THE PROBLEM OF INTERPRETING MODAL LOGIC w. V. QUINE

Similar documents
Quine s Two Dogmas of Empiricism. By Spencer Livingstone

Scientific Philosophy

What is Character? David Braun. University of Rochester. In "Demonstratives", David Kaplan argues that indexicals and other expressions have a

Nissim Francez: Proof-theoretic Semantics College Publications, London, 2015, xx+415 pages

Articulating Medieval Logic, by Terence Parsons. Oxford: Oxford University Press,

PLEASE SCROLL DOWN FOR ARTICLE

Reply to Stalnaker. Timothy Williamson. In Models and Reality, Robert Stalnaker responds to the tensions discerned in Modal Logic

Necessity in Kant; Subjective and Objective

In Defense of the Contingently Nonconcrete

LOGICO-SEMANTIC ASPECTS OF TRUTHFULNESS

Sidestepping the holes of holism

The Philosophy of Language. Frege s Sense/Reference Distinction

Aristotle s Modal Syllogistic. Marko Malink. Cambridge Harvard University Press, Pp X $ 45,95 (hardback). ISBN:

A Note on Analysis and Circular Definitions

Introduction p. 1 The Elements of an Argument p. 1 Deduction and Induction p. 5 Deductive Argument Forms p. 7 Truth and Validity p. 8 Soundness p.

Corcoran, J George Boole. Encyclopedia of Philosophy. 2nd edition. Detroit: Macmillan Reference USA, 2006

Working BO1 BUSINESS ONTOLOGY: OVERVIEW BUSINESS ONTOLOGY - SOME CORE CONCEPTS. B usiness Object R eference Ontology. Program. s i m p l i f y i n g

Peirce's Remarkable Rules of Inference

Bas C. van Fraassen, Scientific Representation: Paradoxes of Perspective, Oxford University Press, 2008.

THE PARADOX OF ANALYSIS

Appendix B. Elements of Style for Proofs

Non-Classical Logics. Viorica Sofronie-Stokkermans Winter Semester 2012/2013

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at

CONTINGENCY AND TIME. Gal YEHEZKEL

Disquotation, Conditionals, and the Liar 1

Resemblance Nominalism: A Solution to the Problem of Universals. GONZALO RODRIGUEZ-PEREYRA. Oxford: Clarendon Press, Pp. xii, 238.

Background to Gottlob Frege

Conclusion. One way of characterizing the project Kant undertakes in the Critique of Pure Reason is by

On Meaning. language to establish several definitions. We then examine the theories of meaning

Ontology as a formal one. The language of ontology as the ontology itself: the zero-level language

Self-reference. Sereny's presentation in "Godel, Tarski, Church, and the Liar,"' although the main idea is

Designing a Deductive Foundation System

Types of perceptual content

THESIS MIND AND WORLD IN KANT S THEORY OF SENSATION. Submitted by. Jessica Murski. Department of Philosophy

Mind Association. Oxford University Press and Mind Association are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Mind.

Logic and Philosophy of Science (LPS)

THE SUBSTITUTIONAL ANALYSIS OF LOGICAL CONSEQUENCE

Immanuel Kant Critique of Pure Reason

KINDS (NATURAL KINDS VS. HUMAN KINDS)

1/8. The Third Paralogism and the Transcendental Unity of Apperception

Categories and Schemata

1 Objects and Logic. 1. Abstract objects

Naïve realism without disjunctivism about experience

Singular Propositions, Abstract Constituents, and Propositional Attitudes

Replies to the Critics

The ambiguity of definite descriptions

INTERNATIONAL CONFERENCE ON ENGINEERING DESIGN ICED 05 MELBOURNE, AUGUST 15-18, 2005 GENERAL DESIGN THEORY AND GENETIC EPISTEMOLOGY

Simplicity, Its Failures And a Naturalistic Rescue?

Bennett on Parts Twice Over

THE SUBSTITUTIONAL ANALYSIS OF LOGICAL CONSEQUENCE

PRIOR ON THE LOGIC AND THE METAPHYSICS OF TIME

138 Great Problems in Philosophy and Physics - Solved? Chapter 11. Meaning. This chapter on the web informationphilosopher.com/knowledge/meaning

SIGNS, SYMBOLS, AND MEANING DANIEL K. STEWMT*

(as methodology) are not always distinguished by Steward: he says,

Elements of Style. Anders O.F. Hendrickson

MATTHEWS GARETH B. Aristotelian Explanation. on "the role of existential presuppositions in syllogistic premisses"

MONOTONE AMAZEMENT RICK NOUWEN

Lecture 10 Popper s Propensity Theory; Hájek s Metatheory

Logical Foundations of Mathematics and Computational Complexity a gentle introduction

Forms and Causality in the Phaedo. Michael Wiitala

1/9. Descartes on Simple Ideas (2)

BOOK REVIEW. William W. Davis

Twentieth Excursus: Reference Magnets and the Grounds of Intentionality

NINO B. COCCHIARELLA LOGIC AND ONTOLOGY

Depictive Structure? I. Introduction

Vagueness & Pragmatics

Existential Cause & Individual Experience

Aristotle s Metaphysics

An Aristotelian Puzzle about Definition: Metaphysics VII.12 Alan Code

Manuel Bremer University Lecturer, Philosophy Department, University of Düsseldorf, Germany

RELATIVISM ABOUT TRUTH AND PERSPECTIVE-NEUTRAL PROPOSITIONS

- 1 - I. Aristotle A. Biographical data 1. Macedonian, from Stagira; hence often referred to as "the Stagirite". 2. Dates: B. C. 3.

1/8. Axioms of Intuition

1/10. The A-Deduction

Aristotle: an ancient mathematical logician

Truth and Tropes. by Keith Lehrer and Joseph Tolliver

QUESTIONS AND LOGICAL ANALYSIS OF NATURAL LANGUAGE: THE CASE OF TRANSPARENT INTENSIONAL LOGIC MICHAL PELIŠ

Plurals Jean Mark Gawron San Diego State University

IN DEFENSE OF ESSENTIALISM 1. L. A. Paul University of Arizona Australian National University/RSSS

Heideggerian Ontology: A Philosophic Base for Arts and Humanties Education

XI*-INTENSIONAL AND INTENTIONAL OBJECTS By Roger Scruton

KANT S TRANSCENDENTAL LOGIC

On The Search for a Perfect Language

Cambridge Introductions to Philosophy new textbooks from cambridge

Intensional Relative Clauses and the Semantics of Variable Objects

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

SOCIAL AND CULTURAL ANTHROPOLOGY

Resemblance Nominalism: A Solution to the Problem of Universals

Lecture 12 Aristotle on Knowledge of Principles

PROBLEMS OF SEMANTICS

Article The Nature of Quantum Reality: What the Phenomena at the Heart of Quantum Theory Reveal About the Nature of Reality (Part III)

AN EXAMPLE FOR NATURAL LANGUAGE UNDERSTANDING AND THE AI PROBLEMS IT RAISES

Two Dogmas of Empiricism 1a


Perceptions and Hallucinations

The Prenective View of propositional content

ABELARD: THEOLOGIA CHRISTIANA

Action Theory for Creativity and Process

Kant IV The Analogies The Schematism updated: 2/2/12. Reading: 78-88, In General

MATH 195: Gödel, Escher, and Bach (Spring 2001) Notes and Study Questions for Tuesday, March 20

Transcription:

THm J OUBKAL OJ' SYMBOLIC LOGlc Volume 12, Number 2, June 1947 THE PROBLEM OF INTERPRETING MODAL LOGIC w. V. QUINE There are logicians, myself among them, to \",~hom the ideas of modal logic (e. g. Lewis's) are not intuitively clear until explained in non-modal terms. But so long as modal logic stops short of quantification theory, it is possible (as I shall indicate in 2) to provide some\vhat the type of explanation desired. When modal logic is extended (as by Miss Barca-n l ) to include quantification theory, on the other hand, serious obstacles to interpretation are encountered-particularly if one cares to avoid a curiously idealistic ontology \vhich repudiates material objects. Such are the matters,vhich it is the purpose of the present paper to set forth. 1. Analytic statements from the standpoint of non-modal logic. All true statements,vhich (like '(x) (x == x)') contain only logical signs are naturally to be classified as logically true. But there are also other logically true statements (e. g. 'Socrates is mortal :::J Socrates is mortal'). \vhich contain extra-logical signs. No\v every logical truth of the latter kind is (if for the present,ve disregard modal logic) either provable u;ithin the familiar logic of truth-functions and quantifieation alone, or else deducible by the logic of truth-functions and quantification from logical truths of the kind \vhich contain only logical signs. So every logical truth is either: (a) a true statement containing only logical signs, or (b) provable in the logic of truth-functions and quantification, or (c) deducible by the logic oftruth-functions and quantification from true statements containing only logical signs. But (c) includes (b), since whatever is provable is also, vacuously, deducible from anything else. Also (c) includes (a), since any statement is deducible from itself. Thus (c) by itself might be adopted as an appropriate definition of logical truth (outside modal logic). The "deducibility" spoken of in (c) can be expanded into purely syntactical terms by an enumeration of the familiar rules,,vhich are kno\vn to be complete; and the reference to "logical signs" can likewise be expanded by enumeration of the familiar primitives. The word 'true' in (c) cannot indeed be expanded; no enumeration of axioms or axiom-schemata would serve the purpose here, because of Godel's proof that there can be no complete consistent system of higher logic. \Ve could desire otherwise, especially in view of the logical paradoxes which are kno\vn to be connected with the general concept of truth. 2 Nevertheless (c) is not \vithout explicative value, as marking out the speeial notion of logical truth \\-ithin the general notion (such as it is) of truth. lleceiveu July 17, 19-16 1 Ruth C. Barcan, A /llru:tivnal calculus of first orde,. based on strict i"tplication, this JOGRNAL, vol. 11 (1946), pp. 1-16. 2 See Alfred Tarski, The sernantic conception of truth and the foundation of semantics, Philosophy and phenomenological research, vol. 4 (1914), pp. 341-376. 43

44 w. V. QUINE The class of analytic statements is broader than that of logical truths, for it contains in addition such statements as 'No bachelor is married.' This example might be assimilated to the logical truths by considering it a definitional abbreviation of 'No man not married is married,' \vhich is indeed a logical truth; but I should prefer not to rest analyticity thus on an unrealistic fiction of there being standard definitions of'extra-iogical expressions in terms of a standard set of extra-logical primitives. What is rather in point, I think, is a relation of synonymy, or sameness of meaning, \vhich holds between expressions of real language though there be no standard hierarchy of definitions. In terms of synonymy and logical truth we could define analyticity: a statement is analytic if by putting synonyms for synonyms (e.g. 'man not married' for 'bachelor') it can be turned into a logical truth. The particular synonymy relation \vanted is one of several which have about equal right to the name "synonymy" and are all describable as "sameness of meaning"-in varying senses of "meaning." Synonymy of the kind which renders expressions interchangeable without violence to indirect quotation, for example, would be a narro\ver relation than the one here concerned; and the sense of synonymy proposed by Lewis 3 is yet a third relation, I believe, intermediate between the two. The particular synonymy relation which I have in mind can easily be described in terms of analyticity, at least when the expressions related happen to be statements, names, or predicates. Statements are synonymous if the biconditional ('if and only if') which joins them is analytic; names are synonymous if the statement of identity which joins them is analytic; and predicates are synonymous if, when they are applied to like variables and then combined into a universally quantified biconditional, the result is analytic. But of course we must seek some other definition of synonymy so as to avoid circularity, if synonymy is to be available for use in defining analyticity. Actually the synonymy relation sought is, insofar as applied to propositions, names, and predicates, precisely what Lewis (loc. cit.) calls sameness of intension; but expansion in turn of his definition of "intension" leaves us with phrases \\Thich I do not feel to be appreciably clearer than "synonymy" and "analyticity" themselves. Synonymy, like other linguistic concepts, involves parameters of times and persons, suppressible in idealized treatment: the expression x is synonymous with the expression y for person z at time t. A satisfactory definition of this tetradic relation \vould no doubt be couched, like those of other general concepts of general linguistics, in behavioristic terms. I should like, as a service both to empirical semantics and to philosophy, to offer a satisfactory definition; but I have none. So long, ho\vever, as \ve persist in speaking of expressions as alike or unlike in meaning (and regardless of \vhether \ve countenance meanings themselves in any detached sense), \ve must suppose that there is an eventually formulable criterion of synonymy in some reasonable sense of the term-and probably, in particular, in the sense appropriate to present purposes. Given it, 3 c. 1. Lewis, The modes of 1neaning, ibid., vol. 4 (1943), p. 245.

PROBLEM OF INTERPRETING MODAL LOGIC 45 and given the general notion of truth (in terms of which logical truth has been seen to be definable), we could define analyticity as previously indicated. The notion of analyticity thus appears, at the present writing, to lack a satisfactory foundation. Even so, the notion is clearer to many of us, and obscurer surely to none, than the notions of modal logic; so \ve are still well advised to explain the latter notions in terms of it. This can be done, as sketched in the next section, so long as modal logic stops short of quantification theory.4 2. Interpretation of pre-quantificational modal logic. We need consider only the mode of logical necessity, symbolized by '0'; for the other modal ideas (possibility, impossibility, and the strict conditional and biconditional) are expressible in terms of necessity in obvious fashion. Now '.0' is not quite interchangeable with 'is analytic,' for this reason: the former attaches to a statement (as ',I",,' does) to form a statement containing the original statement, whereas 'is analytic' (like 'is true,' 'is false') attaches to the name of a statement to form a statement about the named statement. Grammatically'0' is an adverb; 'is analytic' is a verb. The formal difference becomes immediately apparent in the case of iteration: '0' can significantly be applied repeatedly (because the result of any application, being a statement, is the kind of expression to which'b' can still significantly be prefixed) \vhereas 'is analytic' can be applied only once (because the result of the application is a statement, whereas 'is analytic' can be appended only to a name.)5 However, '0' can be explained in terms of analyticity as follows: (i) The result of prefixing'0' to any statement is true if and only if the statement is analytic. Let us speak of a statement as of first intention if it is non-modal; and let us speak of a statement as of (n + l)st intention if '0' occurs in it in application to statements of nth intention and no higher. The portion of modal logic which admits statements of nth intention at most (and includes also all non-modal logic) will be called the logic of nth intention; non-modal logic it~~lf is the logic of first intention. Then (i) above may be taken as our explanation of all statements of second intention; and the word 'analytic' in it (explained in the preceding section) ma,y be read 'analytic in first intention.' Relative to the logic of second intention, no\v, \vhich has some new truths of its own in addition to those of the logic of first intention, \Ve may adopt ne,w definitions of logical truth 4 Dr. Nelson Goodman has suggested (in conversation) the dismal possibility that what we think of as synonymy may be wholly a matter of degree, ranging from out-and-out orthographical sameness of expressions on the one hand to mere factual sameness of designatum (as in the case of 'nine' and'the number of the planets') on the other. In this case analyticity in turn would become a matter of degree-a measr-~re merely of our relative reluctance to give up one statement rather than another from among a set of statements whose conjunction has proved false. But if it does develop that the boundary between analytic and synthetic statements has thus to be rubbed out, no doubt it will be generally agreed that the logical modalities have to be abandoned as well. The explanation of modal logic in terms of analyticity remains of interest so long as there is interest in. r':..ol1al logic itself. 6 Cf. my Mathematical logic, pp. 27-33.

46 w. V. QUINE and analyticity paralleling those of the preceding section (but admitting uniterated use of '0' in addition to truth-functions in (c)). ' There upon we may repeat (i) above as an explanation now of all statements of third intention. Supposing this process continued ad infinitum,,ve have an explanation of '0' in application to any statements. I suppose that some such conception underlies the intuition where by axioms are evaluated and adopted for modal logic. The explanation of modal logic thus afforded is adequate so long as modalities are not used inside the scopes of quantifiers; i. e., so long as '0' is applied only to statements and not to matrices. 6 Of course in actual presentations even of this part of modal logic the sign '0' commonly appears before non-statements such as 'p' or 'p ::) p', but there is no harm in this; such expressions are schemata, used diagrammatically and imagined replaced in any given case by actual statements of the depicted forms. 3. Quantification in modal logic. It will be convenient now to think of our basic modality not as '0' but as '0' (possibility); the t,vo are interdefinable, amounting respectively to ''''''0'''''' and ''''''0''''''. And let us think of our quantifiers as existential, since the universal quantifier '(x)' can be explained as '"",(::Ix)""". When'0' is applied to a matrix within a quantification, the whole context admits, in certain cases, of reduction to the type of case dealt with in the preceding section. For example, the combined prefix'(::ix) 0' is equated by Miss Barcan 7 to '0(3x)',,vherein '0' applies no longer to the matrix but to the statement formed by quantifying it (supposing there are no further free variabies); and accordingly the explanation of the preceding section can thereupon be brought to bear. If every matrix containing '0',vere transformable into a matrix containing '0' only at the beginning, then repeated conversion of r(3a)0' to r0 (3a) 1,vould be adequate to explaining the general case; but unfortunately matrices are not generally thus transformable. Equating '(3:x)0' with 'O(3x)' gives us no clue to the interpretation of such statements, for example, as: (::Ix) (x is red. 0 (x is round)). No doubt a modal logician would regard this example as true, but only by virtue of Borne supplementary intuitive criterion-perhaps this: (ii) An existential quantification holds if there is a constant whose substitution for the variable of quantification would render the matrix trtre. This is at best a partial criterion (both in modal and non-modal logic), because of unnameable objects; an ilnnameable object might satisfy the matrix though there be no constant expression whose substitution for the variable would yield a I I use the word 'matrix' (as in Mathematical logic) for one of the meanings of the ambiguous phrase' propositional function.' A matrix is an expression which is like a statement except for containing, at grammatically permissible places, some free occurrences of variables of the kind that are admissible in quantifiers. Briefly, a matrix is a non-statement \vhich can be turned into a statement by applying quantifiers.?p. cit., theorem 38.

PROBLEM OF INTERPRETING MODAL LOGIC 47 truth. But let us adopt (ii) as a partial criterion (sufficient condition) and see ho\v it fares. What I shall sho,v is that it has queer ontological consequences. It leads us to hold that there are no concrete objects (men, planets, etc.), but rather that there are only, corresponding to each supposed concrete object, a multitude of distinguishable entities (perhaps "individual concepts," in Church's phrase). It leads us to hold, e. g., that there is no such ball of matter.as the so-called planet Venus, but rather at least three distinct entities: Venus, Evening Star, and Morning Star. To see this, let us use 'C' (for 'congruence') to express the relation which Venus, the Evening Star, and the Morning Star, e. g., bear to themselves and, according to empirical evidence, to one another. (It is the relation of identity according to materialistic astronomy, but let us not prejudge this.) Then Morning Star C Evening Star. 0 Therefore, according to (ii), (Morning Star C Morning Star). (1) (3x) (x C Evening Star. 0 (x C Morning Star)). But also Evening Star C Evening Star. ""0 (Evening Star C Morning Star), so that, by (ii), (2) (3x) (x C Evening Star ""0 (x C Morning Star)). Since the matrix quantified in (1) and the matrix quantified in (2) are mutual contraries, the x whose existence is affirmed in (1) and the x \vhose existence is affirmed in (2) are two objects; so there must be at least t,vo objects x such that x C Evening Star. If \ve,vere to introduce the term 'Venus' we could infer a third such object in similar fashion. Thus it is that the contemplated version of quantified modal logic is committed to an ontology which repudiates material objects (such as the Evening Star properly so-called) and leaves only multiplicities of distinct objects (perhaps the Evening-Star-concept, the Morning-Star-concept, etc.) in their place. For, the ontology of a logic is nothing other than the range of admissible values of the variables of quantification. 8 A quite parallel conclusion could be drawn in higher logical types, to show that the contemplated version of quantified modal logic is committed to an ontology which repudiates classes and admits only attributes. But this consequence is likely to be regarded as less objectionable, from the point of vie'v at least of modal logicians, than the consequence concerning individuals. The modal logician who finds the repudiation of material objects (or, indeed, of classes) uncongenial may have recourse to either of the follo\ving alternatives. (a) He may regard his quantified modal logic as only a fragment.of the total' logic to which he is prepared to subscribe, so that the undesirably limited ontology. 8 See my Designation and existence, Journal of philosophy, vol. 36 (1939), pp. 701-709.

48 w. V. QUINE of the former comes to be only, a fragment of a more inclusive ontology which embraces also material objects (and perhaps even classes). Those variables of the total logic which do admit material objects (or classes) as values would then be withheld from quantified modal contexts, or limited to harmless manners of occurrence in them, 9 by special grammatical rules. The total logic would not be one in which we could meaningfully apply a modal operator to any matrix at will and then meaningfully quantify the result at will with respect to any free va~iable. (b) Hemayinsiston theuniversalityof his quantifiedmodallogic, butdisavow the criterion (ii),vhich underlies my argument. But then we have yet to see what might plausibly be put forward in its stead. HARVARD UNIVERSITY 9 Such is Church's procedure in A formulation of the logic of sense and denotation (abstract), this. JOURNAL, vol. 11 (1946), p. 31. I am indebted to Professor Church for several helpful letters in this connection.-i am also indebted, along more general lines, to Professor Rudolf Carnap; correspondence with him on modal logic over recent years has been very instrumental in clarifying my general position.