Art and Morality. Sebastian Nye LECTURE 2. Autonomism and Ethicism

Similar documents
An autonomist view on the ethical criticism of architecture

Film-Philosophy

PHI 3240: Philosophy of Art

MODERATE MORALISM. Noel Carroll I. INTRODUCTION

Rational Agency and Normative Concepts by Geoffrey Sayre-McCord UNC/Chapel Hill [for discussion at the Research Triangle Ethics Circle] Introduction

The Ethical Criticism of Art: A New Mapping of the Territory

On Criticisms of Art: Subjective Interest as a Link between Ethics and

MODERATE AUTONOMISM. James C. Anderson and Jeffrey T. Dean

Formal Properties as the Basis for Value in Music

Simulated killing. Michael Lacewing

On Art, Morality, and the Subject: Revisiting the Relation between Ethics and Aesthetics By Kévin-Orly Irakóze (Connecticut College)

PHI 3240: Philosophy of Art

POST-KANTIAN AUTONOMIST AESTHETICS AS APPLIED ETHICS ETHICAL SUBSTRATUM OF PURIST LITERARY CRITICISM IN 20 TH CENTURY

In this essay, I criticise the arguments made in Dickie's article The Myth of the Aesthetic

6AANA034 Aesthetics Syllabus Academic year 2016/17. Module description. Assessment methods and deadlines

Immoralism and the Valence Constraint. James Harold

Does the ethical criticism of art make sense?

PHI 3240: Philosophy of Art

0 The work does not reach a standard described by the descriptors below.

Emotions from the Perspective of Analytic Aesthetics

In his essay "Of the Standard of Taste," Hume describes an apparent conflict between two

Visual Arts Colorado Sample Graduation Competencies and Evidence Outcomes

Moral and Aesthetic Virtue ALISON HILLS THE ARISTOTELIAN SOCIETY PROCEEDINGS OF SENATE HOUSE UNIVERSITY OF LONDON THE WOBURN SUITE

What do our appreciation of tonal music and tea roses, our acquisition of the concepts

PHL 317K 1 Fall 2017 Overview of Weeks 1 5

that would join theoretical philosophy (metaphysics) and practical philosophy (ethics)?

Why Pleasure Gains Fifth Rank: Against the Anti-Hedonist Interpretation of the Philebus 1

Kant: Notes on the Critique of Judgment

Issue 5, Summer Published by the Durham University Undergraduate Philosophy Society

UNIT SPECIFICATION FOR EXCHANGE AND STUDY ABROAD

Bad Art and Good Taste

Nicomachean Ethics. p. 1. Aristotle. Translated by W. D. Ross. Book II. Moral Virtue (excerpts)

Sight and Sensibility: Evaluating Pictures Mind, Vol April 2008 Mind Association 2008

Humanities Learning Outcomes

The Confluence of Aesthetics and Hermeneutics in Baumgarten, Meier, and Kant

Hume s Sentimentalism: What Not Who Should Have The Final Word Elisabeth Schellekens

An Intense Defence of Gadamer s Significance for Aesthetics

Internal assessment details SL and HL

International Journal of Advancements in Research & Technology, Volume 4, Issue 11, November ISSN

Sidestepping the holes of holism

Aesthetic Formalism, Reactions and Solutions

Sentimentalism and the Intersubjectivity of Aesthetic Evaluations

PHILOSOPHY. Grade: E D C B A. Mark range: The range and suitability of the work submitted

AESTHETIC ATTENTION: A PROPOSAL TO PAY IT MORE ATTENTION

Spectrum Arguments: Objections and Replies Part I. Different Kinds and Sorites Paradoxes

Goldie on the Virtues of Art

An aristotelian account of autonomy

HISTORY ADMISSIONS TEST. Marking Scheme for the 2015 paper

Robert Solomon s Rejection of Aristotelian Virtue: Is the Passion of Erotic Love a Virtue that is Independent of Rationality?

Another Look at Imoral Art

Conclusion. One way of characterizing the project Kant undertakes in the Critique of Pure Reason is by

ener How N AICE: G OT t (8004) o Argue Paper

FUNCTIONAL BEAUTY, ARCHITECTURE, AND MORALITY: A BEAUTIFUL KONZENTRATIONSLAGER?

Review of Carolyn Korsmeyer, Savoring Disgust: The foul and the fair. in aesthetics (Oxford University Press pp (PBK).

Realism and Representation: The Case of Rembrandt s

Directions: Choose the word that is most nearly opposite in meaning to the word in capital letters.

High School Photography 1 Curriculum Essentials Document

David Davies. Aesthetics and Literature. London & New York: Continuum, 2007, 212 pp. ISBN

Logic and argumentation techniques. Dialogue types, rules

The Strengths and Weaknesses of Frege's Critique of Locke By Tony Walton

Theories of Right Action & Their Critics

Student Learning Assessment for ART 100 Katie Frank

SQA Advanced Unit specification. General information for centres. Unit title: Philosophical Aesthetics: An Introduction. Unit code: HT4J 48

National Standards for Visual Art The National Standards for Arts Education

Image and Imagination

Normative Dualism and the Definition of Art

English Literature Unit 4360

SAMPLE COURSE OUTLINE PHILOSOPHY AND ETHICS GENERAL YEAR 12

Cliffhangers are a common plot device in works of narrative fiction. A work or one of its

Sentimentalism and the Intersubjectivity of Aesthetic Evaluations

Are There Two Theories of Goodness in the Republic? A Response to Santas. Rachel Singpurwalla

AESTHETICS. Students will appreciate the variety of human experiences as expressed through the arts.

Poetics by Aristotle, 350 B.C. Contents... Chapter 2. The Objects of Imitation Chapter 7. The Plot must be a Whole

1/8. The Third Paralogism and the Transcendental Unity of Apperception

At the Limit: Violence and Contemporary Representation Guidelines for Final Paper, p. 1. Eugenie Brinkema

By Rahel Jaeggi Suhrkamp, 2014, pbk 20, ISBN , 451pp. by Hans Arentshorst

Virtues o f Authenticity: Essays on Plato and Socrates Republic Symposium Republic Phaedrus Phaedrus), Theaetetus

Strategies for Writing about Literature (from A Short Guide to Writing about Literature, Barnett and Cain)

A Comprehensive Critical Study of Gadamer s Hermeneutics

Marx, Gender, and Human Emancipation

1/10. The A-Deduction

Lecture 11: Anthropocentrism

Philosophy of Mind and Metaphysics Lecture III: Qualitative Change and the Doctrine of Temporal Parts

Open-ended Questions for Advanced Placement English Literature and Composition,

Definition / Explination reference to a statement, a place or person or events from: literature, history, religion, mythology, politics, sports

228 International Journal of Ethics.

The Embedding Problem for Non-Cognitivism; Introduction to Cognitivism; Motivational Externalism

Art: What it Is and Why it Matters Catharine Abell Published in Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, Vol. 85, No. 3, pp

Claim: refers to an arguable proposition or a conclusion whose merit must be established.

The Success of Sophisticated Formalism in Modern Pop Music. Abby Swoboda

Rob van Gerwen. Ethical Autonomism. The work of art as a Moral Agent

Types of perceptual content

Open-ended Questions for Advanced Placement English Literature and Composition,

Affect, perceptual experience, and disclosure

Aesthetic properties in Allen Carlson s theory for the appreciation of nature: Focusing on the functions of categories

Guide to the Republic as it sets up Plato s discussion of education in the Allegory of the Cave.

September 10. Fiction. Andrew Goldstone CA: Octavio R. Gonzalez

On Defining Art Historically

Resemblance Nominalism: A Solution to the Problem of Universals. GONZALO RODRIGUEZ-PEREYRA. Oxford: Clarendon Press, Pp. xii, 238.

A Moorean View of the Value of Lives. Kris McDaniel Forthcoming in Pacific Philosophical Quarterly

Transcription:

Art and Morality Sebastian Nye sjn42@cam.ac.uk LECTURE 2 Autonomism and Ethicism Answers to the ethical question The Ethical Question: Does the ethical value of a work of art contribute to its aesthetic or artistic value, and if so how? Autonomism the ethical value of an artwork is irrelevant to its aesthetic/artistic value. Ethicism the ethical value of an artwork does affect its aesthetic/artistic value; ethical value can enhance the aesthetic/artistic value of a work, and ethical disvalue can diminish it. Contextualism the ethical value of an artwork does affect its aesthetic/artistic value; but the nature of the connection varies in different contexts. Contra ethicism, sometimes ethical features are an aesthetic/artistic defect, and sometimes unethical features enhance the aesthetic/artistic value. For alternative taxonomies see: Schellekens, Aesthetics and Morality; Levinson, Introduction: Aesthetics and Ethics, in Levinson ed., Aesthetics and Ethics: Essays at the Intersection; Gaut, Art, Emotion and Ethics, pp.9-14; Carroll, Art and Ethical Criticism. Arguments for autonomism 1. The common denominator argument See: Carroll, Art and Ethical Criticism, and also Gaut, Art, Emotion and Ethics, p.67. - Any criterion for evaluating an artwork must be applicable to all artworks ( art should be beholden to standards universally applicable to all art Carroll, Art and Ethical Criticism p.352) - Ethical criticism is not applicable to all artworks; pure orchestral music and abstract visual designs are artworks, but cannot be ethically evaluated (Carroll, Art and Ethical Criticism, p.352) - So ethical criticism is inappropriate. This is obviously a terrible argument: - The first premise is not very plausible. There is no general reason to think that the criteria for evaluating something must be generally applicable. Moreover, it doesn t 1

seem specifically plausible in the case of art surely we should use different criteria for evaluating the Sex Pistols, the Egyptian Pyramids and Rembrandt s Girl Sleeping (Carroll, Art and Ethical Criticism, pp.357-358). - Carroll claims that the second premise is an undeniable fact (Carroll, Art and Ethical Criticism, p.352). But recall Adorno s claims about music, discussed last week. 2. The incomprehensibility argument An autonomist could argue that the ethical value of an artwork is irrelevant simply because it is impossible to make sense of the idea that an artwork has ethical value. (Cf. Oscar Wilde s much-quoted quip: There is no such thing as a moral or immoral book. Books are well written or badly written. That is all. ) The most plausible way to defend this claim is to argue that ethical assessment only makes sense when attributed to agents. So although we may condemn Nabokov as immoral for writing Lolita, it makes no sense to condemn Lolita itself for being immoral. (For a discussion of a similar argument, see Gaut, Art, Emotion and Ethics, pp.69-76). Compare with the debate about expression in music (see: Matravers, Art and Emotion; Levinson, Musical Expressiveness ; Davies, Artistic Expression and the Hard Case of Pure Music ). Two difficulties: - We often seem to use moral language to praise or condemn things other than agents, e.g. the bedroom tax is evil. Of course, these too could be merely metaphorical uses, but that s at least not obvious. - There seem to be many ways to make sense of the idea that artworks have ethical value, which we looked at last week. Many of these seem, on the face of it, relatively commonsensical. 3. The aesthetic argument A more hopeful argument: - Aesthetic value should be understood in terms of aesthetic experience, which in turn should be understood as disinterested experience. (This way of thinking about aesthetics is often associated with Kant. For further discussion see: Kant, The Analytic and the Beautiful in The Critique of Judgement; Beardsley, The Aesthetic Experience in his The Aesthetic Point of View: Selected Essays; Dickie, The Myth of the Aesthetic Attitude.) - Artistic value should be understood in terms of aesthetic value (i.e, a work is artistically valuable to the extent that it produces a disinterested aesthetic experience). - Insofar as we engage with the ethical content of an artwork, we are not engaging with it disinterestedly. - Therefore, a work s ethical value is irrelevant to its aesthetic/artistic value. 2

Ways of criticizing this argument: - Deny that the notion of disinterestedness underlies an appropriate characterization of the aesthetic experience. - Deny that aesthetic experience whether or not it is bound up with disinterestedness should underscore our understanding of aesthetic or artistic value. - Deny that appropriate characterization of ethical value, on the one hand, and disinterestedness, on the other, excludes the possibility that we can engage with ethical value in a way that is disinterested. 4. The negative approach An autonomist might argue that, even if there is no good positive reason to think that the ethical value of an artwork is always aesthetically/artistically irrelevant, there is simply no reason to think that the ethical value is aesthetically/artistically irrelevant. If correct, this is a perfectly plausible way to defend autonomism. Establishing it, however, depends upon looking at the arguments for ethicism and contextualism and finding them wanting. Arguments for ethicism 1. The moral beauty argument One argument, offered by Gaut, is as follows: - Artworks that are moral are so in virtue of having a manifested author with morally virtuous traits. Similarly, artworks that are immoral are so in virtue of having a manifested author with vicious traits. - If a character trait is morally virtuous, then it is beautiful; if a character trait is immoral, then it is ugly (see Gaut, Art, Emotion and Ethics, p.120). - If a trait is beautiful, then it has positive aesthetic value; if a trait is ugly, then it has negative aesthetic value. - Therefore, if a work is moral, it is to that extent more beautiful; and if an artwork is immoral, it is to that extent more ugly. Note: by manifested author or artist, Gaut simply means the artist to whom we attribute qualities that are present in the artwork. He says: Criticisms: The manifested artist is ascribed the qualities that are possessed by the artistic acts performed in the work. The manifested artist is, then, the artist as manifested in the artist acts performed in the work. (Gaut, Art, Emotion and Ethics, p.72) - It could be argued that Gaut has an implausible understanding of the ethical value of an artwork. See alternatives from last week s lecture. - Why think that moral virtues are beautiful and vices ugly? Gaut s argument for this basically consists of the observation that sometimes the language of beauty is used to 3

describe virtuous people. But by itself this certainly doesn t seem sufficient to motivate such a strong claim about the affinity between these two evaluative categories. (For his argument, see Gaut, Art, Emotion and Ethics, pp. 114-127). - Even if there is a sense in which moral traits are beautiful, it doesn t follow that this is the same sense in which we use beauty as a term of aesthetic praise. - Consider the third premise: If a trait is beautiful, then has positive aesthetic value; if a trait is ugly, then it has negative aesthetic value. It could be argued that (a) it is straight-forwardly false, sometimes ugly things can have positive aesthetic value or (b) although beauty is an aesthetic value, this does not mean that it is a better artwork. 2. The merited response argument An argument that has various slightly different formulations. I will outline the most discussed version from Gaut (see Gaut, Art, Emotion and Ethics pp.227-252). - Artworks often prescribe certain responses. - If the response that is prescribed by an artwork is unmerited, then that is a failure of the artwork. It is, to some extent, less aesthetically and artistically valuable. - Unethical prescribed responses are always unmerited. This is because it reflects badly on us if we engage with the immoral features of artworks, so we have a reason not to do so. Gaut says: I can criticize someone for taking pleasure in others pain, for being amused by sadistic cruelty, for being angry at someone who has done no wrong, for desiring the bad. The same is true when responses are directed at fictional events, for these responses are actual, not just imagined ones (Gaut, Art, Emotion and Ethics, p.231). - Therefore, ethical defects are aesthetic/artistic defects. This establishes negative part of the ethicists claim, i.e. that ethical disvalue lessens aesthetic/artistic value. Gaut also thinks that a parallel argument can be offered to support the positive claim that ethical value enhances a work of art (see Gaut, Art, Emotion and Ethics, p.233). Criticisms - It is not obvious that unmerited responses necessarily constitute aesthetic/artistic defects. Can something be a failure in its own terms but nonetheless a success? - Is it true that it reflects badly on me if I fictionally engage with an immoral artwork? Some argue that this is too puritanical. - It could be argued that engaging with immoral artworks does indeed reflect badly on you, but only if you do it for the wrong reason. Engaging with immoral artworks in order to gain insight into an immoral world-view from the inside, thus enabling more sophisticated engagement with and criticism of that world-view, might be a good reason to engage with them. 4

3. The distraction argument Finally, an argument from Noel Carroll (see Carroll, Moderate Moralism ): - If a feature of a work distracts the audience from engaging with work in the intended way (as Carroll sometimes puts it, if it failures to secure uptake ), then that feature is an aesthetic defect. This is because it constitutes a failure of the work on its own terms. - Immoral features of an artwork at least sometimes distract audiences in this sense, and so immoral features of a work are (at least sometimes) aesthetic defects. He uses the example of American Psycho: The author intended it as a satire on the rapacious eighties in the USA. He presented a serial killer as the symbol of the vaunted securities marketeer of Reagonomics. However, the serial killings depicted in the novel are so graphically brutal that readers are not able to get past the gore in order to savour the parody that defect was an aesthetic defect, inasmuch as it compromised the novel on its own terms. (Carroll, Moderate Moralism, p.232) Criticisms: - As we saw above, it is not obvious that we can move from the claim that an artwork is a failure on its own terms to the claim that an artwork is a failure. - American Psycho doesn t seem to be a very good example since (a) it is often held up as one of the great modern novels, rather than a failure, and (b) it is unclear whether what is distracting is the immoral content or the grossness. - Even if people are distracted by the content of American Psycho, this might seem to be a rare case. So, at best, this argument is very limited. Carroll shifts from the actual responses of audiences of an artwork, to the hypothetical responses of morally sensitive persons: Movies that thrilled people may come to disgust them morally. And even if they do not disgust the majority of viewers, the films are still flawed, inasmuch as they remain likely to fail to engender the planned response in morally sensitive viewers. (Carroll, Moderate Moralism, p.233) But why should we care about the perhaps merely hypothetical reactions of morally sensitive viewers? - It could be argued that when readers find American Psycho distracting, the fault lies with them, not with American Psycho. Aesthetic merit should be determined by the judgement of a (perhaps idealized) critic who has a strong stomach, and an ability to enter dark places. If you fall short of that, then it is you who is at fault not the artwork. This claim lines up with some of the arguments for contextualism, to be explored next week. 5