Pragmatism and Experience in Contemporary Debates

Similar documents
Today I raise a simple question: which term, experience" or language, best. expresses the central motivation of pragmatism? Which would you choose?

Brandom s Reconstructive Rationality. Some Pragmatist Themes

Undercutting the Realism-Irrealism Debate: John Dewey and the Neo-Pragmatists

HEGEL, ANALYTIC PHILOSOPHY AND THE RETURN OF METAPHYISCS Simon Lumsden

Action, Criticism & Theory for Music Education

PAUL REDDING S CONTINENTAL IDEALISM (AND DELEUZE S CONTINUATION OF THE IDEALIST TRADITION) Sean Bowden

What counts as a convincing scientific argument? Are the standards for such evaluation

A Comprehensive Critical Study of Gadamer s Hermeneutics

What Difference Can Experience Make to Pragmatism?

What Can Experimental Philosophy Do? David Chalmers

observation and conceptual interpretation

The Self as an Object of Criticism: Richard Rorty s Denial of the Objectivity of Truth. Do Kien Trung, Kobe University, Japan

The topic of this Majors Seminar is Relativism how to formulate it, and how to evaluate arguments for and against it.

Swindal, James. Action and Existence: The Case for Agent Causation. New York: Palgrave Macmillan, 2012.

Bas C. van Fraassen, Scientific Representation: Paradoxes of Perspective, Oxford University Press, 2008.

Kant, Peirce, Dewey: on the Supremacy of Practice over Theory

Philosophy of Science: The Pragmatic Alternative April 2017 Center for Philosophy of Science University of Pittsburgh ABSTRACTS

Interpretive and Critical Research Traditions

that would join theoretical philosophy (metaphysics) and practical philosophy (ethics)?

Phenomenology and Non-Conceptual Content

COPYRIGHT 2009 ASSOCIAZIONE PRAGMA

UNIT SPECIFICATION FOR EXCHANGE AND STUDY ABROAD

Creative Actualization: A Meliorist Theory of Values

Conclusion. One way of characterizing the project Kant undertakes in the Critique of Pure Reason is by

Rorty, Dewey, and Incommensurability

Mitchell ABOULAFIA, Transcendence. On selfdetermination

PRAGMATIST METAETHICS

Arnold I. Davidson, Frédéric Gros (eds.), Foucault, Wittgenstein: de possibles rencontres (Éditions Kimé, 2011), ISBN:

Sidestepping the holes of holism

TRAGIC THOUGHTS AT THE END OF PHILOSOPHY

SUMMARY BOETHIUS AND THE PROBLEM OF UNIVERSALS

The Pragmatic Turn, by Richard J. Bernstein. Cambridge: Polity, 2010,, The Pragmatic Turn, Polity, Cambridge Malden 2010, xi pp.

BOOK REVIEW: JOHN DEWEY BETWEEN PRAGMATISM RECONSTRUCTING DEMOCRACY, RECONTEXTUALIZING DEWEY: PRAGMATISM AND INTERACTIVE CONSTRUCTIVISM

Confines of Democracy

Situated actions. Plans are represetitntiom of nction. Plans are representations of action

Ithaque : Revue de philosophie de l'université de Montréal

The Strengths and Weaknesses of Frege's Critique of Locke By Tony Walton

Current Issues in Pictorial Semiotics

CRITICAL CONTEXTUAL EMPIRICISM AND ITS IMPLICATIONS

REFERENCES. 2004), that much of the recent literature in institutional theory adopts a realist position, pos-

Introduction and Overview

Harris Wiseman, The Myth of the Moral Brain: The Limits of Moral Enhancement (Cambridge, MA and London: The MIT Press, 2016), 340 pp.

Richard Rorty s Pragmatism

Anne Freadman, The Machinery of Talk: Charles Peirce and the Sign Hypothesis (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 2004), pp. xxxviii, 310.

What Is Wrong with Dewey s Theory of Knowing

Edward Winters. Aesthetics and Architecture. London: Continuum, 2007, 179 pp. ISBN

Practical Intuition and Rhetorical Example. Paul Schollmeier

Università della Svizzera italiana. Faculty of Communication Sciences. Master of Arts in Philosophy 2017/18

PHILOSOPHY OF SOCIAL SCIENCE INTS 4522 Spring Jack Donnelly and Martin Rhodes -

Humanities Learning Outcomes

By Rahel Jaeggi Suhrkamp, 2014, pbk 20, ISBN , 451pp. by Hans Arentshorst

KINDS (NATURAL KINDS VS. HUMAN KINDS)

Pragmatism as transition. Historicity and Hope in James, Dewey, and Rorty, Columbia University Press, New York, 2009

The Human Intellect: Aristotle s Conception of Νοῦς in his De Anima. Caleb Cohoe

SocioBrains THE INTEGRATED APPROACH TO THE STUDY OF ART

PHILOSOPHY OF EDUCATION

Moral Judgment and Emotions

Truth and Method in Unification Thought: A Preparatory Analysis

COURSE SYLLABUS. 1. Information about the programme

Book Review. John Dewey s Philosophy of Spirit, with the 1897 Lecture on Hegel. Jeff Jackson. 130 Education and Culture 29 (1) (2013):

Media as practice. a brief exchange. Nick Couldry and Mark Hobart. Published as Chapter 3. Theorising Media and Practice

WILLIAM JAMES STUDIES VOLUME 14 NUMBER 1 SPRING 2018 PP

UNIT SPECIFICATION FOR EXCHANGE AND STUDY ABROAD

James SCOTT JOHNSTON, John Dewey s Earlier Logical Theory

Scientific Philosophy

REVIEW ARTICLE IDEAL EMBODIMENT: KANT S THEORY OF SENSIBILITY

RORTY AND BRANDOM: PRAGMATISM AND THE ONTOLOGICAL PRIORITY

Heideggerian Ontology: A Philosophic Base for Arts and Humanties Education

Reply to Stalnaker. Timothy Williamson. In Models and Reality, Robert Stalnaker responds to the tensions discerned in Modal Logic

(1) Writing Essays: An Overview. Essay Writing: Purposes. Essay Writing: Product. Essay Writing: Process. Writing to Learn Writing to Communicate

Kęstas Kirtiklis Vilnius University Not by Communication Alone: The Importance of Epistemology in the Field of Communication Theory.

Truth and Tropes. by Keith Lehrer and Joseph Tolliver

Action Theory for Creativity and Process

What do our appreciation of tonal music and tea roses, our acquisition of the concepts

Mixed Methods: In Search of a Paradigm

High School Photography 1 Curriculum Essentials Document

Visual Argumentation in Commercials: the Tulip Test 1

Normative Engagement Across Difference: A Pragmatic Social-Practice Based Perspective

Philip Kitcher and Gillian Barker, Philosophy of Science: A New Introduction, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2014, pp. 192

Social Semiotic Techniques of Sense Making using Activity Theory

Published in: International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 29(2) (2015):

TROUBLING QUALITATIVE INQUIRY: ACCOUNTS AS DATA, AND AS PRODUCTS

LeBar s Flaccidity: Is there Cause for Concern?

Penultimate draft of a review which will appear in History and Philosophy of. $ ISBN: (hardback); ISBN:

French theories in IS research : An exploratory study on ICIS, AMCIS and MISQ

Pragmatism, neo-pragmatism and sociocultural theory Communicative participation as a perspective in LIS

1. situation (or community) 2. substance (content) and style (form)

Prephilosophical Notions of Thinking

Emotion, an Organ of Happiness. Ruey-Yuan Wu National Tsing-Hua University

John Dewey s Philosophy of Education

Action, Criticism & Theory for Music Education

Action, Criticism & Theory for Music Education

A Letter from Louis Althusser on Gramsci s Thought

Pragmatism and Idealism

On Recanati s Mental Files

BDD-A Universitatea din București Provided by Diacronia.ro for IP ( :46:58 UTC)

On Articulting Reasons of Robert Brandom and His Hegelian Methodology

Nature's Perspectives

Hebrew Bible Monographs 18. Colin Toffelmire McMaster Divinity College Hamilton, Ontario, Canada

SOCIAL AND CULTURAL ANTHROPOLOGY

Transcription:

Pragmatism and Experience in Contemporary Debates Antje Gimmler 1, David Hildebrand, Joseph Margolis, and Bjørn Ramberg 1 Aalborg University [Aalborg] (AAU) Nyhavnsgade 14, 9000 Aalborg Denmark, Denmark Abstract Since the linguistic turn and Wilfred Sellars critique of the myth of the given, the notion of experience had a bad reputation in contemporary philosophy. Richard Rorty amplified Sellars critique of experience and turned it against the very pragmatists in whom he found the most inspiration, John Dewey and William James. Robert Brandom s recent work extends and develops Rorty s neopragmatist turn against experience and affirms, proudly and explicitly, that experience should be abandoned as a mythical, confusing, and useless notion. Submission Draft for Second European Pragmatism Conference Paris September, 9-11, 2015 Category of submission: 1. epistemology and metaphysics Title: Pragmatism and Experience in Contemporary Debates Coordinators: David Hildebrand (University of Colorado Denver, US), Antje Gimmler (University of Aalborg, Denmark) (hilde123@gmail.com) (gimmler@learning.aau.dk) General Abstract Since the linguistic turn and Wilfred Sellars critique of the myth of the given, the notion of experience had a bad reputation in contemporary philosophy. Richard Rorty amplified Sellars critique of experience and turned it against the very pragmatists in whom he found the most inspiration, John Dewey and William James. Robert Brandom s recent work extends and develops Rorty s neopragmatist turn against experience and affirms, proudly and explicitly, that experience should be abandoned as a mythical, confusing, and useless notion. Still, experience may not be so easy to eliminate. Not only has the notion played a fundamental role in the historical development of pragmatism, we find it still being deployed in many ways across a wide range of disciplines. Richard Shusterman, for example, has used Speaker Corresponding author: hilde123@gmail.com Corresponding author: josephmargolis455@hotmail.com Corresponding author: b.t.ramberg@csmn.uio.no sciencesconf.org:epc2:52182

the notion of experience to broaden and extend the subject matter and method of aesthetics. In philosophy of mind and cognitive science, Mark Johnson integrates philosophical theories of experience (from classical pragmatists) along with recent scientific discoveries (from anthropology, psychology, and neuro-physiology) to show how meaningful experience is both in mind and in body. In the social sciences the notion of experience is currently experiencing a second career in form of so-called practice theories. Here scholars like Bruno Latour or Theodore Schatzki emphasize the role of materiality, not exclusively as material culture, but in the way it entangles with our actions. This panel contributes to this Conference s theme (to advance understanding of pragmatism s relevance to contemporary debates in the humanities, social and natural sciences, and communities of practice) with presentations that (a) explicate and analyze the current state of the experience/language tension in contemporary pragmatic theory and (b) provide concrete examples of how experience is playing an indispensable role in contemporary debates. Panel Contributors: - Bjørn Torgrim Ramberg (Oslo University, Norway) - Joseph Margolis (Temple University, Philadelphia) - David Hildebrand (University of Colorado, Denver) - Antje Gimmler (University of Aalborg, Denmark) Abstracts: Bjørn Torgrim Ramberg (University of Oslo, Norway) (b.t.ramberg@csmn.uio.no) Agendas of pragmatism and the concept of experience Neo-pragmatists (Rorty, Brandom, Price and others) are often accused of neglecting or denying the significance of the concept of experience and of over-emphasizing the significance of language and linguistic behavior. Thereby, critics claim, neo-pragmatists betray key commitments and lose central insights of classical pragmatists. I suggest that this charge ought to be assessed in light of specific and different agendas that neo-pragmatists are pursuing. To this end, I distinguish three such agendas; (i) the meta-philosophical critique of representationalist epistemology; (ii) the naturalist redescription of the powers of human agency; (iii) the development of rhetorical strategies in service of political progress. I wish to argue for the following: with respect to (i), a thoroughly skeptical attitude toward the concept of experience is mandatory; with respect to (ii), the differences between minds with language and minds without is independently interesting but actually has little bearing on the pragmatist critique of an epistemologically salient notion of experience; and, finally, with respect to (iii), that the Rortyan idea of redescription in fact and unsurprisingly presupposes a rich notion of experience. This, I claim, is how it should be, as the notion(s) of experience that we necessarily invoke and rely on in taking philosophy as a form of cultural politics are indeed strengthened once we distinguish them clearly from the objects of historicist and naturalist critique targeted in (i) and (ii). Such critique will remain, in my view, an integral aspect of a post-metaphysical pragmatism committed to (iii)-that is, committed in its practice to a hope for justice and democracy. Joseph Margolis (josephmargolis455@hotmail.com) Richard Rorty contra Rorty and John Dewey

Dewey s concept of experience has baffled many a reader. It is, however, assuredly the key to Dewey s distinctive philosophical contribution. It owes a measure of verbal daring to James s free-wheeling usage, in Essays in Radical Empiricism; but, doctrinally, it s entirely Dewey s invention, in the form it takes in Logic: The Theory of Inquiry and Experience and Nature. The first chapters of these two books confirm their common theme, though their respective treatments are very different indeed. The main thrust of the Logic is to explain the subordination and the reason for the subordination of the would-be rational resources of canonical logic, standard science, and their merely enabling instrumentalities, within the more organic, humanely orienting powers of what Dewey names the logic of inquiry. Existentially (as we may say), inquiry is effectively coextensive with experience, which applies to all the vicissitudes of the career(s) of what Dewey calls a situation, which begins inchoately, though organismically -as indeterminate, that is, marked by some diffusely suffered dysfunctionality (pointedly applied to the entire situation )-essentially noncognitive, even nonconscious at first. Inquiry may be construed as a situation s power of self-discovery, mediated by the problematizing of its initial dysfunctionality, which issues gradually in denoting transient, instrumentally passing objects and processes that lead, under favorable circumstances, to its becoming suitably determinate (the resolution of the initial dis-ease ). The point of this extraordinary usage (call it heuristic or mythic) is to signal that the human career is itself a contingent articulation of some sort within the formative and transformative contexts of situations, that is broadly self-regulative in a respect that cannot be independently denoted by the instrumental powers of logic and science. Failure to grasp this conceptual (and organismic) dependency accounts for the underlying disorientation and widespread ills of human life (which, culturally, democracy effectively combats). Experience and Nature provides a corrective picture along natural and cultural lines, brought to bear, particularly, on inadequate philosophies that succumb to the classically disabling dualisms of what Dewey identifies as a spectatorial metaphysics and epistemology. Notoriously, Rorty urges that Dewey would have been well-advised to abandon experience: in favor of discourse (that is, the linguistic method of philosophy ), which he draws largely from Davidson and Sellars. For various reasons, Rorty betrays his deep misunderstanding of Dewey s pragmatism, the lack of any close relationship between Sellars s notion of the given (as a philosophical target) and Dewey s notion of the saving discovery of what is denoted (in inquiry) as the given ; and the extremely problematic (possibly even incoherent) treatment of linguistic meaning in Davidson s most pertinent papers (which Rorty seems to regard as pragmatist in an important sense and is guided by). In any event, neither Davidson nor Rorty can be rightly supposed to extend or improve Deweyan pragmatism: Rorty, in fact, explicitly and unconditionally repudiates the linguistic turn ; and Davidson finally subverts the very theory of language on which any reading of Rorty s pragmatist account of Davidson s theory of meaning would be at all feasible. The exposé of these disorders may contribute to a more careful formulation of the pragmatist undertaking, which lies elsewhere and depends on a measure of convergence between Dewey and Peirce. David Hildebrand (University of Colorado, Denver) (hilde123@gmail.com) A Case, with Examples, for Experience in Contemporary Pragmatism Thirty-plus years ago, Richard Rorty published Consequences of Pragmatism. One consequence of that book-along with other subsequent work by Rorty-has been to challenge the centrality of experience for pragmatism s conceptions of truth, morality, and reality. Rorty denigrated experience and argued that the notion should be eliminated from pragmatism. He criticized pragmatists like Dewey and James for either lapsing into bad faith (offering experience as a substitute for substance, or mind, etc.) or for simply lacking the linguistic

tools (devised later by analytic philosophy) to escape philosophical dead ends. Rorty s challenge, one may safely assert, created both space and motivation for the development of a more language-centered pragmatism, sometimes called neopragmatism or new pragmatism. This language-centered strategy has become important in the work of figures such as Robert Brandom, Huw Price, Cheryl Misak, Michael Williams, and Bjørn Ramberg. However, while Rorty was trying to eliminate experience from pragmatism, contemporaries of Rorty (e.g., John J. McDermott and Richard Bernstein) were elucidating the notion and arguing for its indispensability to pragmatism. In a The Pragmatic Turn (2010) Bernstein argued that a pragmatic conception of inquiry requires experience: [Rortyan] redescription, Bernstein writes, no matter how imaginative, is not enough. Bernstein traces this lesson to Charles S. Peirce s view that experience involves bruteness, constraint, over-and-againstness. Experience is our great teacher. And experience takes place by a series of surprises. (Bernstein, R., 2010, The Pragmatic Turn, Polity Press, Cambridge, p. 132) Bernstein s point was that without the element of experience, experimental inquiries lack friction. While this is surely correct, the case for the centrality of experience needs to be made more broadly and more forcefully. Many, indeed, have been working in this vein. This paper will contribute to those arguments not with more theoretical parsings of experience and language, but rather by offering a range of illustrations and examples. The examples come from various arenas, including the technological (medical, educational, communication), the aesthetic, and the religious. Specific examples may include: social companion robots, social media such as Facebook or Instagram, Massive Open Online Courses (MOOC s), obstetrical ultrasounds, Native American wisdom quests, and the challenge posed to the epistemological hierarchy of the senses by recent developments in the aesthetics of cuisine. Theoretical frameworks for these examples will come from recent work in the philosophy of technology (Peter Paul Verbeek, Larry Hickman, Sherry Turkle), the philosophy of mind (Mark Johnson), and aesthetics (Thomas Alexander, Raymond Boisvert). Again, the goal of these examples is primarily to expand our imaginations about the roles pre- or non-linguistic experience can play in meaning-making. By showing how meaning can and does rely upon such experiences, the more abstract argument about the necessity of experience to pragmatism is given additional weight. This reliance, we might say, strengthens the claim that experience occupies a normative role in pragmatism (indeed, in life), one that cannot be fulfilled by language or its cognates. The paper will end with the critical observation that a reliance on experience shows (though I won t have space to spell out this in the paper) the inability of linguistic pragmatisms to accommodate these practices. Existentially, that is, such pragmatisms are too thin. Antje Gimmler (University of Aalborg, Denmark) gimmler@learning.aau.dk What experience does and language not - and the other way round That classical pragmatism is not really on top of what counts as philosophical method in the traditions of logical empiricism and the following analytical philosophy has become a common opinion. This has been fueled by Rorty s interpretation of Dewey as well as comments by Robert Brandom. The point seems to be that classical pragmatism has not performed the linguistic turn, thus classical pragmatism has not understood that philosophical problems have to be analyzed in terms of the language one uses to formulate them. Instead classical pragmatism does - and here John Dewey is the most persistent protagonist - insist upon to use such an old-fashioned concept as experience. But do we have to choose between language and experience? First of all, for classical pragmatism, language is also a central concept, but it takes a different role than in analytic language philosophy. However, we need to know what is at stake with the alleged alterna-

tive between language and experience. This is a meta-philosophical question and so what is at stake is the understanding and role of philosophy itself. To put the question very bluntly: do we follow Dewey and the reconstruction of philosophy he recommends (which basically includes a transformation of philosophy); or do we add on a practice perspective to the more recent linguistically focused philosophy - analytical philosophy cum practices - in order to broaden the scope of analytical philosophy? The transformation Dewey argued for is originally not directed towards language philosophy; rather, Dewey s reconstructionist philosophy is schooled in critical debate with the Platonic-Aristotelian tradition and its ideal of theory. Does this critique also apply to analytical philosophy? These questions comprise an orientating framework for the following questions which the paper shall pose and discuss: 1. What kind of concept of experience does Dewey advocate? In Robert Brandom s outlines, Dewey s concept of experience has Hegelian traits. This first part discusses the different dimensions of Dewey s concept of experience and concludes that experience from Dewey s viewpoint should not be conceptualized as a purely epistemological concept. 2. This leads to the second question: Is a consistent anti-representationalist position in epistemology possible without also accepting anti-foundationalist consequences and - this is the crucial point - wouldn t that also include the notion of experience in a way where it is neither an empiricist remnant nor a new (mythological, residual) category? These first two questions are formulated from the viewpoint of philosophy: an inner, philosophical discussion. 3. The third part takes a different perspective. What does Dewey s reconstructed philosophy offer to other disciplines? In social science and political theory, Dewey s philosophy has gained new popularity. It is exactly his theory of inquiry and experience that seems to be most attractive to practice theory (Schatzki, Latour) and non-ideal political theory (Anderson). This part will show that Deweyan pragmatism interprets practices more radically than most of the approaches united under the umbrella term practice theory. Still, experience may not be so easy to eliminate. Not only has the notion played a fundamental role in the historical development of pragmatism, we find it still being deployed in many ways across a wide range of disciplines. Richard Shusterman, for example, has used the notion of experience to broaden and extend the subject matter and method of aesthetics. In philosophy of mind and cognitive science, Mark Johnson integrates philosophical theories of experience (from classical pragmatists) along with recent scientific discoveries (from anthropology, psychology, and neuro-physiology) to show how meaningful experience is both in mind and in body. In the social sciences the notion of experience is currently experiencing a second career in form of so-called practice theories. Here scholars like Bruno Latour or Theodore Schatzki emphasize the role of materiality, not exclusively as material culture, but in the way it entangles with our actions. This panel contributes to this Conference s theme (to advance understanding of pragmatism s relevance to contemporary debates in the humanities, social and natural sciences, and communities of practice) with presentations that (a) explicate and analyze the current state of the experience/language tension in contemporary pragmatic theory and (b) provide concrete examples of how experience is playing an indispensable role in contemporary debates. Keywords: language, experience, representationalism, Dewey, practices