There Are No Easy Problems of Consciousness 1

Similar documents
A Confusion of the term Subjectivity in the philosophy of Mind *

Conclusion. One way of characterizing the project Kant undertakes in the Critique of Pure Reason is by

that would join theoretical philosophy (metaphysics) and practical philosophy (ethics)?

Kant Prolegomena to any Future Metaphysics, Preface, excerpts 1 Critique of Pure Reason, excerpts 2 PHIL101 Prof. Oakes updated: 9/19/13 12:13 PM

Immanuel Kant Critique of Pure Reason

In his essay "Of the Standard of Taste," Hume describes an apparent conflict between two

Existential Cause & Individual Experience

Rational Agency and Normative Concepts by Geoffrey Sayre-McCord UNC/Chapel Hill [for discussion at the Research Triangle Ethics Circle] Introduction

1/8. The Third Paralogism and the Transcendental Unity of Apperception

Review of David Woodruff Smith and Amie L. Thomasson, eds., Phenomenology and the Philosophy of Mind, 2005, Oxford University Press.

Categories and Schemata

The aim of this paper is to explore Kant s notion of death with special attention paid to

Affect, perceptual experience, and disclosure

6 The Analysis of Culture

1/6. The Anticipations of Perception

REVIEW ARTICLE IDEAL EMBODIMENT: KANT S THEORY OF SENSIBILITY

What do our appreciation of tonal music and tea roses, our acquisition of the concepts

Book Reviews Department of Philosophy and Religion Appalachian State University 401 Academy Street Boone, NC USA

Making Modal Distinctions: Kant on the possible, the actual, and the intuitive understanding.

Perception and Mind-Dependence Lecture 3

Comments on Dumont, Intension and Remission of Forms. Robert Pasnau

Social Mechanisms and Scientific Realism: Discussion of Mechanistic Explanation in Social Contexts Daniel Little, University of Michigan-Dearborn

A Study of the Bergsonian Notion of <Sensibility>

The Senses at first let in particular Ideas. (Essay Concerning Human Understanding I.II.15)

LeBar s Flaccidity: Is there Cause for Concern?

Naïve realism without disjunctivism about experience

1/10. The A-Deduction

Perceptions and Hallucinations

McDowell, Demonstrative Concepts, and Nonconceptual Representational Content Wayne Wright

John Locke Book II: Of Ideas in General, and Their Origin. Andrew Branting 11

THESIS MIND AND WORLD IN KANT S THEORY OF SENSATION. Submitted by. Jessica Murski. Department of Philosophy

Rethinking the Aesthetic Experience: Kant s Subjective Universality

Having the World in View: Essays on Kant, Hegel, and Sellars

Philosophy Pathways Issue th December 2016

Philosophical Background to 19 th Century Modernism

Necessity in Kant; Subjective and Objective

Some (Philosophical) Problems for Consciousness as a Neural Capacity for Objectivity

Harris Wiseman, The Myth of the Moral Brain: The Limits of Moral Enhancement (Cambridge, MA and London: The MIT Press, 2016), 340 pp.

The Phenomenological Negation of the Causal Closure of the Physical

Presented as part of the Colloquium Sponsored by the Lonergan Project at Marquette University on Lonergan s Philosophy and Theology

PHI 3240: Philosophy of Art

Naturalizing Phenomenology? Dretske on Qualia*

Comments on Bence Nanay, Perceptual Content and the Content of Mental Imagery

THE ECOLOGICAL MEANING OF EMBODIMENT

HEGEL, ANALYTIC PHILOSOPHY AND THE RETURN OF METAPHYISCS Simon Lumsden

TERMS & CONCEPTS. The Critical Analytic Vocabulary of the English Language A GLOSSARY OF CRITICAL THINKING

The Pure Concepts of the Understanding and Synthetic A Priori Cognition: the Problem of Metaphysics in the Critique of Pure Reason and a Solution

1/9. The B-Deduction

Moral Judgment and Emotions

A New Look at Kant s Theory of Pleasure 1

Thomas Szanto: Bewusstsein, Intentionalität und mentale Repräsentation. Husserl und die analytische Philosophie des Geistes

On Recanati s Mental Files

Types of perceptual content

FUNCTIONALISM AND THE QUALIA WARS. Ekai Txapartegi

Kant on Unity in Experience

UNITY, OBJECTIVITY, AND THE PASSIVITY OF EXPERIENCE

KANT S TRANSCENDENTAL LOGIC

We know of the efforts of such philosophers as Frege and Husserl to undo the

Kant: Notes on the Critique of Judgment

Kant IV The Analogies The Schematism updated: 2/2/12. Reading: 78-88, In General

NATIONAL SEMINAR ON EDUCATIONAL RESEARCH: ISSUES AND CONCERNS 1 ST AND 2 ND MARCH, 2013

Philosophical History and the Problem of Consciousness

du Châtelet s ontology: element, corpuscle, body

Subjective Universality in Kant s Aesthetics Wilson

Immanuel Kant s Theory of Knowledge: Exploring the Relation between Sensibility and Understanding Wendell Allan Marinay

Investigating subjectivity

Steven E. Kaufman * Key Words: existential mechanics, reality, experience, relation of existence, structure of reality. Overview

The topic of this Majors Seminar is Relativism how to formulate it, and how to evaluate arguments for and against it.

Peircean concept of sign. How many concepts of normative sign are needed. How to clarify the meaning of the Peircean concept of sign?

2 Unified Reality Theory

Faculty of Philosophy, University of Cambridge Part IB: Metaphysics & Epistemology

Situated actions. Plans are represetitntiom of nction. Plans are representations of action

Phenomenology Glossary

6 Bodily Sensations as an Obstacle for Representationism

ENVIRONMENTAL EXPERIENCE: Beyond Aesthetic Subjectivism and Objectivism

Conceptualism and Phenomenal Character

By Tetsushi Hirano. PHENOMENOLOGY at the University College of Dublin on June 21 st 2013)

1/8. Axioms of Intuition

The red apple I am eating is sweet and juicy. LOCKE S EMPIRICAL THEORY OF COGNITION: THE THEORY OF IDEAS. Locke s way of ideas

Review of Carolyn Korsmeyer, Savoring Disgust: The foul and the fair. in aesthetics (Oxford University Press pp (PBK).

Bas C. van Fraassen, Scientific Representation: Paradoxes of Perspective, Oxford University Press, 2008.

The Problem of Perception

WHY STUDY THE HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY? 1

TEST BANK. Chapter 1 Historical Studies: Some Issues

c. MP claims that this is one s primary knowledge of the world and as it is not conscious as is evident in the case of the phantom limb patient

observation and conceptual interpretation

The Art of Time Travel: A Bigger Picture

Kant and the Problem of Experience

Diachronic and synchronic unity

The Polish Peasant in Europe and America. W. I. Thomas and Florian Znaniecki

MODES OF PRESENTATION AND WAYS OF APPEARING: A CRITICAL REVISION OF EVANS S ACCOUNT*

Action Theory for Creativity and Process

Edward Winters. Aesthetics and Architecture. London: Continuum, 2007, 179 pp. ISBN

The central and defining characteristic of thoughts is that they have objects. The object

Prephilosophical Notions of Thinking

Image and Imagination

Chudnoff on the Awareness of Abstract Objects 1

The Strengths and Weaknesses of Frege's Critique of Locke By Tony Walton

NATURALIZING QUALIA. ALESSANDRA BUCCELLA University of Pittsburgh abstract

On The Search for a Perfect Language

Transcription:

There Are No Easy Problems of Consciousness 1 E. J. Lowe Department of Philosophy, University of Durham, Durham, UK This paper challenges David Chalmers proposed division of the problems of consciousness into the easy ones and the hard one, the former allegedly being susceptible to explanation in terms of computational or neural mechanisms and the latter supposedly turning on the fact that experiential qualia resist any sort of functional definition. Such a division, it is argued, rests upon a misrepresention of the nature of human cognition and experience and their intimate interrelationship, thereby neglecting a vitally important insight of Kant. From a Kantian perspective, our capacity for conceptual thought is so inextricably bound up with our capacity for phenomenal consciousness that it is an illusion to imagine that there are any easy problems of consciousness, resolvable within the computational or neural paradigms. David Chalmers is to be commended for challenging the complacent assumptions of reductive physicalism regarding the tractability of the problems of consciousness, but he concedes too much to such physicalists in allowing that some, at least, of these problems the easy ones will fall prey to their favoured methods. 2 I do not consider that there are any easy problems of consciousness, and consider that Chalmers division of the problems into easy ones and the hard one betrays an inadequate conception of conscious thought and experience a conception which plays into the hands of physicalists by suggesting that the only problem with functionalism is its apparent inability to say anything about qualia. 3 At the beginning of his paper, Chalmers lists some of the problems of consciousness which he considers to be easy, in the sense that these are the ones which, in his view, seem directly susceptible to the standard methods of cognitive science, whereby a phenomenon is explained in terms of computational or neural mechanisms (p. 200). These problems include: the ability to discriminate, categorize and react to environmental stimuli; the integration of information by a cognitive system; the reportability of mental states; and the deliberate control of behaviour. Chalmers remarks that, All 1 Originally published in Journal of Consciousness Studies 2 (3), 1995, pp. 266 271. Copyright Imprint Academic 2005. Reproduced with permission. 2 See Chalmers (1995); all page references are to this paper. 3 Much of what I have to say about consciousness, thought and experience in this paper is developed at much greater length in Lowe (1996) and, in an earlier version, in Lowe (1992).

74 ANTIMATTERS 2 (1) 2008 of these phenomena are associated with the notion of consciousness, and confidently asserts that, All of them are straightforwardly vulnerable to explanation in terms of computational or neural mechanisms (p. 201). But it needs to be pointed out at once that the terms employed in describing these problems terms like discrimination, information, report and control are extremely slippery, and that we use them both in a high level way to describe the conscious, intelligent activity of genuinely thoughtful creatures like ourselves and also in a low level way (which may in fact be no more than a metaphorical way) to describe the programmed behaviour of mindless machines and various lowly forms of life. For example, we may speak of a thermostat as discriminating ambient temperatures and as controlling a switch, or of a computer as storing information and reporting on the contents of its memory. But there is no reason whatever to believe that the activities thus described really have much in common with those activities of thoughtful human beings which we would customarily describe in these same terms. To suppose otherwise is to fall victim to the so-called pathetic fallacy the fallacy of ascribing thought and feeling to mindless objects on account of superficial likenesses between their behaviour or appearance and our own. Now, it is true enough that the activities of thermostats and computers which we describe in such terms can indeed be explained in the ways Chalmers suggests, but it is far from evident that those of human beings can. Indeed, I shall try to make it evident in what follows that the latter activities can certainly not be explained in these ways, and that the reason for this has to do with the nature of human consciousness and its relation to our capacities for thought, understanding and conceptformation. As a preliminary to tackling this task, I want to say something more about Chalmers notions of experience and consciousness, which I find seriously inadequate. As regards the notion of experience, it seems to me that he distorts this notion by focusing exclusively upon the sensuous, or phenomenal, or qualitative character of experience (the what it is like aspect of experience, to use Thomas Nagel s well-worn phrase). And this distortion serves, in my view, to obscure the intimate relation between experience and thought. Some experiences pains provide a possible example are indeed almost purely sensational in character, but the sort of experiences which are central to our cognitive capacities namely, perceptual experiences are certainly not. Perceptual experiences such as, for example, a visual experience of seeing a red book lying on top of a brown table possess not only qualitative or phenomenal characteristics but also, most importantly, intentional or representational content. Not only is it like something to enjoy such an experience, in which the phenomenal character of sensed colours impresses itself upon our awareness, but also such an experience represents or, better, presents our immediate physical environment as being some way (in this case, as containing a red book on top of a brown table). Moreover, and quite crucially, the intentional content of such an experience stands in an especially intimate relation to its qualitative or phenomenal character: the two aspects of the experience are not simply independent of one another.

LOWE : THERE ARE NO EASY PROBLEMS OF CONSCIOUSNESS 75 I want to say that the intentional content of a perceptual experience is, in a certain sense, grounded in its phenomenal character, but that the grounding relation here is a complicated one, which arises at least in part through the subject s individual history of perceptual learning. One of the most important things we learn through perception is what various sorts of physical object look like (or otherwise appear to other sense modalities what they sound like, and feel like, for instance). And how objects look to us is, at least in part, a matter of how they affect the phenomenal or qualitative character of our visual experience. (The same applies, mutatis mutandis, with regard to the other sense modalities.) The importance of all this lies in the fact that how we conceive of physical objects is inextricably bound up with how they appear to us in perception how they look, sound, feel and so forth. Thus, although conscious thought is not, of course, the same thing as perceptual experience, the conceptual content of thought is intimately related to the content, both phenomenal and intentional, of perceptual experience. Thoughts differ from perceptual experiences in possessing only intentional, and not sensuous content; yet, even so, the intentional content of our thought depends inescapably, by way of its conceptual structure, upon our capacity to enjoy perceptual experiences with sensuous or phenomenal characteristics. And, at the same time, our perceptual experiences possess intentional content often, the very same content as may be possessed by our thoughts because we are able to bring concepts to bear upon the deliverances of our sense organs and so clothe our perceptual sensations with representational properties. All this has been said before, of course and no doubt much better than I have been able to by Immanuel Kant, and is encapsulated in his famous dictum that Thoughts without [sensible] content are empty, [sensible] intuitions without concepts are blind (1933, p. 93). But the upshot is that it is quite erroneous to suppose that we can ascribe genuine thoughts, with conceptually articulated structure, to creatures or machines lacking altogether the capacity to enjoy conscious experiences with phenomenal or qualitative character. Whatever a computer can do by way of information processing, storage and retrieval is not by any means to be confused with what a thinking human being does who reasons, remembers and recalls. And here I note a particularly serious inadequacy in the (essentially Shannonian) notion of information which Chalmers deploys in attempting to characterize aspects of human cognition. This notion of information is appropriate enough for describing the activities of computing machines, but is wholly inappropriate for characterizing the cognitive states beliefs, thoughts and judgements of human beings. And the reason, once again, has to do with conceptual content. An informational state in Chalmers sense is not, essentially, a state possessing conceptually articulated content; but the beliefs, thoughts and judgements of human beings most certainly do possess such content essentially. A simple, if somewhat timeworn, example will serve to bring out this distinction. Consider the pattern of rings exposed by a horizontal cut through a tree s trunk: such a ring pattern is, in the sense of information deployed by Chalmers, an informational state of the tree it carries information about the tree s age, amongst other things. Clearly, though, it is not a state with conceptual content: it would be ludicrous to suggest that

76 ANTIMATTERS 2 (1) 2008 the ring pattern somehow embodies the concepts of number and time (concepts which are themselves involved in the analysis of the concept of a tree s age). By contrast, one cannot properly ascribe to a person a belief that a certain tree is so-and-so many years old without simultaneously ascribing to that person concepts of number and time. And, once again, I would appeal to the Kantian principle that our conceptual capacities even those relating to such relatively abstract concepts as those of number and time are intimately related to our capacities for perceptual experience, in order to explain what the relevant difference between a human being and a tree is in this regard. That a tree can merely carry (Shannonian) information about its age, whereas a human being can believe that, or think that, it has a certain age is intimately related to the fact that human beings can, whereas trees cannot, enjoy conscious perceptual experiences with phenomenal character. So far I have criticized Chalmers notions of experience and information, but there is a related criticism I have to make which goes to the heart of his attempted distinction between the easy problems of consciousness and the hard problem. This concerns his terminological proposal regarding the use of the words consciousness and awareness. Chalmers suggests that we reserve the term consciousness for the phenomena of experience, using the less loaded term awareness for the more straightforward phenomena described earlier (p. 201). But given that I dispute Chalmers claim that the latter phenomena are indeed more straightforward (in the sense of being amenable to computational or neural explanation), I cannot acquiesce in his terminological proposal. To do so would be, implicitly, to concede far too much to reductive physicalism and at the same time would be to gainsay all I have just said concerning the intimate relationship between phenomenal consciousness and the intelligent thought and activity of human beings. In Chalmers proposed sense of awareness, it seems fair to say, there could be nothing in principle wrong in speaking of a computer, or even a thermostat, as being aware but then to suggest that human beings are only aware in this attenuated sense is completely to misrepresent the capacities involved in our being aware of our selves and of our own thoughts and experiences. My foregoing criticisms of Chalmers bear directly upon section III of his paper, in which he attempts to explain why the easy problems are easy and the hard problem hard. Here he asserts that The easy problems are easy precisely because they concern the explanation of cognitive abilities and functions [and] to explain a cognitive function, we need only specify a mechanism that can perform the function (p. 202). He gives the following example, amongst others: To explain reportability... is just to explain how a system could perform the function of producing reports on internal states (ibid.). But, of course, I must immediately protest that if by producing a report on an internal state Chalmers just means generating a second-order informational state (in the Shannonian sense of information ), then although this is something which can indeed be perfectly well explained in a mechanistic way, it is not the sort of thing that needs to be explained when we are talking about the ability of human subjects to express in words their knowledge of the contents of their own thoughts and experiences for such an

LOWE : THERE ARE NO EASY PROBLEMS OF CONSCIOUSNESS 77 ability demands the possession of genuine concepts, not only concepts of the things those thoughts and experiences are about but also the very concepts of thought and experience themselves. And the truth is that we have not the slightest reason to believe that a mechanistic explanation is available, even in principle, for the capacity of creatures like ourselves to deploy the concepts of thought and experience and to ascribe the possession of such concepts to ourselves. Only by trading upon a thoroughly jejune sense of reportability can Chalmers make out even the appearance of a case for saying that such a capacity, as exercised by human beings, is easy to explain as being a function performed by a computational or neural mechanism. The key point here is that a function, in Chalmers sense, is specified in terms of certain behaviour which a system subserving that function produces. (As Chalmers himself puts it, Here function is... used... in the... sense of any causal role in the production of behavior that a system might perform (p. 202 f).) But then everything turns on how we characterize the behaviour in question. In the example just discussed, the behaviour in question was described by Chalmers as that of producing reports on internal states. But only if such behaviour is interpreted in a narrowly physicalistic way for example, in terms of the generation of a second-order (Shannonian) informational state is a mechanistic explanation of the corresponding function going to be straightforwardly available. If, by contrast, we understand producing reports on internal states to embrace such genuinely intelligent, thoughtful activities as a human being s using language to express its knowledge of the contents of its own thoughts and experiences, then there is not the slightest reason to suppose that a mechanistic explanation for this capacity is possible. Mechanistically characterized behaviour is, quite unsurprizingly, amenable to mechanistic explanation, and this is what underlies Chalmers own perception that In a way, the point is trivial (p. 202) the point being that you can always explain the performance of a function by specifying a mechanism that performs the function (ibid.). Chalmers problem is that he entirely begs the real question at issue in supposing that the sort of performance we have to do with in cases of thoughtful human activity is something that can be characterized in a mechanistic way and which, consequently, a mechanism can uncontroversially be supposed capable of engaging in. Because Chalmers misconstrues what he sees as being the easy problems of consciousness, he also misrepresents what he calls the hard problem. According to Chalmers, the hard problem is this: Why doesn t all this information-processing go on in the dark, free of any inner feel? (p. 203). Believing as he does that human thought and cognition in general are just a matter of information-processing, of a sort which could in principle go on in a mindless computer, he is left with the idea that all that is really distinctive about consciousness is its qualitative or phenomenal aspects (the what it is like, or inner feel ). And then it begins to look like a strange mystery or quirk of evolution that creatures like us should possess this sort of consciousness in addition to all our capacities for thought and understanding these capacities being, for Chalmers, simply capacities for certain sorts of information-processing and storage.

78 ANTIMATTERS 2 (1) 2008 My response is that consciousness has only been put in this queer position by Chalmers (and, to be fair, by many others) because he has mistakenly denied it any role in his account of the nature of human thought and understanding. In short, it is the reductive, and wholly inadequate, information-processing conception of human cognition which is responsible for the misperception that consciousness (in the form of qualia and the like) occupies what threatens to be a merely epiphenomenal role as a peculiar additional feature of human mentation that is in no way essential to our basic intellectual capacities. Once we appreciate the Kantian point that genuine thought, with real conceptual content, is only available to creatures with a capacity for perceptual experiences bearing not only intentional but also phenomenal content, we see that the sort of phenomenal consciousness which we humans enjoy but which computers and trees do not, far from being an epiphenomenon of information-processing in our brains, is an absolutely indispensable element in our cognitive make-up, without which we could not properly be described as thinking beings at all. In a curious way, it is perhaps a rationalistic, quasi-cartesian bias which is responsible for this side-lining of phenomenal consciousness as an epiphenomenon of cognition: a failure to recognize that human cognition is not a matter of abstract computation but is, on the contrary, thoroughly integrated with our sensitive nature as embodied creatures acted upon by and ourselves acting upon our physical environment. There is irony, then, in Chalmers concessive remark, towards the end of section III of his paper, that Perhaps [experience] will turn out to play an important cognitive role (p. 203). Perhaps! If Kant is right, no one who is in any doubt about this has even begun to achieve an adequate grasp of the notions of experience and cognition. If what I have said so far is correct and our capacity for genuine thought and understanding is quite inseparable from our capacity for phenomenal consciousness, then, to the extent that Chalmers himself is correct in contending that reductive physicalism offers no prospect for an explanation of phenomenal consciousness, the conclusion ought to be that reductive physicalism, far from being equipped to solve the socalled easy problems of consciousness, has in fact nothing very useful to say about any aspect of consciousness. This indeed is my own conclusion. (I hasten to add, though, that I am very far from considering disciplines such as cognitive neuropsychology as being utterly worthless and uninformative: such disciplines take the notion of conscious thought and experience for granted, and attempt to correlate features of such mental states with structures and processes in the brain an enterprise with which I have no argument but they do not and cannot pretend to explain what thought and experience are and how their existence is possible in physically embodied creatures like ourselves.) But Chalmers, by contrast, occupies an unstable position, precisely because he has already conceded so much to reductive physicalism. Effectively, he subscribes to a position which we might call functionalism plus qualia. According to this view, everything about human mentation except for the fact of qualia can be explained in reductive (computational or neural) terms. But how, then, can qualia be anything but epiphenomenal and in that case, why should they exist at all? The position is unstable because there is intense pressure on it either to give

LOWE : THERE ARE NO EASY PROBLEMS OF CONSCIOUSNESS 79 qualia some more substantive causal role and this would be to challenge the reductive physicalist account of the rest of human mentation or else to squeeze qualia out altogether, as Dennett and others have tried to do. The awkardness of Chalmers position is, I think, clearly brought out by his allegiance to what he calls the principle of organizational invariance (p. 214). According to this principle, any two systems with the same fine-grained functional organization will have qualitatively identical experiences (ibid.). As he himself points out, this means that the philosophical hypotheses of absent qualia and inverted qualia, while logically possible, are empirically and nomologically impossible (p. 215). But this is, in effect, finally to concede the whole game to functionalism. For once one has adopted what I just now called the position of functionalism plus qualia, the only reason for holding on to a special, physicalistically irreducible notion of phenomenal consciousness is that possibilities like those of absent and inverted qualia escape any attempt at functionalist explanation. But now that these possibilities are denied to be anything more than merely logical possibilities, there is nothing substantive left which functionalism is allegedly incapable of explaining about human mentation. One can perfectly well see why Chalmers is attracted to his principle of organizational invariance, given how much ground he has already conceded to functionalism and given the correspondingly nugatory role he accords to phenomenal consciousness in an account of the nature of human cognition. What he doesn t seem to appreciate is that, having conceded this much, to adopt this principle as well is effectively to sell out completely to functionalism. At the end of his paper, Chalmers becomes more speculative, suggesting that the most fundamental notion of all, both as regards the physical world and as regards conscious experience, is that of information (again, quite explicitly in Shannon s sense of this term). And he offers a double-aspect hypothesis, whereby one and the same information space is both physically and phenomenally embodied. Noting that physics only characterizes its basic entities extrinsically, he even goes so far as to speculate, in what seems to be a quasi-idealistic vein, that the intrinsic properties of the physical... are themselves phenomenal properties (p. 217). This is heady stuff, and to some extent offsets the earlier concessions Chalmers has made to physicalism. But this sort of challenge to physicalism comes too late, operating as it does only at a level of speculative metaphysics. By this account, physicalism is still left unchallenged as a scientific doctrine. My own view, as I hope I have made plain, is that the challenge to a physicalist account of the human mind has to be mounted much earlier than this, and in mounting that challenge one of the first things to appreciate is that the (Shannonian) notion of information is too impoverished to be of use in characterizing the conceptually articulated structure of human thought and its intimate relation to our capacity for phenomenal consciousness (our sensibility, as Kant calls it). We human beings are creatures capable of both thought and perceptual experience, but these capacities are inextricably interrelated. Thought is more than just information-processing and perceptual experience is more than just the having of qualia : both are states which are conceptually articulated and each depends for its possibility upon the other. Kant was right!

80 ANTIMATTERS 2 (1) 2008 References Chalmers, D J (1995). Facing up to the problem of consciousness. Journal of Consciousness Studies 2 (3), 200 19. Kant, I (1933). Critique of Pure Reason [1787], trans. N Kemp Smith. London: Macmillan. Lowe, E J (1992). Experience and its objects. In The Contents of Experience, ed. T Crane. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Lowe, E J (1996). Subjects of Experience. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.