Rachel G.K. Singpurwalla

Similar documents
Are There Two Theories of Goodness in the Republic? A Response to Santas. Rachel Singpurwalla

Guide to the Republic as it sets up Plato s discussion of education in the Allegory of the Cave.

Aristotle on the Human Good

Why Pleasure Gains Fifth Rank: Against the Anti-Hedonist Interpretation of the Philebus 1

GORDON, J. (2012) PLATO S EROTIC WORLD: FROM COSMIC ORIGINS TO HUMAN DEATH. CAMBRIDGE, CAMBRIDGE UNIVERSITY PRESS.

Volume, pace, clarity and expression are appropriate. Tone of voice occasionally engages the audience

International Journal of Advancements in Research & Technology, Volume 4, Issue 11, November ISSN

Student Performance Q&A:

SUMMARY BOETHIUS AND THE PROBLEM OF UNIVERSALS

Pleasure, Pain, and Calm: A Puzzling Argument at Republic 583e1-8

English/Philosophy Department ENG/PHL 100 Level Course Descriptions and Learning Outcomes

Sidestepping the holes of holism

Integration, Ambivalence, and Mental Conflict

PHILOSOPHY. Grade: E D C B A. Mark range: The range and suitability of the work submitted

Virtues o f Authenticity: Essays on Plato and Socrates Republic Symposium Republic Phaedrus Phaedrus), Theaetetus

Conclusion. One way of characterizing the project Kant undertakes in the Critique of Pure Reason is by

2016 Summer Assignment: Honors English 10

Colonnade Program Course Proposal: Explorations Category

Overcoming Attempts to Dichotomize the Republic

WRITING A PRÈCIS. What is a précis? The definition

VIRTUE ETHICS-ARISTOTLE

The Theory and Practice of Virtue Education Edited by Tom Harrison and David I. Walker *

UNIT SPECIFICATION FOR EXCHANGE AND STUDY ABROAD

Abstract Several accounts of the nature of fiction have been proposed that draw on speech act

Course Syllabus. Ancient Greek Philosophy (direct to Philosophy) (toll-free; ask for the UM-Flint Philosophy Department)

RESEARCH WRITING. Copyright by Pearson Education, publishing as Longman Publishers Fowler/Aaron, The Little, Brown Handbook, Ninth Edition

An Aristotelian Puzzle about Definition: Metaphysics VII.12 Alan Code

0:24 Arthur Holmes (AH): Aristotle s ethics 2:18 AH: 2:43 AH: 4:14 AH: 5:34 AH: capacity 7:05 AH:

Care of the self: An Interview with Alexander Nehamas

The Strengths and Weaknesses of Frege's Critique of Locke By Tony Walton

Forms and Causality in the Phaedo. Michael Wiitala

McDowell, Demonstrative Concepts, and Nonconceptual Representational Content Wayne Wright

SpringBoard Academic Vocabulary for Grades 10-11

Rhetoric & Media Studies Sample Comprehensive Examination Question Ethics

Marx, Gender, and Human Emancipation

Theory or Theories? Based on: R.T. Craig (1999), Communication Theory as a field, Communication Theory, n. 2, May,

AP English Literature 1999 Scoring Guidelines

Strategies for Writing about Literature (from A Short Guide to Writing about Literature, Barnett and Cain)

The Rhetorical Modes Schemes and Patterns for Papers

Kent Academic Repository

The Concept of Nature

PHL 317K 1 Fall 2017 Overview of Weeks 1 5

AP ENGLISH LITERATURE AND COMPOSITION 2014 SCORING GUIDELINES

ENGLISH 160 WORLD LITERATURE THROUGH THE RENAISSANCE FALL PROFESSOR LESLEY DANZIGER Friday 9:35 a.m. - 12:45 p.m. Home Ec.

Theory or Theories? Based on: R.T. Craig (1999), Communication Theory as a field, Communication Theory, n. 2, May,

Mastering the Art Of. The English Essay. By Jeremiah Bourque

COMPREHENSIVE EXAMINATION SAMPLE QUESTIONS

Any attempt to revitalize the relationship between rhetoric and ethics is challenged

AP English Literature and Composition 2012 Scoring Guidelines

KINDS (NATURAL KINDS VS. HUMAN KINDS)

Feel Like a Natural Human: The Polis By Nature, and Human Nature in Aristotle s The Politics. by Laura Zax

City, University of London Institutional Repository. This version of the publication may differ from the final published version.

Categories and Schemata

Historical/Biographical

Plato and Aristotle: Mimesis, Catharsis, and the Functions of Art

ENGL S092 Improving Writing Skills ENGL S110 Introduction to College Writing ENGL S111 Methods of Written Communication

Nicomachean Ethics. p. 1. Aristotle. Translated by W. D. Ross. Book II. Moral Virtue (excerpts)

Hegel's Absolute: An Introduction to Reading the Phenomenology of Spirit

WHAT BELONGS IN MY RESEARCH PAPER?

Julie K. Ward. Ancient Philosophy 31 (2011) Mathesis Publications

The Value of Mathematics within the 'Republic'

Deconstruction is a way of understanding how something was created and breaking something down into smaller parts.

Book Review. John Dewey s Philosophy of Spirit, with the 1897 Lecture on Hegel. Jeff Jackson. 130 Education and Culture 29 (1) (2013):

ARISTOTLE ON SCIENTIFIC VS NON-SCIENTIFIC DISCOURSE. Philosophical / Scientific Discourse. Author > Discourse > Audience

Myth and Philosophy in Plato s Phaedrus

AP Language And Composition Chapter 1: An Introduction to Rhetoric

RESEARCH WRITING. Copyright by Pearson Education, publishing as Longman Aaron, The Little, Brown Compact Handbook, Sixth Edition

CONCERNING music there are some questions

Literary Theory and Criticism

Dawn M. Phillips The real challenge for an aesthetics of photography

Art and Morality. Sebastian Nye LECTURE 2. Autonomism and Ethicism

Aristotle. By Sarah, Lina, & Sufana

AP Literature and Composition

Plato s Forms. Feb. 3, 2016

Twentieth Excursus: Reference Magnets and the Grounds of Intentionality

Cite. Infer. to determine the meaning of something by applying background knowledge to evidence found in a text.

Homer and Tragedy: Persuasion

Literary Criticism. Literary critics removing passages that displease them. By Charles Joseph Travies de Villiers in 1830

Moralistic Criticism. Post Modern Moral Criticism asks how the work in question affects the reader.

HEGEL S CONCEPT OF ACTION

AP English Literature and Composition

Aristotle s Three Ways to Persuade. Logos Ethos Pathos

Logic and argumentation techniques. Dialogue types, rules

What counts as a convincing scientific argument? Are the standards for such evaluation

AP English Literature and Composition 2004 Scoring Guidelines Form B

1. Physically, because they are all dressed up to look their best, as beautiful as they can.


Reading/Study Guide: Lyotard. The Postmodern Condition

Writing a Critical or Rhetorical Analysis

Persuasive Speech Rubric

The Human Intellect: Aristotle s Conception of Νοῦς in his De Anima. Caleb Cohoe

ART216: Term Project

RHETORICAL DEVICES. Rhetoric: the art of effective, persuasive speaking or writing

in order to formulate and communicate meaning, and our capacity to use symbols reaches far beyond the basic. This is not, however, primarily a book

McDougal Littell Literature Writing Workshops Grade 11 ** topic to be placed into red folder

Plato s dialogue the Symposium takes

Claim: refers to an arguable proposition or a conclusion whose merit must be established.

The art and study of using language effectively

Stenberg, Shari J. Composition Studies Through a Feminist Lens. Anderson: Parlor Press, Print. 120 pages.

SAMPLE COURSE OUTLINE PHILOSOPHY AND ETHICS GENERAL YEAR 12

Transcription:

470 Gender and Rhetoric in Plato's Political Thought. By Michael S. Kochin. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. 2002. Pp. viii + 164. $40.00 (cloth). ISBN 0-521-80852-9. Rachel G.K. Singpurwalla This book advances the thesis that the Republic and the Laws should not be read as straightforward political treatises, but as examples of political rhetoric. According to Kochin. the rhetorical aim of both works is to turn men away from gendered conceptions of excellence and toward a standard of human excellence that includes the virtues of both men and women as traditionally understood. Gi ven the purported aim of Kochin' s project, the precise nature and role of rhetoric in the book is remarkably obscure. Kochin never sufficiently distinguishes rhetoric from other sorts of speech: he defines rhetoric as 'the art of invoking conventional understandings of the good and the just so as to move one's audience' (2). But on this account, the claim that we should understand Plato's dialogues as rhetorical is not at all illuminating. for this account fails to distinguish rhetoric from other persuasive uses of language, including straightforward philosophical argumentation. And indeed, the majority of Kochin' s book reads like a straightforward interpretation of the political theses and arguments of the Republic and the Laws. In some instances, however, Kochin employs a more robust sense of rhetoric: he argues that Plato does not really believe all of the claims that he makes in the Republic and LaM'S, but merely uses certain ideas in order to move his audience. The grounds that Kochin provides for reading Plato in this way, however, are feeble at best. Thus, his general thesis that the Republic and the Laws should be read as examples of political rhetoric is either uninformative or indefensible. Despite this difficulty, Kochin does put forward numerous original and provocative interpretations of Plato's political theses, most of which can be presented and evaluated independently of any consideration of rhetoric. In what follows, I summarize the main line of argument of Kochin's book. I then take issue with the most important instance where Kochin explicitly treats Plato's remarks as rhetorical in the robust sense. I conclude that Kochin provides insufficient grounds for thinking that Plato is not reporting his own convictions. Moreover, the rhetorical strategy that Kochin attributes to Plato is both a weak rhetorical strategy and inconsistent with Plato's conception of art and education as presented in Republic ii and iii. Accordingly, we have no reason to think of the Republic and the Laws as examples of political rhetoric in any distinct or interesting sense of the word. The book is divided into three parts. In the first part of the book (chapters 1 and 2), Kochin describes conventional Greek views of excellence or virtue (arete) and explains Plato's criticism of these conventional views. Conventional Greek views of virtue were highly 'gendered', in the sense that men and women were held to different standards of excellence. Kochin argues that there were two com- Ancient Philosophy 24 (2004) Mathesis Publications

471 peting conceptions of the good man: the civic and the heroic conceptions of masculinity. According to both conceptions, the good man must be courageous (andreia) and so master his fears. The two conceptions diverge, ho\vever, with regard to the virtue of moderation (sophrosune). According to the civic conception, the true man masters his desires. Indeed, on this conception. a man who submits to his desires for food. sex, or drink is seen as weak and eft'cminate. On the heroic conception, hy contrast, the true man eschews all forms of self-control: the real man has the courage and the skill to do whatever it takes to satisfy whatever desires he happens to have. Here, we may think of the manly ideals put forward by Callicles in the Gorgias and Thrasymachus in the Republic. According to Kochin, a two-fold account of femininity emerged as the negation of the civic and heroic conceptions of masculinity: women were seen as naturally lacking both courage and moderation. Accordingly, women were excluded from public life and relegated to the private sphere. The only virtue appropriate for women, then, was moderation, and in particular. chastity. Kochin proceeds to argue that Plato thought that the gendered conception of the virtues was problematic for at least two reasons. First, the civic conception of masculinity taught that moderation and self-control were good hut only for the purpose of later self-aggrandizement in either the political or military spheres. Thus, ordinary Greek men saw moderation as an instrumental and so defeasible, good at best. Second, the various conceptions of virtue are riddled with conflict. The civic conception, for example, which puts forth moderation and justice as ideals, conflicts with the heroic conception, which holds that moderation and justice are for those too cowardly, weak, and 'unmanly' to take what they want for themselves. Additionally, hy promulgating both the civic and the heroic ideals of masculinity, the city simultaneously taught that self-controlled male citizens ought to rule over uncontrolled female citizens and that self-control is unmanly and thus suitable only for women. In the second part of the book (chapters 3 and 4), Kochin provides an interpretation of the Republic according to which Plato's primary aim is to persuade men to turn away from both the civic and the heroic conceptions of the good man and towards a standard of excellence that vindicates both justice and moderation. To achieve this goal Plato must rcplace gendered conceptions of virtue with a standard of excellence that includes moderation and justice as real goods and thus incorporates the virtues of both men and women as traditionally understood. Kochin argues that Plato puts forward the philosopher as the model for this single standard of human excellence (anthropine arete). According to Kochin, Plato argues against the heroic conception of masculinity by allying himself. for rhetorical purposes only, with the civic conception of masculinity ane! descrihing the lack of self-control and lack of freedom that characterizes the life of the hero or tyrant as 'womanly' and thus unworthy of a real man. Kochin further contends that Plato attempts to dismantle the civic conception of masculinity by 're-valuing' war and political life in general such that neither is for the purpose of self-aggrandizement or exercising one's manliness.

472 Plato does this by changing the purpose of war from self-aggrandizement to selfpreservation, education, rearing, and reproduction, and by allowing women to be leaders and warriors. In the last third of the book (chapters 5 and 6), Kochin turns his attention to the Laws. Kochin argues that Plato describes Magnesia as a 'second best' because it does not aim to cultivate in its citizens a single standard of human excellence, but reverts hack to gendered conceptions of excellence. Magnesia fails to aim at a single standard of excellence for men and women because it, unlike the city described in the Republic, is built upon private families and property and the sovereignty of the law. According to Kochin, Plato holds that the reintroduction of the family and thus of the private sphere prevents women from attaining certain virtues. In particular, they fail to develop a certain responsiveness to spirit (thi/mos). Additionally, the reintroduction of private property and the sovereignty of law foster 'manly' spiritedness in men. According to Kochin. despite the fact that the organization of the city makes it impossible for men and women to aspire to the same standard of excellence, Plato still attempts to modify the gendered conception of virtue in at least three ways. First, Plato attempts to ensure that women are not relegated solely to the private sphere. Second, Plato encourages moderation in men by, again, allying himself with the civic conception of virtue, and describing lack of self-control as 'womanly' and thus unfit for men. And finally, Plato legislates the Nocturnal Council, an institutional organ designed to correct the laws and move the citizens of Magnesia toward the pursuit of a truly unified human excellence. It should be clear ii'om this brief summary that the only instance where Kochin explicitly argues that Plato's remarks are rhetorical in the sense of insincere is in the case of Plato's disparaging remarks about women in the Republic (see, for example, 395d, 469d). According to Kochin, Plato takes up. for rhetorical purposes on!\". the aspect of the civic conception of excellence that portrays lack of control as effeminate and so unworthy of real men. He does this to convince men to turn away from the heroic conception of virtue and aspire to moderation and self-control instead. Kochin says, We must continually recall that Socrates attacks the pretensions of masculinity before an all-male audience. His occasional use of sexist language is a concession to the limitations of his audience before his speeches have done their work. Greek men understand what is good as what is manly; whatever Socrates can portray as womanish, whether it he Achilles' excessive lamentation or his defiling Hector's corpse, his male listeners will henceforth see as bad if his regendering of these practices is sllccessful. (41) Thus, according to Kochin, Plato does not truly endorse these misogynist statements; he makes them for rhetorical purposes only. Koehin's claim that Plato's sexist remarks are rhetorical only is interesting in its own right, for if true, it would provide a resolution to the vexed issue of the tension between Plato's pro-

473 gressive and derisive attitudes towards women in the Republic. But what reason do we have for thinking that Plato's comments are rhetorical? Unfortunately, Kochin's justification for reading the Repuhlic and the Laws as rhetorical in the sense of insincere is remarkably weak. Kochin defends his reading of Plato as rhetorician by citing the fact that Plato uses encomiums to praise Eros in the Snnposiwl/ and the just life in the Gorgius (15). It should be obvious, however. that we cannot infer from the fact that Plato sometimes uses words with the intent of emotionally moving his audience that he uses words with the intent of emotionally moving his audience in the Republic and the Laws. In addition, we cannot infer that Plato is not committed to the claims that he makes when he is trying to be persuasive in this way. Kochin also argues that Plato's concern with the meaning of justice in the Republic illustrates the rhetorical effort to distinguish between apparent and real goods (15). But, again, it should be obvious that the effort to distinguish between apparent and real goods is also, and indeed perhaps more clearly, an example of the general philosophical effort to distinguish appearances from reality. Thus, the fact that Plato is concerned with uncovering the true meaning of justice in the Republic lends absolutely no support to the claim that the ReplIhlic is a rhetorical work in any interesting or distinct sense of the term. Finally, Kochin argues that the Laws should be read as an example of rhetoric by stating, without providing any citation, that Plato adds persuasive preludes to the laws' commands and prohibitions (15-16). Again, however. this fact gives us no reason to think that either the whole dialogue is an example of persuasive speech or that Plato is not committed to the claims he makes in his persuasive speeches. Perhaps, though, the fact that Kochin's claim that Plato's sexist remarks are rhetorical, if true, would provide a resolution to a serious tension in Plato's work gives us some reason for taking Kochin's thesis seriously. Since Kochin provides insufficient textual grounds for thinking that Plato's remarks are rhetorical, we can think of Koehin's claim as a speculative resolution to the tension. Is it plausihie that Plato's sexist remarks are simply part of a rhetorical aim of turning men away from gendered conceptions of virtue'? I think not, for this would be a highly questionable rhetorical strategy. Kochin argues that Plato's aim is to persuade men to value women, to see them as equals so that they learn wholeheartedly to value certain traits. such as moderation, traditionally seen as feminine (133). At the same ti me, however, Koehin argues that Plato wants to persuade men to reject certain hehaviors hy portraying them as womanly and therefore undesirable. That is, he continues and reinforces the tradition of viewing anything that is womanly as bad. But how could this lead to anything but inconsistent beliefs and attitudes in Plato's audience'? Koehin argues that Plato's sexist remarks are 'a concession to the limitations of his audience before his speeches have clone their work' (41). But how could Plato's speeches convince his audience to see women as the equals of men by reinforcing the prejudice that anything 'womanly' is bad? The rhetorical strategy seems incoherent. On Kochin's account, Plato's purported method of rhetoric is at oclds with itself in exactly the same way that the

474 ordinary Greek view on gender and virtue was at odds vyith itself: it yields inconsistent ideals. Moreover, we know that Plato was particularly attuned to the danger of instilling contradictory beliefs in individuals. Indeed, the philosophy of art and education that Plato presents in Republic ii and iii is explicitly designed to avoid instilling beliefs in children that will conflict with the true beliefs that they ought to have as adults (see, for example, 377b). Thus.. it seems highly unlikely that Plato would intentionally put forward inconsistent ideals in the way that Koehin describes. Thus, Kochin's claim that Plato's sexist remarks are rhetorical both lacks textual support and is inconsistent with Platonic ideals. My discussion of Kochin's claim that Plato's sexist remarks are rhetorical is illustrative of the main problem with his project: Kochin never gives us explicit and defensible standards for determining whether Plato's remarks should be read as examples of insincere rhetoric as opposed to expression s of Plato's own beliefs. As I mentioned at the outset of the review, most of Kochin's book reads as a straightforward interpretive essay on Plato's views on politics and gender; the issue of rhetoric, in any interesting and distinct sense of the word, seems irrelevant to most of Kochin' s book. Only very rarely does the notion of rhetoric in the sense of insincere seem crucial for Kochin' s understanding of Plato. But it is not up to Kochin simply to choose which of Plato's remarks are rhetorical and which are sincere. And yet, in the absence of independent defensible standards for determining which of Plato's remarks are rhetorical and which are sincere, Kochin is simply making his own choice, where this choice probably has more to do with Kochin's own views than Plato's. Nonetheless, because the notion of rhetoric in any robust sense plays such a small role in Kochin's book, we can still appreciate the majority of his project. Of course it is altogether plausible to think that Plato is interested in critiquing ordinary Greek ideals of the good man and replacing them with his own ideal. Furthermore, much of Kochin's account of Plato's critique and remedy of ordinary Greek ideals is interesting and plausible. Kochin simply gives us no reason to think that Plato does not mean everything that he says. In sum, then, I would recommend Kochin's book to anyone with an interest in Plato's views on politics and gender; I would simply advise the reader not to take the claims about rhetoric too seriously. Department of Philosophy Southern Illinois University, Edwardsville Edwardsville IL 62026-1433