Book Review. John Dewey s Philosophy of Spirit, with the 1897 Lecture on Hegel. Jeff Jackson. 130 Education and Culture 29 (1) (2013):

Similar documents
By Rahel Jaeggi Suhrkamp, 2014, pbk 20, ISBN , 451pp. by Hans Arentshorst

James SCOTT JOHNSTON, John Dewey s Earlier Logical Theory

UNIT SPECIFICATION FOR EXCHANGE AND STUDY ABROAD

Bas C. van Fraassen, Scientific Representation: Paradoxes of Perspective, Oxford University Press, 2008.

6 The Analysis of Culture

PH th Century Philosophy Ryerson University Department of Philosophy Mondays, 3-6pm Fall 2010

Action, Criticism & Theory for Music Education

Mind, Thinking and Creativity

John Dewey s Philosophy of Spirit, with the 1897 Lecture on Hegel, Fordham University Press, New York 2010, pp. 197, by Roberto Gronda.

A Comprehensive Critical Study of Gadamer s Hermeneutics

Misc Fiction Irony Point of view Plot time place social environment

HEGEL, ANALYTIC PHILOSOPHY AND THE RETURN OF METAPHYISCS Simon Lumsden

Philosophy Pathways Issue th December 2016

REVIEW ARTICLE IDEAL EMBODIMENT: KANT S THEORY OF SENSIBILITY

Moral Judgment and Emotions

Penultimate draft of a review which will appear in History and Philosophy of. $ ISBN: (hardback); ISBN:

Hamletmachine: The Objective Real and the Subjective Fantasy. Heiner Mueller s play Hamletmachine focuses on Shakespeare s Hamlet,

Chapter Six Integral Spirituality

Chapter 2: Karl Marx Test Bank

Truth and Method in Unification Thought: A Preparatory Analysis

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at

A Letter from Louis Althusser on Gramsci s Thought

CHAPTER II LITERATURE REVIEW, CONCEPTS, AND THEORITICAL FRAMEWORK

RESPONSE AND REJOINDER

observation and conceptual interpretation

Sidestepping the holes of holism

Feel Like a Natural Human: The Polis By Nature, and Human Nature in Aristotle s The Politics. by Laura Zax

CHAPTER II LITERATURE REVIEW. In this chapter, the research needs to be supported by relevant theories.

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

Georg Simmel's Sociology of Individuality

Renaissance Old Masters and Modernist Art History-Writing

PAUL REDDING S CONTINENTAL IDEALISM (AND DELEUZE S CONTINUATION OF THE IDEALIST TRADITION) Sean Bowden

Review of David Woodruff Smith and Amie L. Thomasson, eds., Phenomenology and the Philosophy of Mind, 2005, Oxford University Press.

Philosophy of Science: The Pragmatic Alternative April 2017 Center for Philosophy of Science University of Pittsburgh ABSTRACTS

MAURICE MANDELBAUM HISTORY, MAN, & REASON A STUDY IN NINETEENTH-CENTURY THOUGHT THE JOHNS HOPKINS PRESS: BALTIMORE AND LONDON

Issue 5, Summer Published by the Durham University Undergraduate Philosophy Society

Scientific Philosophy

Presented as part of the Colloquium Sponsored by the Lonergan Project at Marquette University on Lonergan s Philosophy and Theology

The Strengths and Weaknesses of Frege's Critique of Locke By Tony Walton

The Kelvingrove Review Issue 3

What is Character? David Braun. University of Rochester. In "Demonstratives", David Kaplan argues that indexicals and other expressions have a

TRAGIC THOUGHTS AT THE END OF PHILOSOPHY

Undercutting the Realism-Irrealism Debate: John Dewey and the Neo-Pragmatists

Hans-Georg Gadamer, Truth and Method, 2d ed. transl. by Joel Weinsheimer and Donald G. Marshall (London : Sheed & Ward, 1989), pp [1960].

scholars have imagined and dealt with religious people s imaginings and dealings

The Concept of Nature

HEGEL AND THE HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY

Culture and Art Criticism

Sociology. Open Session on Answer Writing. (Session 2; Date: 7 July 2018) Topics. Paper I. 4. Sociological Thinkers (Karl Marx and Emile Durkheim)

Any attempt to revitalize the relationship between rhetoric and ethics is challenged

THE 13th INTERNATIONAL CONFERENCE OF. ISSEI International Society for the Study of European Ideas in cooperation with the University of Cyprus

A person represented in a story

CHAPTER SIX. Habitation, structure, meaning

CAROL HUNTS University of Kansas

S/A 4074: Ritual and Ceremony. Lecture 14: Culture, Symbolic Systems, and Action 1

AN INTRODUCTION OF THE STUDY OF LITERATURE

2015 Arizona Arts Standards. Theatre Standards K - High School

Michael Lüthy Retracing Modernist Praxis: Richard Shiff

What do our appreciation of tonal music and tea roses, our acquisition of the concepts

In Defense of the Contingently Nonconcrete

Heideggerian Ontology: A Philosophic Base for Arts and Humanties Education

Reality According to Language and Concepts Ben G. Yacobi *

Mark Jarman. Body and Soul. essays on poetry. Ann Arbor

JOHN KEATS: THE NOTION OF NEGATIVE CAPABILITY AND POETIC VISION

Philosophy of History

Karen Hutzel The Ohio State University, Columbus, Ohio REFERENCE BOOK REVIEW 327

SUMMARY BOETHIUS AND THE PROBLEM OF UNIVERSALS

IIL-HEGEL'S TREATMENT OF THE CATE- GORIES OF OUALITY.

Mixed Methods: In Search of a Paradigm

Necessity in Kant; Subjective and Objective

Ralph K. Hawkins Bethel College Mishawaka, Indiana

Notes: Short Stories

An Aristotelian Puzzle about Definition: Metaphysics VII.12 Alan Code

Escapism and Luck. problem of moral luck posed by Joel Feinberg, Thomas Nagel, and Bernard Williams. 2

The Polish Peasant in Europe and America. W. I. Thomas and Florian Znaniecki

Writing an Honors Preface

Marxist Criticism. Critical Approach to Literature

Department of Philosophy Florida State University

Moral Geography and Exploration of the Moral Possibility Space

CST/CAHSEE GRADE 9 ENGLISH-LANGUAGE ARTS (Blueprints adopted by the State Board of Education 10/02)

The Kantian and Hegelian Sublime

(as methodology) are not always distinguished by Steward: he says,

DESCRIBING THE STORM CHAPTER THREE

An Ancient Quarrel in Hegel s Phenomenology

Thai Architecture in Anthropological Perspective

(1) Writing Essays: An Overview. Essay Writing: Purposes. Essay Writing: Product. Essay Writing: Process. Writing to Learn Writing to Communicate

Kuhn Formalized. Christian Damböck Institute Vienna Circle University of Vienna

outline the paper's understanding of play through the sociologically oriented characterization

Pragmatism and Idealism

Hegel, Subjectivity, and Metaphysics: A Heideggerean Interpretation

Futurity, Omniscience, and the End of History: A Vindication of Hegel s Claim to Absolute Knowing

Attitudes to teaching and learning in The History Boys

Natika Newton, Foundations of Understanding. (John Benjamins, 1996). 210 pages, $34.95.

Strategies for Writing about Literature (from A Short Guide to Writing about Literature, Barnett and Cain)

Creative Actualization: A Meliorist Theory of Values

Second Grade: National Visual Arts Core Standards

A New Approach to the Paradox of Fiction Pete Faulconbridge

AP English Literature 1999 Scoring Guidelines

SHORT STORY NOTES Fall 2013

3. The knower s perspective is essential in the pursuit of knowledge. To what extent do you agree?

Transcription:

Book Review John Dewey s Philosophy of Spirit, with the 1897 Lecture on Hegel Jeff Jackson John R. Shook and James A. Good, John Dewey s Philosophy of Spirit, with the 1897 Lecture on Hegel. New York: Fordham University Press, 2010. xii + 197 pages. ISBN 978-0-8232-3139-3. $25.00 (pbk.) John Shook and James Good have each made significant contributions to the scholarly discussion of John Dewey s permanent Hegelian deposit. In this collection, they come together to further develop their respective analyses of Dewey s Hegelianism. The volume combines two essays, one from each of the authors, in addition to the definitive text of Dewey s own 1897 lecture on Hegel, given at the University of Chicago, and entitled Hegel s Philosophy of Spirit. In comparison to Shook s earlier, more comprehensive work on Dewey s relationship to Hegel, Dewey s Empirical Theory of Knowledge and Reality (2000), and Good s similarly intensive treatment, A Search for Unity in Diversity: The Permanent Hegelian Deposit in the Philosophy of John Dewey (2006), the two essays, even in combination with one another, are somewhat fractional and incomplete. The essays succeed, however, in furthering our understanding of the way Dewey s Hegelianism can illuminate his mature philosophy. In the first essay, Dewey s Naturalized Philosophy of Spirit and Religion, Shook explores how Dewey maintained a place for religious faith in his pragmatism despite his antipathy toward organized religion. Drawing on several of Dewey s texts, and in particular A Common Faith (1934), Shook interprets Deweyan faith as a practical tool which sustains individuals in pursuit of their self-chosen ends (34-35). For Dewey, an ideal cannot be achieved without overcoming obstacles in its pursuit. Since persistence does not guarantee success, faith in the possibility of achieving the ideal is necessary for persevering through inevitable setbacks. Alluding to Dewey s distinction between religion and the religious, Shook describes how Dewey saw adherence to organized religion as ineffective for coping in a fundamentally uncertain world. Dewey viewed any belief in the existence of a divine power to be incompatible with naturalism and quite irrelevant for a genuinely religious life (19). Religious individuals, on the other hand, rather than simply trusting in the 130 Education and Culture 29 (1) (2013): 130 134

Review: John Dewey s Philosophy of Spirit 131 protection of an external divine entity, possess the necessary faith not to abandon pursuit of self-chosen ends when confronted with a devastating loss: The religious, according to Dewey, do not surrender their ideals and moral convictions in the face of tragedy, and neither do they repose in certainty about guaranteed ideals (36). This is the pragmatic value of Deweyan faith; and for Shook, it exhibits substantial Hegelian influence. He presents Dewey s notion that there is religious quality to our practical engagements with our surroundings as a translation of Hegel s concept of the divine manifesting itself through purposive human action. He argues that Dewey understood and presented Hegel as taking this generally pragmatic approach to religion (17). Shook s analysis thus allows us to conceptualize Dewey s use of religious language in terms consistent with his pragmatism, once we see his religious views as a prominent illustration of the way that he remained indebted to Hegel throughout his long career (31). In the second essay, Rereading Dewey s Permanent Hegelian Deposit, Good provides a sustained analysis of Dewey s 1897 lecture on Hegel. His purpose is to further develop the central claim of his 2006 book, namely, that Dewey s break with the British neo-hegelians during the 1890s was not a break with Hegel himself. Rather, it was a move toward a humanist/historicist reading of Hegel and away from the neo-hegelians metaphysical/theological reading. Good explains how it is assumed that Dewey s pragmatic notion that ideas have real effects in the world was at odds with Hegelian philosophy. But Dewey s lecture Hegel s Philosophy of Spirit demonstrates that he saw this pragmatic account of ideas in Hegel (66). Good particularly emphasizes the way Dewey s claim [in the 1897 lecture] that Hegel was a great actualist markedly contrasts with the common characterization of Hegel as the grand metaphysician who reduced the particularities of experience to transient nodes of a dynamic, eternal, and transcendent supreme being (66). This accurately depicts Dewey and Hegel s shared distaste for mere abstraction from concrete action, and their conviction that any idea, or concept, only attains actuality in being progressively worked out through experience. Thus, in contrast to the static, transcendent absolute that neo-hegelians such as T.H. Green find so attractive, Dewey s Hegel is committed to the continuous engagement with the practical conflicts of ordinary experience, and does not require any entity separate from experience to drive this movement: Dewey s lecture Hegel s Philosophy of Spirit, in conjunction with Dewey s critique of Green s moral thought, demonstrates that his rejection of neo-hegelianism during the early 1890s should not be equated with a rejection of Hegel (71-72). For Dewey, then, the Hegelian Absolute refers not to any static, divine achievement, but rather to the continuous, infinite development of human achievements. So what is Dewey s philosophy of spirit? Neither Shook nor Good clearly answers this question. In particular, I think the authors could have been more precise in their definitions of Hegel s philosophy of spirit, and in their accounts of how this Volume 29 (1) 2013

132 Jeff Jackson concept connects with Dewey s pragmatism. Shook asserts that Dewey s philosophy of spirit is his theory of the social conditions for the growth of individuality (55). In slightly different terms, Good explains how the unity of Hegel s absolute spirit is constantly being sundered and re-created by adversity and diversity (Hegel s negation). Hence particular identities are not a mere means to a final state of maturation in which they will be abolished but are the essential engine of its never-ending growth (61). He then states that Dewey s philosophy of education, which characterizes education as perpetual growth... formulates a philosophy of spirit (61). I would not say either of these descriptions is off the mark; it is certainly true that Dewey s ideal of self-directed, continuous growth cannot exist apart from necessary social conditions, and it is true that Hegel s Spirit requires particular identities to drive its growth much like Dewey's description of individuals and communities that continuously develop through the activities of communication, inquiry, and action. However, I think we can draw a more precise link between Spirit and pragmatism, and explain in clearer terms what is required of individuals and collectivities if they are to contribute to Spirit s continuous progression. In The Phenomenology of Spirit ([1807] 1977), Hegel states that Spirit is the knowledge of oneself in the externalization of oneself; the being that is the movement of retaining its self-identity in its otherness (459). The being which manifests Spirit thus sees itself in what negates it, and moves Spirit forward by negating negation. In the 1897 lecture on Hegel presented in this volume, Dewey emphasizes the link between Spirit and the negation of negation. He points out that for Hegel, it is of the very nature of... spirit, to oppose itself and through this opposition to reach its own realized development (107). Spirit is then actualized by the movement to negate such negation: opposition is constantly overcome in the very life of the spirit itself (107). On Dewey s reading, Hegel s Spirit is not separate from individuals lived experience, but rather realized through it: the individual is himself an expression of the absolute spirit... (113). This connection of Spirit with the individual act of negating negation, however, is not highlighted by Shook or Good, despite Dewey s emphasis on this point in his lecture. For Dewey (and Hegel), individuals demonstrate a spiritual (rather than merely natural ) existence by stamping themselves onto the world in a reflective, self-chosen way; and this spiritual action requires [utilizing] the material of nature by forming out of it ends and ideals and then proceeding to realize these ends (119). Dewey s philosophy of spirit is thus intimately connected with individuals practical activity. Individuals formulate their own ends, and give themselves objective existence through action toward those ends, which, in turn, drives the actualization of spirit. Hegel s Spirit is the distinctly human power of overcoming contradiction, or, of synthesizing the opposing elements generated by any human action. So, it is required of spiritual individuals to see themselves in the negation brought about by new experiences, and to put forward the effort to negate the ne- E&C Education and Culture

Review: John Dewey s Philosophy of Spirit 133 gation. That Dewey shares such a philosophy of spirit with Hegel is evident in The Quest for Certainty (1929). He describes a scientific attitude which is capable of enjoying the doubtful (228), and which can effect the transformation of the obscure and perplexing situations of experience into clear and resolved situations (124). This negation of negations, this resolution of problematic situations, requires that individuals initially feel unsettled and anxious about a disruption in the situation. It is an experience that Dewey describes in How We Think (1910) as a condition of mental unrest and disturbance (13). As he explains in Human Nature and Conduct (1922), this disturbed state is necessary if individuals are to take the already accomplished work of Spirit, the long record of past experimentation in conduct, and move Spirit forward by observ[ing] how old principles actually work under new conditions, and modify[ing] them so that they will be more effectual instruments in judging new cases (239). By moving Spirit forward, individuals generate greater certainty for themselves in a world where complete certainty is unattainable an important insight for both Dewey and Hegel. The connection between Hegel s Spirit and Dewey s pragmatism can thus be found in their shared focus on the most effective ways of overcoming the obstacles intrinsic to lived experience for the purpose of generating a more stable future. Hence, if we are to identify a Hegel-inspired philosophy of spirit in Dewey s thought, and also shore up the imprecise aspects of Shook and Good s analyses, it is worthwhile to recognize Spirit as a movement through contradiction which is progressively actualized through individuals own pragmatic activity. Overall, this volume represents a constructive extension of the authors previous work on Dewey s relationship with Hegel. Shook s 2000 book argued that Dewey, instead of breaking from Hegelian idealism, developed a consistent idealism which dealt seriously with lived experience. Good s 2006 work went further by distinguishing Dewey s humanist/historicist interpretation of Hegel from the metaphysical/theological reading by the British neo-hegelians. The essays in this volume are narrower in scope, but they do show how Dewey s religious faith can be illuminated through his relationship to Hegel, and how his 1897 lecture on Hegel further differentiates his own reading of Hegel from that of the neo-hegelians. I would have liked greater precision in the conceptualization of Dewey s philosophy of spirit, specifically how the movement of spirit is carried forward through individual action. Nevertheless, Shook and Good s volume successfully makes the case that we cannot fully understand Dewey s pragmatism without also first gaining a better understanding of Hegel s philosophy of spirit. References Dewey, John. How We Think. Boston, MA: D. C. Heath, 1910.. Human Nature and Conduct. New York: Henry Holt, 1922..The Quest for Certainty. New York: Minton, Balch & Company, 1929. Volume 29 (1) 2013

134 Jeff Jackson. A Common Faith. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1934. Good, James A. A Search for Unity in Diversity: The Permanent Hegelian Deposit in the Philosophy of John Dewey. Lanham, MD: Lexington Books, 2006. Hegel, Georg W.F. The Phenomenology of Spirit. New York: Oxford University Press, 1977. (Original work published 1807). Shook, John R. Dewey s Empirical Theory of Knowledge and Reality. Nashville, TN: Vanderbilt University Press, 2000. Jeff Jackson is a graduate student in the political science department at the University of California, Los Angeles. E-mail: jjack32@ucla.edu E&C Education and Culture