledano and Crispen Karanda

There is a quaintness to Herbert Marcuse s manifesto on

1. Two very different yet related scholars

The phenomenological tradition conceptualizes

Lukács and the Dialectical Critique of Capitalism Moishe Postone

Claudio Corradetti The Frankfurt School and Critical Theory

An Analytical Approach to The Challenges of Cultural Relativism. The world is a conglomeration of people with many different cultures, each with

Mitchell ABOULAFIA, Transcendence. On selfdetermination

Hans-Georg Gadamer, Truth and Method, 2d ed. transl. by Joel Weinsheimer and Donald G. Marshall (London : Sheed & Ward, 1989), pp [1960].

Kuhn s Notion of Scientific Progress. Christian Damböck Institute Vienna Circle University of Vienna

210 Marcus Ohlström, Marco Solinas and Olivier Voirol

Todd Hedrick

Kant: Notes on the Critique of Judgment

CRITIQUE AS UNCERTAINTY

Marx: Overall Doctrine and Dynamics of Social Change

1. The Original Frankfurt School

Tradition and the Individual Poem: An Inquiry into Anthologies (review)

The topic of this Majors Seminar is Relativism how to formulate it, and how to evaluate arguments for and against it.

Critical Theory, Poststructuralism and the Philosophy of Liberation. By Douglas Kellner (

A: Knowledge of and Understanding

M E M O. When the book is published, the University of Guelph will be acknowledged for their support (in the acknowledgements section of the book).

Writing an Honors Preface

Introduction. Normative scepticism

IDEALISM WITHOUT LIMITS

Deconstruction is a way of understanding how something was created and breaking something down into smaller parts.

The Path Choice of the Chinese Communist Party's Theoretical Innovation under the Perspective of Chinese Traditional Culture

Herbert Marcuse. Douglas Kellner (

Transcription:

Rhetorical Affects and Critical Intentions: A Response to Ben Gregg Author(s): Seyla Benhabib Reviewed work(s): Source: Theory and Society, Vol. 16, No. 1 (Jan., 1987), pp. 153-158 Published by: Springer Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/657082. Accessed: 30/11/2011 17:35 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at. http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org. Springer is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Theory and Society. http://www.jstor.org

153 Rhetorical affects and critical intentions A response to Ben Gregg SEYLA BENHABIB Harvard University In the mid-1970s at the height of the so-called "terrorist hunt" West German conservatives argued that Critical Theory from Horkheimer to Habermas was indirectly responsible for political terrorism because it corroded the rationality and legitimacy of existing society through its doctrines. The opponents of critical theory made it seem as if an unbroken logic led from rational criticism to political violence and terror. If I am not mistaken, in our days Critical Theory is accused of a new kind of terrorism - the "terrorism" of reason and of the rational. This kind of terrorism need not resort to action and to violence against things and persons to make its point. According to postmodernists like Richard Rorty and Jean-Fransois Lyotard, the privileging of one language-game over others, the articulation of a "grand narrative" of modernity and Enlightenment, the insistence that critical thought reveal the normative principles in the name of which it speaks, are instances of the terrorism of the rational. Such a rationality does not allow the heteronomous, the discontinuous, the agonistic, in short, the diverse language-games and their small narratives to remain as they are and to enjoy their proper legitimacy. Ben Gregg is certainly no postmodernist critic of critical theory and of Habermas. However, his assumption that any defense of the paradigm shift in critical theory from instrumental to communicative reason does "violence" to the Hegelian-Marxist tradition and to early critical theory is reminiscent of recent postmodernist denunciations of the terror of the rational. Gregg's major discontent with my treatment of this paradigm shift is indicated by the rhetorical subtitle of his review: "Must a History of Philosophy be a Philosophy of History?" He identifies the "violence" that such a philosophy of history does to its object as follows: "The main Theory and Society 16: 153-158 (1987)? Martinus Nijhoff Publishers, Dordrecht - Printed in the Netherlands

154 weakness of Critique, Norm and Utopia should by now be clear: it tends toward being a Geschichtsphilosophie with Habermas as the immanent telos of critical normative philosophy since Hegel." If this were indeed the case, if my presentation of the tradition of critical theory triumphed with Habermas at the end as the new "World Spirit on horseback," Gregg would be correct. The terrorism of the rational would then consist in viewing past developments in the critical Marxist tradition as so many paths leading to Habermas's triumphant march. But this is a serious misrepresentation of my intentions in Critique, Norm and Utopia - serious enough indeed to have occasioned this response. Gregg can accuse me of presenting the history of theories as a cryptophilosophy of history because he confuses the method of presentation I follow with substantive assumptions about the philosophy of history that I denounce. At the beginning of his review Gregg identifies my methodology as "the presentation of the history of theories from a systematic point of view," and describes this procedure as "the reconstruction of continuities and breaks in the 'evolution' of theories within a given intellectual tradition... toward identifying systematic problems and developing alternative strategies to overcome its immanent problems, rescuing a thinker's intentions, now reinterpreted, from a framework precluding their realization." Although this is a fair characterization of the method of presentation I follow, the phrase the "'evolution' of theories," can be - and I think in Gregg's case has been - seriously misleading. Such evolution would imply that traditions of thought were more continuous and homogeneous than they in fact are, and that a later theory is in some sense an "advance" or an improvement over an "earlier" one. Although I believe that "learning processes" in some weak sense take place in theoretical traditions (Critical Theorists have learned from Marx's critique of Hegel), and that a future theory, because it attempts to surpass the mistakes of the earlier ones, can register a gain in rationality in this respect (Habermas's treatment of the problem of ethics, when compared to Horkheimer and Adorno, involves such a learning process), my goal in Critique, Norm and Utopia was not to argue that Hegel and Marx, Adorno and Horkheimer were theorists of communicative rationality malgre' eux. My aim was not to place these thinkers along an evolutionary continuum in some Popperian "third world" (would it not be silly to argue that just because it is later in time Negative Dialectics surpasses the Phenomenology of Spirit?), but to show the existence of tensions, problems, and aporias in their thought resulting from their subscription to the work model of action and the philosophy of the subject. As I note in the introduction, "From Marx to Horkheimer, the vi-

155 sion of a demiurge-like mankind, producing externality, unfolding its capacities in this process, and destined to emancipation by appropriating its own alienated forces, dominates... In Hegel's critique of Kantian moral philosophy, in Marx's emphasis on concrete, sensuous finitude and individuals in social relations, and in Adorno's critique of identity philosophies, one can discover traces of a more intersubjectively oriented and pluralistic conception of self, society, and politics. To develop the full implications of these scattered elements and insights, however, the shortcomings of the work model of action and of the philosophy of the subject must be seen more clearly." Because my purpose was to reveal the tension between these various strands in the tradition of Critical Theory from Hegel to Habermas, and to play off against the philosophy of the subject aspects of a more intersubjectively centered and pluralistic conception of self, society, and politics, I myself characterized this method through the model of Gadamerian dialogue, and warned explicitly at the beginning of my interpretation of Habermas in chapter seven against the teleological and evolutionary history of theories that Gregg accuses me of following (cf. 224-225). "The reconstruction of the history of theories," I write in the preface, "proceeds like a dialogue in which one asks a question, seeks to comprehend whether this question is meaningful to the other, listens and reformulates the answer of the other, and in light of this answer rearticulates one's original position. It is in this spirit that I have approached the problem of the normative foundations of critical theory" (x). Admittedly, there is a distinction between the intentions of an author and their execution or concretization. It is up to the readers to judge whether in this respect Critique, Norm and Utopia has been successful in upholding the model of dialogue it evokes. It is the critic's responsibility, however, to inform the reader of an author's intentions and to distinguish them from his own evaluation of the author's success or failure in their execution. That Gregg fails in this task, that he cannot distinguish between his largely negative evaluation of the Habermasian program and my own analysis of the paradigm shift in critical theory, is indicated by the following: the concepts of "norm" and "utopia" that figure in the title of the book and that describe the two visions of politics and emancipation between which critical theorists vacillate are not mentioned by Gregg at all. But the major argument in Critique, Norm and Utopia is that while the "politics of fulfillment" (norm) continues the universalist promise of

156 bourgeois revolutions in demanding justice, equality, civil rights, democracy, and publicity, the "politics of transfiguration" (utopia) continues the tradition of early socialist, communitarian, and anarchist movements seeking qualitatively new relations among self, nature, and others. After establishing the presence of both visions of emancipatory politics in Marx's work, I argue that Habermas's "paradigm shift" in critical theory emphasizes the politics of fulfillment at the risk of repressing the moment of utopia or transfiguration.' I would like to think that this critique of the loss of the utopian dimension of earlier Critical Theory does not only amount to a "small change" in the Habermasian paradigm as Gregg suggests. For some time now, sympathetic critics of Habermas have been forming what Joel Whitebook has aptly described as a "loyal opposition." Like Albrecht Wellmer, Thomas McCarthy, and Richard Bernstein, I see a tension between the transcendental and the historically and contextually situated aspects of Habermas's thought. The cost, however, of becoming overly transcendental, in my opinion, is not only epistemic or methodological, but also normative and political. The dominance of the transcendental approach represses the utopian moment in Critical Theory. This utopian perspective proceeds from our finite, historical, and embodied existence to project moments of solidarity and happiness among "concrete others," and does not rest satisfied with the vision of reciprocal recognition among the abstract, "generalized others" of transcendental reason. Because he misjudges the extent to which I want to save the utopian intentions of early Critical Theory and to criticize Habermas in their light, Gregg also misevaluates my interpretation of new social movements. First, he accuses me of deviating from Habermas's views (as if this were a criticism); second, he maintains that in my scheme new social movements become the new "subject" of history. While the first point is one that I myself address, the second is simply false. I state very clearly at several points in the text (233 ff; 251), that I doubt whether the theory of the "colonization of the lifeworld" alone can explain the rise and significance of new social movements. Habermas fails to appreciate that groups organized in peace, ecology, women's, alternative, and other movements are not only or even primarily defending the lifeworld against capitalism and bureaucracy but that they are also creating new principles of politics, and putting the systems of power and money on the defensive. (The success of neoconservativism in the last number of years, I would argue, is not evidence to the contrary, because neoconservatives defend what they take to be corroding under the attack of these

157 movements plus the damaging ideology of the "adversary intellegentsia.") I characterize this new political principle as the creation of a "community of needs and solidarity." That I see these movements as careers of a utopian promise by no means suggests that I see them as the solution to the riddle of history. One of the most interesting aspects of these movements is their self-limiting character; unlike the bourgeois and workers' movements of the last century, they do not speak in the name of the social totality, but are aware of "difference" and regard this as a positive moment. By contrast, the philosophy of the subject always searches for a particular group, be it the working class, the Third World, women, and the Party whose particularity would represent universality. New social movements, or at least the non-fundamentalists among them, are aware that there is no single spot in the social structure that privileges those who occupy it with a vision of the social totality, and that this is not lamentable. Gregg is simply wrong therefore in his claim that for me these new social movements replace the revolutionary subject in the traditional philosophy of the subject. What we learn from these movements is that there is no unified subject of history, but that there are at the most different, struggling collectivities, grouped around eminently fragile and revisable normative conceptions of identity, self-limiting but experimental and inspirational in their search for new ways of interacting with inner and outer nature, new ways of organizing our living and public spaces, and new ways of conceptualizing and living in peace and security. Whether the paradigm shift from the critique of instrumental reason to that of communicative rationality in Critical Theory will allow us to conceptualize the "newness" of these movements better, as well as delivering us normative standards in light of which to judge them, is a question I leave open in my book. It seems clear to me that there are compelling reasons of a theoretical and political nature at the present to endorse this paradigm shift in critical theory, while strengthening those moments of situated and contextual critique against transcendental flights from the concrete. We have to remember the lessons of Enlightenment universalism without forgetting those utopian aspirations of the past that have failed. The purpose of Critique, Norm and Utopia is to argue that a critical social theory of the present is only viable insofar as it can do justice both to norm and to utopia. My aim certainly was not, as Gregg suggests, to write a panegyric suggesting that the theory program of a single individual was the implicit telos of an entire tradition.

158 Notes 1. Cf. however the essay on "Die Krise des Wohlfahrtstaates und die Erschopfung utopischer Energien" in Die Neue Unubersichtlichkeit (Frankfurt: Suhrkamp, 1985) 141-167; English translation by Phillips Jacobs in Philosophy and Social Criticism as "The New Obscurity," which was published after my book had gone to press, and in which Habermas himself laments the exhaustion of utopian energies in the welfare state. This essay indicates that many of the criticisms I raise about the absence of utopia in Habermas's thought is a concern he himself has felt the need to address in recent years.