Poetry and Play in Kant s Critique of Judgment

Similar documents
Kant: Notes on the Critique of Judgment

Conclusion. One way of characterizing the project Kant undertakes in the Critique of Pure Reason is by

1/10. The A-Deduction

that would join theoretical philosophy (metaphysics) and practical philosophy (ethics)?

Immanuel Kant Critique of Pure Reason

What is the Object of Thinking Differently?

THESIS MIND AND WORLD IN KANT S THEORY OF SENSATION. Submitted by. Jessica Murski. Department of Philosophy

REVIEW ARTICLE IDEAL EMBODIMENT: KANT S THEORY OF SENSIBILITY

Jacek Surzyn University of Silesia Kant s Political Philosophy

The Role of Imagination in Kant's Theory of Reflective Judgment. Johannes Haag

Rethinking the Aesthetic Experience: Kant s Subjective Universality

Categories and Schemata

KANT S TRANSCENDENTAL LOGIC

1/8. Axioms of Intuition

1/9. The B-Deduction

The Case for Absolute Spontaneity in Kant s Critique of Pure Reason. La defensa de la espontaneidad absoluta en la Crítica de la razón pura de Kant

1/8. The Third Paralogism and the Transcendental Unity of Apperception

The Pure Concepts of the Understanding and Synthetic A Priori Cognition: the Problem of Metaphysics in the Critique of Pure Reason and a Solution

Practical Action First Critique Foundations *

What do our appreciation of tonal music and tea roses, our acquisition of the concepts

The aim of this paper is to explore Kant s notion of death with special attention paid to

Architecture as the Psyche of a Culture

Biological Purposiveness and Analogical Reflection

Kant IV The Analogies The Schematism updated: 2/2/12. Reading: 78-88, In General

ANALOGY, SCHEMATISM AND THE EXISTENCE OF GOD

Summary of the Transcendental Ideas

4 Unity in Variety: Theoretical, Practical and Aesthetic Reason in Kant

From Individuality to Universality: The Role of Aesthetic Education in Kant

Self-Consciousness and Knowledge

Notes on Gadamer, The Relevance of the Beautiful

The Aesthetic Idea and the Unity of Cognitive Faculties in Kant's Aesthetics

Necessity in Kant; Subjective and Objective

Immanuel Kant, the author of the Copernican revolution in philosophy,

genesis in kant notes

Making Modal Distinctions: Kant on the possible, the actual, and the intuitive understanding.

The Polish Peasant in Europe and America. W. I. Thomas and Florian Znaniecki

A Study of the Bergsonian Notion of <Sensibility>

KANT S THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE

1 For the purposes of this paper, I will focus only on Kant s account of sublimity in nature, setting aside the vexed issues

Kant s Critique of Judgment

The Kantian and Hegelian Sublime

Review of Carolyn Korsmeyer, Savoring Disgust: The foul and the fair. in aesthetics (Oxford University Press pp (PBK).

Kant's Aesthetics and Teleology

The Aesthetic of Ugliness A Kantian Perspective

Having the World in View: Essays on Kant, Hegel, and Sellars

Humanities 4: Lecture 19. Friedrich Schiller: On the Aesthetic Education of Man

Narrating the Self: Parergonality, Closure and. by Holly Franking. hermeneutics focus attention on the transactional aspect of the aesthetic

Kant and the Problem of Experience

Immanuel Kant s Theory of Knowledge: Exploring the Relation between Sensibility and Understanding Wendell Allan Marinay

Imagination and Contingency: Overcoming the Problems of Kant s Transcendental Deduction

1/9. Descartes on Simple Ideas (2)

THE CRITIQUE OF JUDGEMENT PART 1: CRITIQUE OF AESTHETIC JUDGEMENT

The Second Copernican Turn of Kant s Philosophy 1

IMPORTANT QUOTATIONS

index 417 Fricke, Christel, 365, 372, 375,

INTRODUCTION. Cambridge University Press

The Place of Logic within Kant s Philosophy

SocioBrains THE INTEGRATED APPROACH TO THE STUDY OF ART

Philosophical Background to 19 th Century Modernism

None DEREE COLLEGE SYLLABUS FOR: PH 4028 KANT AND GERMAN IDEALISM UK LEVEL 6 UK CREDITS: 15 US CREDITS: 3/0/3. (Updated SPRING 2016) PREREQUISITES:

1/6. The Anticipations of Perception

Human Finitude and the Dialectics of Experience

Kant: Critique of Pure Reason

Theory of Aesthetics and Teleology

Philosophy Pathways Issue th December 2016

The Doctrine of the Mean

Intellect and the Structuring of Reality in Plotinus and Averroes

Kant and the Problem of Experience. Hannah Ginsborg. As most of its readers are aware, the Critique of Pure Reason is

Chapter 11. Æsthetic Judgements are Necessary by Immanuel Kant

Copyright Nikolaos Bogiatzis 1. Athenaeum Fragment 116. Romantic poetry is a progressive, universal poetry. Its aim isn t merely to reunite all the

Kant s Formalism? Distinguishing between Aesthetic Judgment and an Overall Response to Art in the Critique of Judgment

Kant on Unity in Experience

No Other Use than in Judgment? Kant on Concepts and Sensible Synthesis

Aristotle on the Human Good

Chapter 5 The Categories of Understanding

Objective vs. Subjective

A New Look at Kant s Theory of Pleasure 1

E-LOGOS. Kant's Understanding Imagination in Critique of Pure Reason. Milos Rastovic ELECTRONIC JOURNAL FOR PHILOSOPHY ISSN /2013

CAROL HUNTS University of Kansas

Philosophical Foundations of Mathematical Universe Hypothesis Using Immanuel Kant

The Critique of Judgement

Foucault's Technologies of the Self: A Kantian Project?

This is an electronic reprint of the original article. This reprint may differ from the original in pagination and typographic detail.

Ergo. Images and Kant s Theory of Perception. 1. Introduction. University of California, Santa Cruz

Excerpt: Karl Marx's Economic and Philosophical Manuscripts

The Teaching Method of Creative Education

Kant Prolegomena to any Future Metaphysics, Preface, excerpts 1 Critique of Pure Reason, excerpts 2 PHIL101 Prof. Oakes updated: 9/19/13 12:13 PM

Valuable Particulars

Intention and Interpretation

Chapter 11 The Momenta of Practical Judgment

The role of productive imagination in creating artworks and discovering scientific hypotheses

THE DIDACTIC PROCESS AT THE ATELIER OF SCULPTURE, PREPARED FOR STUDENTS OF ARCHITECTURE

Existential Cause & Individual Experience

On the Anxiety Prior to Any Possible Judgment of Taste

Introduction SABINE FLACH, DANIEL MARGULIES, AND JAN SÖFFNER

Chapter 14 Art Lesson Plans

Intelligible Matter in Aristotle, Aquinas, and Lonergan. by Br. Dunstan Robidoux OSB

KANT. The English Garden

No (I, p. 208f)

(Ulrich Schloesser/ Humboldt-Universität zu Berlin)

Transcription:

Poetry and Play in Kant s Critique of Judgment In Kant s CJ, creation and appreciation of fine art are tied to the concept of free play and to a particular kind of freedom. The relationship of poetry and play deserves closer attention because it throws light on what Kaulbach calls aesthetic freedom, as opposed to intellectual or moral freedom 1, expressed by subjecting our choices and actions to moral law and precepts we prescribe to ourselves. Aesthetic freedom is realized by creation of and response to a work of fine art. The former forms the matter of a creation aesthetic, the latter of a reception aesthetic. 2 In production of an artwork, the artist unites conscious design with unconscious regularity of natural processes to achieve a singular imaginative representation of ideas. The result seems as if it were a product of nature, despite our recognition that it is product of the artist s intention. As such, the work of art and our response to it form a counterpart to the experience of the beautiful and sublime in natural phenomena, which give the appearance of being products of intentional design, though we recognize them to have been produced by necessary processes according to universal natural laws. The fortuitous purposiveness of the work of art resonates with the harmonious functioning of our sensitive, imaginative and intellectual powers, bringing them into free play with one another. The pleasurable experience of playful purposiveness which this unexpected harmonisation affords serves not only to strengthen and enliven our faculties, and further their cooperation, but also forms the basis for aesthetic judgment. To the extent that these relationships are governed by natural causality, the idea of aesthetic freedom remains problematic. Kant s concepts of genius and freedom of the imagination offer some clarification. His idea of an intellectus archetypus provides an analogy and possible solution. Kant attributes to poetry the highest rank among the fine arts. 3 His sparse indications point to poetry s ability to elicit the highest pleasure, and to embody the highest degree of aesthetic 1 Kaulbach, Friedrich: Ästhetische Welterkenntnis bei Kant. Würzburg 1984, 82. 2 Allison, Henry E.: Kant s Theory of Taste. A Reading of the Critique of Aesthetic Judgment. Cambridge 2001, 269f., 271 and n. 1. sees Kant s discussion of fine art and genius as episodic and difficult to integrate into the overall argument of the CJ, relegating it, along with the account of the sublime, to the work s parerga. Crawford is right to question Allison s formalistic interpretation of Kant s aesthetic theory, which by focussing on questions of the universality and objectivity of aesthetic judgments on the beautiful and the sublime, underestimates the centrality of Kant s theory of the creative imagination in his aesthetic theory. Crawford, Donald: Kant s Theory of the Creative Imagination. In Guyer, Paul: Kant s Critique of the Power of Judgment. Critical Essays Lanham/Boulder/New York/Oxford 2003, 143 170; 143. The discussion of fine art and genius, meanwhile, is essential for an understanding of Kant s idea of aesthetic freedom. 3 KU, AA 05: 326.22 24; Engl. according to: Critique of Judgment. transl. Pluhar, Werner. Indianapolis/Cambridge 1987. Divergences from Pluhar and other translations are my own.

Zovko 2 freedom, as reasons for its privileged status. Art in general is distinguished from nature as doing (facere) is from acting (agere), the former producing a work or opus, the latter a mere effectus. 4 For only a production through freedom, i.e. through a power of choice that bases its acts on reason, qualifies as art. An artwork is a product of volition, which grounds its actions on intelligence and rational deliberation. 5 Yet it differs from science and technical production, insofar as neither knowledge nor objective presentation of an intended product suffice to produce an artwork. Fine art is distinguished from craft as free art from mercenary art. Free art can only turn out purposively [ ] (i.e. succeed) if it is play. 6 Play is opposed to law, work, force 7, as an occupation agreeable in its own account and as such freely chosen; whereas craft is labor, i.e. an occupation on its own account [ ]disagreeable[ ]that attracts us only through its effect (e.g.) pay. The free play that is art nonetheless depends on the lawfulness which governs nature, knowledge, and craft. For realization of the artwork requires a natural medium, whose order of constraint or natural mechanism the artist must master. 8 In its full perfection, then, art requires much science. Poetry, eg., in Kant s definition, is the art of conducting free play of the imagination as a business of understanding, requiring correctness and richness of language prosody and meter. A poet, thus, needs knowledge of Classical literature, in order to become familiar with the inherent lawfulness and correct use of language, with literary figures and rhetorical devices, pleasing use of meter and prosody, etc. 9 In creation of and response to a work of art, imagination and judgment are in a specific sense free or autonomous. 10 Whereas in cognition, sense perception is subject to the laws of understanding, in aesthetic judgment, a complete liberation of the sensible from the dominion of understanding takes place. 11 This is made possible by freedom of 4 KU, AA 05: 303.07 09. 5 KU, AA 05: 303.13 18. As opposed to phenomena like a beehive, whose purposive form, is not based on any rational deliberation, but only on instinct, although by virtue of an analogy with art, it seems to require that a presentation precede it in its cause (in the bees or their Creator). 6 KU, AA 05: 304.06 07. 7 cf. KU, AA 05: 321.30 34; 327: 31 33. 8 Guyer observes that in a crucial respect a work of artistic genius does not merely look like a product of nature, but is one. Guyer, Paul: Kant and the Claims of Taste, Cambridge 1997, 356. In this respect, art is subject to the conditions of the possibility of experience. 9 AA 05: 304ff., 321; cf. 382. 10 Kaulbach compares aesthetic freedom, as independence of thinking feeling and feeling thought, to the maxim of the Enlightenment to think for oneself. Kaulbach 141, cf. 140. Recki, Birgit: Ästhetik der Sitten. Frankfurt am Main 2001, sees free play of the powers of cognition as connected with autonomy of the subject which judges the feeling of pleasure disinterestedly (KU, AA 05: 281.11-13). The subject is to be understood as autonomous, insofar as it thereby gives itself its own principle, i.e. of fortuitous purposiveness (Recki, 62, cf. 65). 11 Kaulbach, 35; cf. AA 05: 282.17-32; 350.7-28.

Zovko 3 imagination. 12 Imagination, as ability to produce images of an object in intuition without the object being present, constitutes a necessary ingredient of perception, connecting sense intuition and understanding, and forms therewith one of the conditions of the possibility of cognition. In its transcendental function, imagination is both receptive and spontaneous, mediating a corresponding intuition to concepts of the understanding, and determining sense a priori according to the categories as necessarily related to the original unity of apperception. 13 In this role, however, imagination is not free, but a mere effect of the understanding and its [ ] first application to objects of a possible experience, a blind, although indispensable function of the soul [ ] of which we are only seldom conscious. 14 In its aesthetic function, imagination is free from the constraints of understanding, and able to produce a wealth of images above and beyond strict adequacy to concepts. 15 Aesthetic judgment either induces or coincides with the feeling of pleasure elicited by a subjective purposiveness of the presentation in relation to the power of judgment. 16 In order to avoid what Kaulbach calls the danger of empiricism 17, i.e. having to construe the relationship between pleasure and judgment as pathological, and judgment as a necessary effect of its object, it is necessary to establish the priority of reflective judgment vis à vis the source of aesthetic pleasure. 18 This is because the pleasure associated with achievement of an aim forms part of the natural mechanism which ensures our survival. Anytime an aim is achieved, we experience pleasure. The fulfillment of a physical need eg., arouses pleasure, and stimulates us to strive for the source of pleasure, for whatever appears to be good for us in this regard. We enjoy thereby not only the end itself, but also our aim-directed behaviour. Pleasure in the good is tied, thus, to the interest we have in existence of the object of our striving; our judgment in this respect is not free. Rather, pleasure in the good precedes and determines our judgment. 12 cf. KU, AA 05: 242.30. Cf. Recki, 63. In aesthetic judgment, imagination schematizes without a concept (KU, AA 05: 287.16 17), whereas in cognition it schematizes by subsuming the manifold of sense intuition under a concept. 13 KrV, AA 3:119.32 36f. 14 KrV, AA 3:91.29 31. 15 cf. AA 05: 316.27 317.06. 16 KU, AA 05: 248.15 16; cf. EEKU, AA 20: 230.11 13; 231:1 4. 17 Kaulbach, 59. 18 In Allison s view, Kant held that the relationship between the free harmony of the faculties and the pleasure in the judgment of taste is intentional as well as causal. Pleasure is to some extent an effect of the experience of the free harmony of the faculties, but also the very means through which one becomes aware of this harmony, though not in the form of cognition, but as a feeling apprehension, and inherently pleasurable mental state (Allison 53, 54).

Zovko 4 Kant differentiates pleasure in the good and pleasure in the agreeable from aesthetic pleasure as related to judgments of the beautiful and the sublime. 19 Pleasure in what is agreeable to the senses in sensation, like pleasure in the good, is tied to interest in whatever arouses immediate sensual pleasure. 20 Pleasure in the beautiful, on the other hand, is devoid of all interest. 21 Judgment of beauty, in this regard, is not determined by the presentation of the object in sense intuition, but employs imagination in connection with understanding or reason to refer the presentation to the subject and his feeling of pleasure or displeasure. 22 Our liking for the beautiful involves, namely, making a judgment of reflection rather than a judgment of sense or a logically determinative one, i.e. one which depends directly neither on a sensation, nor on a determinate concept, as does our liking for the good, but is connected with the mere [ ] power of exhibition, i.e., the imagination. Pleasure is thereby said to accompany the presentation of a free play of the powers of presentation in a given presentation to something which is known, resulting in a quickening of the two powers (imagination and understanding) to an activity which is indeterminate, but, as a result of the the prompting of the given presentation, nonetheless accordant. 23 Kant s argument for the universal validity of aesthetic judgments seems to imply that aesthetic judgment both causes and is an effect of free play and the pleasure it arouses. 24 The subjective formal purposiveness of the object on which judgment of beauty depends entails the object s being commensurate with the cognitive powers that are, and insofar as they are, brought into play when we judge reflectively. 25 Although it is the form of the object and not (as in cognition) the material which is judged, in mere reflection on it, to be the source of aesthetic pleasure, the presentation of the object is seen here to be connected necessarily with this pleasure, and hence connected with it not merely for the subject apprehending this form but in general for everyone who judges it. Elsewhere, Kant suggests that reflective judgment acts unintentionally when it compares forms of the imagination with its ability [ ] to refer intuitions to concepts, and that aesthetic judgment follows necessarily from the resulting harmonisation of our cognitive powers: if [ ] a given presentation unintentionally brings the imagination [ ] into harmony with the understanding [ ] and this harmony 19 cf. KU, AA 05, 4. 20 cf. KU, AA 05: 207.26 209., cf. 266, 305 21 KU, AA 05: 204.21. 22 KU, AA 05: 203.09 12. 23 KU, AA 05: 217.15-218.07; 219.04 07. 24 Kaulbach seems to equate aesthetic pleasure with aesthetic freedom when he says (53): Der Charakter des reflektierten, durch Gelingen des Weltexperimentes zustandekommenden Zu-standes der Lust ist ästhetische Freiheit. 25 KU, AA 05: 189.36 190.02.

Zovko 5 arouses a feeling of pleasure, then the object must thereupon be regarded as purposive for the reflective power of judgment. 26 Kant s idea of an intellectus archetypus 27 may shed light on the problem. Our intellect is described in the CJ as intellectus ectypus, as requiring images of things which appear to be outside the intellect. Our understanding, namely, is discursive, it cannot directly intuit, i.e. produce the objects of its intuition, but depends on sense perception for the matter to which its synthetic activity is applied. An understanding, however, in which through selfconsciousness simultaneously everything manifold is given would intuit, i.e. depend only on itself for its object. 28 Causality of an understanding which acts according to purposes is a requirement for the reality of freedom in Kant. The intellectus archetypus, however, though itself the originator of purposiveness, embodies a different kind of freedom, namely, independence from external coercion or immanent causality. The artist, similarly, by freely producing images to correspond to ideas she wishes to represent, acts not only aimfully, but also independently of coercion by concepts of understanding. 29 Her native talent or genius permits her, moreover, to co-operate with the conditions of her medium, so that what is aimful in her work appears necessary. Judgment of the artwork, correspondingly, becomes autonomy of one who gives herself an object of intuition in reflection on and intellectual re-enactment of the process by which ideas are represented aesthetically by the artist. Freedom of imagination and judgment, conjoined with talent, skill and momentary inspiration comprise the conditions for a successful work of art. 30 The conditions of the physical medium 26 KU, AA 5:190.02-10. 27 cf. KrV, AA 03:457. In the Transcendental Dialectic, the intellectus archetypus is a regulative idea or ideal of pure reason, which serves as ground of the order in the world and its connection according to general laws. It is not a real substance or object of cognition, since no sense intuition corresponds to it, but may nonetheless be conceived, in analogy to objects of experience, as an unknown substratum of systematic unity, order, and purposiveness in the structure of the world, which reason must posit as regulative principle of its investigation of nature. 28 KrV, AA 03:110; cf. Prol., AA 04:316.18 26. 29 Spinoza ascribes this type of freedom to the substantia infinita or causa sui. Cf. Ethics I, 7: Ea res libera dicitur quae ex sola suae naturae necessitate existit et a se sola ad agendum determinatur [ ] Kant calls Spinoza s position fatalism of purposiveness, since it attributes the appearance of purposiveness in nature to an unintentional activity of the substantia infinita. In Kant s view, teleological explanation should be based on the idea of an architectonic understanding ( einer nach Zwecken handelnden (verständigen) Weltursache ). Cf. KU, AA 05:391f.; 393:11 22. 30 Genius, a talent which no science can teach and no diligence learn, of discovering ideas for a given concept and [ ] finding the expression for these, through which the subjective disposition of the mind that is effected by them [ ] can be communicated to others, enables the artist to express the unnameable in the mental state and make it universally communicable, whether [ ] in language, or painting, or sculpture. (KU AA 05: 316-17)

Zovko 6 allow the artwork to appear as phenomenon of a second nature. 31 Aesthetic judgment, the exercise of our ability to judge an object in reference to the free lawfulness of the imagination, takes as its point of departure the free (spontaneous, harmonious) play of cognitive powers which the paradoxical coincidence of freedom and necessity in the apparition of beauty and the sublime 32 induces in us. Imagination is considered thereby in its freedom or self-sufficiency, not as reproductive, or subject to the laws of association, but as productive and spontaneous (as originator of chosen forms of possible intuitions) (my italics). In perception, as Kant sees it, imagination is tied to a determinate form of this object and to that extent does not have free play (as it does [ ] in poetry). 33 It is conceivable, however, that the object may offer it just the sort of form in the combination of its manifold as the imagination, if it were left to itself [and were] free would design in harmony with the understanding s lawfulness in general. 34 The artist and the recipient of the artwork, then, exercise a freedom of imagination which is analogous to the freedom of the intellectus archetypus, by their relative independence from external causality. In poetry, the faculty of aesthetic ideas manifests itself to its fullest, because it is primarily a product of genius and of all the arts it depends least of all on precepts or models. 35 Poetry is the art of conducting a free play of the imagination as if it were a task of the understanding 36, joining images with concepts as if in it understanding could intuit. It sets the imagination free, bringing to the concept from the manifold of images which may be associated with a it a fullness of thoughts beyond mere denotation, for which discursivity alone is inadequate. Poetry raises us thereby in feeling to ideas, strengthening and expanding the spirit, by letting it feel its free, autonomous power, which is independent of determination by nature, to contemplate and to judge nature as appearance according to points of view which do not present themselves either to sense or understanding and to use these for the purpose of and so to speak as schema of the transcendent (zum Schema des Übersinnlichen). 37 When understanding alone gives the law, its product is determined by concepts, and imagination is compelled to proceed according to a 31 Cf. KU, AA 05:314.09-11: For the imagination[ ] (as a productive cognitive power) is very mighty when it creates, as it were, another nature out of the material that actual nature gives it. (my italics) Consideration of Kant s analysis of the concept of a natural purpose and the conditions of its possibility sheds light on the concept of a work of fine art and the conditions of its possibility, revealing natural purposes and the artwork to be virtual mirror images of each other (Allison 278). 32 The free play of imagination and reason with respect to the sublime cannot be dealt with here. 33 KU AA, 05:240.28 31. 34 KU AA, 05:240.31 241.03; my italics. 35 KU AA, 05:314; 326; cf. 314; 282f. 36 KU AA, 05:321.09 10. 37 KU, AA 05:326.30 35.

Zovko 7 determinate law. Any liking that may arise thereby is not for the beautiful but for the good [ ] and the judgment is not a judgment made by taste, that is, it is not an instance of aesthetic freedom. Only lawfulness without a law and a subjective harmony of the imagination with the understanding without an objective harmony [ ] is compatible with the free lawfulness of the understanding [ ] and with the peculiarity of a judgment of taste. 38 Poetic art, by permitting imagination the best opportunity to create as if its work were a product of an understanding which intuits, enables our closest assimilation to the intellectus archetypus and greatest aesthetic freedom. 38 KU, AA 05:241:08-17.