Postphenomenology vs Postpositivism : Don Ihde vs Bruno Latour

Similar documents
PHILOSOPHY OF SOCIAL SCIENCE INTS 4522 Spring Jack Donnelly and Martin Rhodes -

Natika Newton, Foundations of Understanding. (John Benjamins, 1996). 210 pages, $34.95.


Course Description: looks into the from a range dedicated too. Course Goals: Requirements: each), a 6-8. page writing. assignment. grade.

Philosophy Department Expanded Course Descriptions Fall, 2007

INTERVIEW WITH DON IHDE

What counts as a convincing scientific argument? Are the standards for such evaluation

Part IV Social Science and Network Theory

The Public Thing: On the Idea of a Politics of Artefacts

Post-positivism. Nick J Fox

The Strengths and Weaknesses of Frege's Critique of Locke By Tony Walton

8/28/2008. An instance of great change or alteration in affairs or in some particular thing. (1450)

Mass Communication Theory

In inquiry into what constitutes interpretation in natural science. will have to reflect on the constitutive elements of interpretation and three

Four Characteristic Research Paradigms

observation and conceptual interpretation

10/24/2016 RESEARCH METHODOLOGY Lecture 4: Research Paradigms Paradigm is E- mail Mobile

INTRODUCTION TO THE POLITICS OF SOCIAL THEORY

1. What is Phenomenology?

A Comprehensive Critical Study of Gadamer s Hermeneutics

ENVIRONMENTAL EXPERIENCE: Beyond Aesthetic Subjectivism and Objectivism

BOOK REVIEWS. Celebrating Don Ihde

VALUES AND VALUING [Adapted from Carl Mitcham, ed., Encyclopedia of Science, Technology, and Ethics (New York: Macmillan Reference, 2005).

Philosophical Background to 19 th Century Modernism

Department of Philosophy Florida State University

The topic of this Majors Seminar is Relativism how to formulate it, and how to evaluate arguments for and against it.

These are some notes to give you some idea of the content of the lecture they are not exhaustive, nor always accurate! So read the referenced work.

uniformity and individual uniqueness

The Spell of the Sensuous Chapter Summaries 1-4 Breakthrough Intensive 2016/2017

A Copernican Revolution in IS: Using Kant's Critique of Pure Reason for Describing Epistemological Trends in IS

UNIVERSITY OF TORONTO INSTRUCTORSHIPS IN PHILOSOPHY CUPE Local 3902, Unit 1 SUMMER SESSION 2019

206 Metaphysics. Chapter 21. Universals

The Landscape of Philosophy of Science

PH 8122: Topics in Philosophy: Phenomenology and the Problem of Passivity Fall 2013 Thursdays, 6-9 p.m, 440 JORG

Phenomenology and Non-Conceptual Content

Phenomenology and Structuralism PHIL 607 Fall 2011

FORUM: QUALITATIVE SOCIAL RESEARCH SOZIALFORSCHUNG

INTRODUCTION TO NONREPRESENTATION, THOMAS KUHN, AND LARRY LAUDAN


Content. Philosophy from sources to postmodernity. Kurmangaliyeva G. Tradition of Aristotelism: Meeting of Cultural Worlds and Worldviews...

Merleau-Ponty Final Take Home Questions

Phenomenology Glossary

Review of David Woodruff Smith and Amie L. Thomasson, eds., Phenomenology and the Philosophy of Mind, 2005, Oxford University Press.

EPISTEMOLOGY, METHODOLOGY, AND THE SOCIAL SCIENCES

Caught in the Middle. Philosophy of Science Between the Historical Turn and Formal Philosophy as Illustrated by the Program of Kuhn Sneedified

Global culture, media culture and semiotics

Qualitative Design and Measurement Objectives 1. Describe five approaches to questions posed in qualitative research 2. Describe the relationship betw

6AANB th Century Continental Philosophy. Basic information. Module description. Assessment methods and deadlines. Syllabus Academic year 2016/17

French theories in IS research : An exploratory study on ICIS, AMCIS and MISQ

Theory or Theories? Based on: R.T. Craig (1999), Communication Theory as a field, Communication Theory, n. 2, May,

PH 360 CROSS-CULTURAL PHILOSOPHY IES Abroad Vienna

Kęstas Kirtiklis Vilnius University Not by Communication Alone: The Importance of Epistemology in the Field of Communication Theory.

Introduction to The Handbook of Economic Methodology

A short-term certificate course

Rorty, Dewey, and Incommensurability

PETER - PAUL VERBEEK. Beyond the Human Eye Technological Mediation and Posthuman Visions

Theory or Theories? Based on: R.T. Craig (1999), Communication Theory as a field, Communication Theory, n. 2, May,


Embodied music cognition and mediation technology

Back to Basics: Appreciating Appreciative Inquiry as Not Normal Science

Big Questions in Philosophy. What Is Relativism? Paul O Grady 22 nd Jan 2019

Relativism and the Social Construction of Science: Kuhn, Lakatos, Feyerabend

This is an electronic reprint of the original article. This reprint may differ from the original in pagination and typographic detail.

what we see, what we ought to see.

Aalborg Universitet. The Dimension of Seriousness in Moral Education Wiberg, Merete. Publication date: 2007

Naïve realism without disjunctivism about experience

Complete bibliography: Erving Goffman s writings. Persson, Anders. Published: Link to publication

GEORG W. F. HEGEL, JEAN-PAUL SARTRE AND MAURICE MERLEAU-PONTY: WHERE AND HOW DO THEY MEET?

ON GESTURAL MEANING IN ACTS OF EXPRESSION

PHIL 415 Continental Philosophy: Key Problems Spring 2013

SENIOR SEMINAR: Aesthetics and the Philosophy of Art: Between Phenomenology and Semiotic. Fall 2012 & Winter 2013

Mimesis and World-building: Berger and Girard on the Sacred

By Tetsushi Hirano. PHENOMENOLOGY at the University College of Dublin on June 21 st 2013)

Louw-01.qxd 12/16/2004 6:44 PM Page 1. 1 Introduction

UC Berkeley UC Berkeley Previously Published Works

Chapter 2: Karl Marx Test Bank

Action, Criticism & Theory for Music Education

What is Science? What is the purpose of science? What is the relationship between science and social theory?

Reflexive Methodology

ANALYSIS OF THE PREVAILING VIEWS REGARDING THE NATURE OF THEORY- CHANGE IN THE FIELD OF SCIENCE

Aalborg Universitet. An introduction to Historical Phenomenology Dorfman, Benjamin. Publication date: 2005

Foucault and the Human Sciences. By Rebecca Norlander. January 1, 2008

Penultimate Draft- Final version forthcoming in Philosophical Psychology

HPS 1653 / PHIL 1610 Introduction to the Philosophy of Science

Valuable Particulars

Postphenomenology, Embodiment and Technics

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

TROUBLING QUALITATIVE INQUIRY: ACCOUNTS AS DATA, AND AS PRODUCTS

THE IMPORTANCE OF INTERPRETATION. Mark Bevir, Ph.D.

Lecture (0) Introduction

Louw-3944-Ch-01:Fox et al-3776-ch-20.qxp 31/07/2009 7:29 PM Page 1 ONE. Introduction

Conceptual Change, Relativism, and Rationality

Introduction. Doing Phenomenology State University of New York Press, Albany

Towards a constructivist program in safety

P executes intuition in its particular way of looking at the experience(s) reflected upon and sees its structures and dynamics. c.

EASTERN INTUITION AND WESTERN COGNITION: WHERE AND HOW DO THEY MEET?

The phenomenological tradition conceptualizes

In retrospect: The Structure of Scientific Revolutions

The Application of Karl Popper s Three Worlds Schema to Questions about Information in the Fields of Complexity, Cybernetics, and Informatics

GRADUATE SEMINARS

Transcription:

Postphenomenology vs Postpositivism : Don Ihde vs Bruno Latour Flores, Fernando Unpublished: 2014-01-01 Link to publication Citation for published version (APA): Flores, F. (2014). Postphenomenology vs Postpositivism : Don Ihde vs Bruno Latour. 1-16. Paper presented at Broken Technologies, a postphenomenological approach to anthropology and social sciences,. General rights Copyright and moral rights for the publications made accessible in the public portal are retained by the authors and/or other copyright owners and it is a condition of accessing publications that users recognise and abide by the legal requirements associated with these rights. Users may download and print one copy of any publication from the public portal for the purpose of private study or research. You may not further distribute the material or use it for any profit-making activity or commercial gain You may freely distribute the URL identifying the publication in the public portal Take down policy If you believe that this document breaches copyright please contact us providing details, and we will remove access to the work immediately and investigate your claim. L UNDUNI VERS I TY PO Box117 22100L und +46462220000

Download date: 18. Jun. 2018

Postphenomenology vs Postpositivism Don Ihde vs Bruno Latour Introduction Contemporary studies of technology and its relation to science are inspired by the works of Don Ihde and Bruno Latour. In a very concise manner we will describe Don Ihde as a phenomenologist who has developed a very original synthesis between phenomenology and American pragmatism that he has named Postphenomenology. The work of Ihde, based on his studies of the work of Paul Ricoeur implies also an expansion of hermeneutics to embrace the interpretation of science and technology. On the other hand, Latour s writings, which have been identified with the general name of ANT (actor-network-theory), are akin to the works of the Postpositivists, e.g. Kuhn s sociology of science along with Austin and Wittgenstein s philosophy of language with the additional outsider influence from Foucault s work, specially his theory of power as bio-power. Let us see how Ihde understand Postpositivism: By the late fifties the strong version of positivism was already under attack by Karl Popper and Imre Lakatos, who effectively reduced verification to a combination of falsification plus consensual research programs. Paul Feyerabend, perhaps the most radical of the iconoclasts, although active in this time, followed Thomas Kuhn with Against Method. But it was Kuhn who both won the antipositivist battle and ended up the new reframe of science construal. The Structure of Scientific Revolutions remains the most cited history and philosophy of science book in the twentieth century. The most important indicator, however, is the use of Kuhnian language in the selfinterpretation of scientists which can be found in virtually every issue of Science, 1

Scientific American, and other widely read science magazines. 1 As Ihde described it, Postpositivism also labelled as Postempiricism - arose as a consequence of the crisis of Positivism suffered in the West after the Second World War and the Vietnam War. This crisis opened empiricist philosophy for the readings of Phenomenology and other specific approaches traditionally belonging to Continental Thought. Let us see in the next section about the particularities of these two different approaches. The Phenomenological standpoint The first aspect of Phenomenology that we want to stress is that all my knowledge of the world, even my scientific knowledge, is gained from my own particular point of view ; these are words from Merleau-Ponty: Phenomenology is a matter of describing, not of explaining or analyzing. Husserl s first directive to phenomenology, in its early stages, to be a descriptive psychology, or to return to the things themselves, is from the start a rejection of science. I am not the outcome or the meeting-point of numerous causal agencies which determine my bodily or psychological make-up. I cannot conceive myself as nothing but a bit of the world, a mere object of biological, psychological or sociological investigation. I cannot shut myself up within the realm of science. All my knowledge of the world, even my scientific knowledge, is gained from my own particular point of view, or from some experience of the world without which the symbols of science would be meaningless. The whole universe of science is built upon the world as directly experienced, and if we want to subject science itself to rigorous scrutiny and arrive at a precise assessment of its meaning and scope, we must begin by reawakening the basic experience of the world of which science is the second-order expression. 2 In short, phenomenology cannot and does not try to approach the world with 1 Ihde, Don. Expanding Hermeneutics. Visualism in Science; p. 143. 2 Merleau-Ponty, Maurice, Phenomenology of perception, Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1962; p. VIII. 2

impartiality or objectivity. Probably the chief gain from phenomenology is to have united extreme subjectivism and extreme objectivism in its notion of the world or of rationality. 3 For phenomenology, the things of the world show existential existence, and therefore are very fragile, changing in all possible ways and becoming fixed only in concrete moments of existential experience. The phenomenologist relations to things is intentional that means that to look at an object is to inhabit it, and from this habitation to grasp all things in terms of the aspect which they present to it. Let us read the whole worlds of Merleau-Ponty: The object-horizon structure, or the perspective, is no obstacle to me when I want to see the object: for just as it is the means whereby objects are distinguished from each other, it is also the means whereby they are disclosed. To see is to enter a universe of beings, which display themselves, and they would not do this if they could not be hidden behind each other or behind me. In other words: to look at an object is to inhabit it, and from this habitation to grasp all things in terms of the aspect which they present to it. But in so far as I see those things too, they remain abodes open to my gaze, and, being potentially lodged in them, I already perceive from various angles the central object of my present vision. Thus every object is the mirror of all others. When I look at the lamp on my table, I attribute to it not only the qualities visible from where I am, but also those which the chimney, the walls, the table can 'see'; but back of my lamp is nothing but the face which it 'shows' to the chimney. I can therefore see an object in so far as objects form a system or a world, and in so far as each one treats the others round it as spectators of its hidden aspects and as guarantee of the permanence of those aspects. Any seeing of an object by me is instantaneously reiterated among all those objects in the world, which are apprehended as co-existent, because each of them is all that the others 'see' of it. 4 For phenomenology, there are no objective things with fast forms and properties. Neither the usability of things is forever determined because through intentionality the Ego inhabits the things of the world changing with experience. The family of approaches that consider essential the subjective perspective is known with the general name of Continental 3 Merleau-Ponty, Maurice; p. XIX. 4 Merleau-Ponty, Maurice, Phenomenology of perception, Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1962; p.68. 3

Thought. In this family of philosophies there are different expressions of earlier forms of phenomenology: [Phenomenology] Has been long on the way, and its adherents have discovered it in every quarter, certainly in Hegel and Kierkegaard, but equally in Marx, Nietzsche and Freud. A purely linguistic examination of the texts in question would yield no proof; we find in texts only what we put into them, and if ever any kind of history has suggested the interpretations which should be put on it, it is the history of philosophy. 5 One common characteristic of Continental Thought that has been particularly influential to Postpositivism is the hermeneutical approach, which makes the question of truth contextual dependent. Some aspects of ANT Actor-network-theory also tried to break with the radical dualism of the Cartesian metaphysics. This is achieved by creating the category of the world of things as hybrids; the former Cartesian objective world populated with objective things becomes now a world populated by things that are both culture and nature. In that sense is correct to assume that ANT attempts to distance itself from Positivism and consequently approaches to Phenomenology. Don Ihde described the incorporation of hermeneutics to the postpositvist perspective as follows: A second set of Field-clearers, from a different perspective, began to gain ground, largely in the seventies on: the so-called social constructionist sociologists of science. The new "post-mertonian" sociologists of science, in the simplest perspective, apply the methods of the various social sciences to science-as-institution, thus making of science a culture. In stark contrast to the "theory machine" of earlier positivism, the sociology of science looks at daily practice, usually at what 5 Merleau-Ponty, Maurice; p. VIII. 4

goes on in experimental and laboratory science. Early and strongly discussed work centered on the "strong program" of Bloor et al., the look at laboratory life by Steve Woolgar and Bruno Latour and by Karin Knorr-Cetina, and the examination of how scientific "products" are "constructed" as in Andrew Pickering's Constructing Quarks. Again, I shall not follow out the details, but note in passing that; first, there is some indirect connection here with the P-H traditions among these thinkers. Pickering, in particular, draws from the "social construction of reality" tradition of Berger and Luckmann, who in turn draw heavily from Husserl and Schutz, so there is a quasi-phenomenological background lurking here. Similarly, the popular and highly visible work of Bruno Latour clearly draws from the continental traditions, and the shadows of both Derrida and Foucault are not hard to detect. 6 But the worldview of Positivism was characterized not only by a Cartesian metaphysics but also by a radical anti-subjectivism. Positivism has been possible through the negation of the cognitive importance of the subjective dimension. We notice that ANT does not break with this anti-subjectivist tradition and this makes its approach closer to the family of Positivism. Latour s categories Latour s work has been described as a critic to Modernism (understood as a positivist endeavour) and in this sense his work include a critic to Positivism. Reading the title of Latour s book we discover very soon that for Latour Modernity is not a historical category. Latour refers to the categories of postmodernity, premodernity and modernity but he is not referring to historical periods but to the names of epistemological frameworks. Let see how Latour presents his standpoint. Latour exhorted us to assume a new paradigm choosing some specific aspects from premodernity, modernity and postmodernity: 6 Ihde, Don; p. 144-145. 5

Latour, Bruno, We have never been modern, Harvard Univ. Press, Cambridge, Mass., 1993; p. 135. As we can see Latour s work fits into the positivistic reduction of historical periods to epistemological standpoints. Latour and non-human agency At the center of Latour s work we find the concept of acting performed by artifacts described as non-humans. It is obvious that Latour is meaning this seriously attributing intentionality to technologies. Latour s words: Early this morning, I was in a bad mood and decided to break a law and start my car without buckling my seat belt. My car usually does not want to start before I buckle the belt. It first flashes a red light FASTEN YOUR SEAT BELT!, then an alarm sounds; it is so high pitched, so relentless, so repetitive, that I cannot stand it. After ten seconds I swear and put on the belt. This time, I stood the alarm for twenty seconds and then gave in. My mood had worsened quite a bit, but I was at peace with the law at least 6

with that law. I wished to break it, but I could not. Where is the morality? In me, a human driver, dominated by the mindless power of an artifact? 7 There are some aspects in Latour s work that reminds the approach to artefacts which characterizes Merleau-Ponty, but there are clear differences too. While the first perceives things as the mirror of all others, Latour sees in things the hidden and despised social masses that make up our morality. From a phenomenological perspective, it is acceptable to consider that artefacts and technologies in general mediate intentionality, but this mediation is only relevant in a study of intersubjectivity. That what is interesting in a study of technology is their human face and not their non-humanity. Let us see how Latour expresses the way things make up our morality: I expect sociologists to be much more fortunate than cosmologists, because they will soon discover their missing mass. To balance our accounts of society, we simply have to turn our exclusive attention away from humans and look also at nonhumans. Here they are the hidden and despised social masses who make up our morality. They knock at the door of sociology, requesting a place in the accounts of society as stubbornly as the human masses did in the nineteenth century. What our ancestors, the founders of sociology, did a century ago to house the human masses in the fabric of social theory; we should do now to find a place in a new social theory for the non- human masses that beg us for understanding. 8 The agency of things in Latour s approach remember us the efforts made by the defenders of artificial intelligence and artificial life in the earlier days of computer science. The origins of the idea of the agency of an artificial intelligence, is found already in the work of the English mathematician Alan Matheson Turing. During the 1950 s he publishes Computing Machinery and Intelligence in the journal of philosophy Mind. In this article, his thoughts transcend the limited circles of the specialists and became an important issue in 7 Latour, Bruno. Where Are the Missing Masses? The Sociology of a Few Mundane Artifacts ; in Bijker & Law (1992) - Shaping Technology / Building Society: Studies in Sociotechnical Change. MIT Press, 1992; p. 225-226. 8 Latour, Bruno. Where Are the Missing Masses? The Sociology of a Few Mundane Artifacts ; in Bijker & Law; 1992, p. 227. 7

the foundation of a new ideology for technological action. In those historical pages, Turing asked, can a machine think? His answer was affirmative, arriving to it through a series of pragmatic substitutions to the initial question. We can see that Turing identified mechanical communication with human communication and processing with thinking. That can be attributed to the erroneous use that engineers and scientists made of terms that were originated in an intentional context, for example the terms intelligence and communication. If we now translate Turing question to a Latourian context and ask us: Is it possible to distinguish a non-human actant (the car when it does not want to start before I buckle the belt ) from a person in the moment of non-face-to-face communication? Can I really believe that my car does not want to start before I buckle the belt? Of course this perspective discovers a kind of fetishism that refuses to see the person behind the thing. To answer the question it must be reformulated as follows: can I be capable of recognizing the voice of the technician that programmed the behavior of my car in spite of his/her absence? That is possible because the human programmer is able to condense the rules of human communication (human thought) in such a way that these could be expressed by mechanical procedures. The question about the artifacts capability to think is similar to that of as asking if the gramophones can sing, or if a video camera possesses the sense of sight. While the gramophone reproduces the voice or music and the book reproduces words, the computer reproduces abstract human action (no acts ). The great contribution of Turing and his generation is that of being able to capture the formal structures of human action into mechanical procedures; however as many times before and after, this achievement was interpreted philosophically in an incorrect manner creating false problems and false expectations. The essence of programming (that is to say, the art of understanding and reproducing the rules of human action) consists on describing the steps of any process in its atomic units, one by one, in a univocal way. But what are captured are the physical aspects of the human acts, namely actions, never the acts themselves. 8

Intentional congruency and causality The non-humans of ANT are responsible of social behavior; they make us humans and other non-humans to do something according to their wishes. They are carrying scripts that work as Austin s performatives. Madeleine Akrich explained this as follows: Designers thus define actors with specific tastes, competences, motives, aspirations, political prejudices, and the rest, and they assume that morality, technology, science, and economy will evolve in particular ways. A large part of the work of innovators is that of inscribing this vision of (or prediction about) the world in the technical content of the new object. I will call the end product of this work a script or a scenario. 9 However there is an important difference between Austin performatives and the scripts of the program of a machine; the first is an intentional linguistic act, the second is the reduction of human intentionality to a series of non-intentional actions. In this sense, the scripts of the technics that surround us cannot make us to do anything without our willing it. For example, in Latour s example according to which my car usually does not want to start before I buckle the belt implies that I cannot drive without buckling the belt, which is clearly wrong. The flashing red light of the text FASTEN YOUR SEAT BELT! and the relentless high pitched and repetitive sound of the alarm have no authority upon the subject. It is easy to avoid the demands of the car for instance buckling the belt before sitting. Very different would be the case if a person demands or commands me to fasten my belt because not doing it would imply an intentional conflict. Literature Bijker & Law. Shaping technology/building society: studies in sociotechnical change, MIT Press, Cambridge, Mass., 1992. 9 Bijker & Law; (1992); p. 208. 9

Blok, Anders & Elgaard Jensen, Torben, Bruno Latour: hybride tanker i en hybrid verden, 1. udgave, 1. oplag., Hans Reitzel, Kbh., 2009. Merleau-Ponty, Maurice. Phenomenology of perception, Routledge, London, 2002[1962]. Ihde, Don, Expanding hermeneutics: visualism in science, Northwestern Univ. Press, Evanston, Ill., 1998. Latour, Bruno, We have never been modern, Harvester Wheatsheaf, New York, 1993. Latour, Bruno, Reassembling the social: an introduction to actor-network-theory, University Press, Oxford, 2005. 10