PHIL12A Section answers, 20 April 2011

Similar documents
Multiple Quantifiers. Multiple uses of a single quantifier. Chapter 11

/ The Logic of Atomic Sentences. Remember

Introduction p. 1 The Elements of an Argument p. 1 Deduction and Induction p. 5 Deductive Argument Forms p. 7 Truth and Validity p. 8 Soundness p.

Logik für Informatiker Logic for computer scientists

Lecture 7. Scope and Anaphora. October 27, 2008 Hana Filip 1

Logica & Linguaggio: Tablaux

8.5 --Intro to RAA Proofs Practice with Proofs. Today s Lecture 4/20/10

Argument and argument forms

MATH 195: Gödel, Escher, and Bach (Spring 2001) Notes and Study Questions for Tuesday, March 20

Universals. Some Existence Arguments

Communities of Logical Practice

Chapter 4. Predicate logic allows us to represent the internal properties of the statement. Example:

Review Jean Mark Gawron SDSU. March 14, Translation basics (you shouldnt get these things wrong):

Proofs That Are Not Valid. Identify errors in proofs. Area = 65. Area = 64. Since I used the same tiles: 64 = 65

Some Basic Concepts. Highlights of Chapter 1, 2, 3.

Section 3.1 Statements, Negations, and Quantified Statements

Formalising arguments

Topics in Linguistic Theory: Propositional Attitudes

SAMPLE COURSE OUTLINE PHILOSOPHY AND ETHICS GENERAL YEAR 12

Reply to Stalnaker. Timothy Williamson. In Models and Reality, Robert Stalnaker responds to the tensions discerned in Modal Logic

Peirce's Remarkable Rules of Inference

6.034 Notes: Section 4.1

From Propositional! to Predicate Logic" CSCI 2824, Fall 2011" classes/struct11/home.html "

Philosophy 405: Knowledge, Truth and Mathematics Spring Russell Marcus Hamilton College

The Language of First-Order Predicate Logic

The Language Revolution Russell Marcus Fall Class #7 Final Thoughts on Frege on Sense and Reference

Elements of Style. Anders O.F. Hendrickson

Building Mental Muscle & Growing the Mind through Logic Exercises: Lesson 5b Material Fallacies Answer sheet

Corcoran, J George Boole. Encyclopedia of Philosophy. 2nd edition. Detroit: Macmillan Reference USA, 2006

Appendix B. Elements of Style for Proofs

PHL 317K 1 Fall 2017 Overview of Weeks 1 5

Sidestepping the holes of holism

Pleasure, Pain, and Calm: A Puzzling Argument at Republic 583e1-8

Christopher W. Tindale, Fallacies and Argument Appraisal

Articulating Medieval Logic, by Terence Parsons. Oxford: Oxford University Press,

1 HW1 is due now. 2 HW2 & HW3 are due next Tuesday. 3 We are trying to find space to hold the sections. 4 Our TA (Theo Korzukhin) has an office hour

Picture Descriptions and Centered Content

17. Semantics in L1A

CPSC 121: Models of Computation. Module 1: Propositional Logic

Manuel Bremer University Lecturer, Philosophy Department, University of Düsseldorf, Germany

What are meanings? What do linguistic expressions stand for or denote?

The Embedding Problem for Non-Cognitivism; Introduction to Cognitivism; Motivational Externalism

Logic and argumentation techniques. Dialogue types, rules

THE SUBSTITUTIONAL ANALYSIS OF LOGICAL CONSEQUENCE

Scientific Philosophy

SAMPLE COURSE OUTLINE PHILOSOPHY AND ETHICS ATAR YEAR 11

Exploring touch: A review of Matthew Fulkerson s The First Sense

The Language Revolution Russell Marcus Fall 2015

On the Analogy between Cognitive Representation and Truth

Piano Performance Grade SYLLABUS. Valid from Current until further notice. Issued by authority of the

Dynamic Semantics! (Part 1: Not Actually Dynamic Semantics) Brian Morris, William Rose

Part I: Graph Coloring

The verb PIACERE (to like) #1

Symbolization and Truth-Functional Connectives in SL

QUANTIFICATION IN AFRICAN LOGIC. Jonathan M. O. Chimakonam Ph.D Department of Philosophy University of Calabar, Nigeria

Partitioning a Proof: An Exploratory Study on Undergraduates Comprehension of Proofs

Ling 130: Formal Semantics. Spring Natural Deduction with Propositional Logic. Introducing. Natural Deduction

Logic and Ontology in Hegel s Theory of Predication

Unit 7 : Chap. 1 Inductive and Deductive Reasoning

CAS LX 502 Semantics. Meaning as truth conditions. Recall the trick we can do. How do we arrive at truth conditions?

Business Communication Skills

Social conditions affect our perceptions, our actions, and our relationships.

Necessity in Kant; Subjective and Objective

21W.016: Designing Meaning

Q1. Name the texts that you studied for media texts and society s values this year.

Subordination in complex sentences. Tani, Mary, Brandon

How to Solve Syllogisms for IBPS Exam Reasoning Section?

What is Character? David Braun. University of Rochester. In "Demonstratives", David Kaplan argues that indexicals and other expressions have a

THE SUBSTITUTIONAL ANALYSIS OF LOGICAL CONSEQUENCE

#1 THIS ACTIVITY WILL TEACH:

Existential Cause & Individual Experience

I. INTRODUCING STORIES

THE ELEMENTS OF STYLE. English 4 AP - Smith

1. Introduction. Abstract. 1.1 Logic Criteria

Language, Typography and Meaning. Connotation and Resonance in Type

Sequential Logic and Clocked Circuits

Janice Lee. Recitation 2. TA: Milo Phillips-Brown

Visual Argumentation in Commercials: the Tulip Test 1

MUSIC THEORY. Welcome to the Music Theory Class!

Claim: refers to an arguable proposition or a conclusion whose merit must be established.

Identity Logic = = = Romeo is the lover of Juliet. (identity) Romeo is Italian. (predication) There are Italians. (existence)

Understanding Role Concepts Working Note 20

Nissim Francez: Proof-theoretic Semantics College Publications, London, 2015, xx+415 pages

Intro to Pragmatics (Fox/Menéndez-Benito) 10/12/06. Questions 1

Replies to the Critics

Classifying the Patterns of Natural Arguments

PROOF AND PROVING: LOGIC, IMPASSES, AND THE RELATIONSHIP TO PROBLEM SOLVING MILOS SAVIC, B.S., M.S. A dissertation submitted to the Graduate School

FLIP-FLOPS AND RELATED DEVICES

Study Guide. Solutions to Selected Exercises. Foundations of Music and Musicianship with CD-ROM. 2nd Edition. David Damschroder

Paradoxes: Part 2 of 2. Of Art and Mathematics. feature. Punya Mishra & Gaurav Bhatnagar. Self - Reference and Russell s Paradox

Resemblance Nominalism: A Solution to the Problem of Universals. GONZALO RODRIGUEZ-PEREYRA. Oxford: Clarendon Press, Pp. xii, 238.

ARISTOTLE ON LANGUAGE PARALOGISMS SophElen. c.4 p.165b-166b

Lesson 10 November 10, 2009 BMC Elementary

Fallacies of Ambiguity

Jaakko Hintikka ANALYZING (AND SYNTHESIZING) ANALYSIS. theories. Yet such a theory was rampant in the seventeenth century. No less a thinker than

CS 3 Midterm 1 Review

ENGR 40M Project 3b: Programming the LED cube

Logic and Philosophy of Science (LPS)

CONTINGENCY AND TIME. Gal YEHEZKEL

ARISTOTLE AND THE UNITY CONDITION FOR SCIENTIFIC DEFINITIONS ALAN CODE [Discussion of DAVID CHARLES: ARISTOTLE ON MEANING AND ESSENCE]

Transcription:

PHIL12A Section answers, 20 April 2011 Julian Jonker 1 From last time... Compare especially (a), (d) and (e) below. 1. (Ex 11.19) (c) No cube with nothing to its left is between two cubes. x((cube(x) yleftof(y,x)) z wbetween(x,z,w)) (d) The only large cubes are b and c. Large(b) Cube(b) Large(c) Cube(c) x((large(x) Cube(x)) (x = b x = c)) (e) At most b and c are large cubes. NB: last time I omitted the following important tip printed in the textbook. There is a significant difference between this sentence and the previous one. This one does not imply that b and c are large cubes, while the previous one does. x((large(x) Cube(x)) (x = b x = c)) 2 FOL translation exercises 1. The following sentence is ambiguous. I show you how to translate it twice, showing how the English supports two different FOL translations. Every medium dodecahedron is adjacent to a medium cube. There are two ways to translate this sentence. (Note how I use constructions like for all and there is some in order to make explicit the role of quantifiers in the sentence.) (i) There is some medium cube such that all the medium dodecahedra are next to it. (ii) For every medium dodecahedron there is some medium cube that it is next to. 1

Here are the FOL translations: (i) x[cube(x) Medium(x) y((dodec(y) Medium(y)) Adjoins(x,y))] (ii) x[(dodec(x) Medium(x)) y(cube(y) Medium(y) Adjoins(x,y))] 2. One of the above translations is strong, and the other weak, in the sense that the strong sentence implies the weaker one, but not vice versa. Indicate which translation is which. (i) is the stronger claim. Whenever (i) is true, (ii) is true too. In other words, every model that makes (ii) true makes (i) true. But there are models that make (ii) true but not (i). So it is not always the case that (i) is true when (ii) is true. 3. (Ex 11.27 and 11.28) Here are two arguments, each of whose first premise is ambiguous. Translate each argument into FOL twice (using sensible predicates), corresponding to the ambiguity in the first premise. Under one translation the conclusion follows: prove it. Under the other it does not: describe a situation in which the premises are true but the conclusion false. (a) (Ex 11.27) 1 Everyone admires someone who has red hair. 2 Anyone who admires himself is conceited. 3 Someone with red hair is conceited. Here s a translation that makes the argument valid: 1 x(red(x) y(admires(x,y))) 2 x(admires(x,x) Conceited(x)) 3 x(red(x) Conceited(x) The argument would be invalid if we had translated the first premise as the weaker: x y(red(y) Admires(y,x)). (b) (Ex 11.28) 1 All that glitters is not gold. 2 This ring glitters. 3 This ring is not gold. The following translation makes the argument valid: 2

1 x(glitters(x) Gold(x)) 2 Glitters(ring) 3 Gold(ring The following weaker translation of the first premise would make the argument invalid: x(glitters(x) Gold(x)) 3 Proofs with quantifiers 1. Some of the following arguments are valid, some are not. Give an informal proof for those which are valid; for the others, give counterexamples. I ve done the first one. (a) (Ex 12.4) 1 y[cube(y) Dodec(y)] 2 x[cube(x) Large(x)] 3 x Large(x) 4 xdodec(x) Proof. The third premise tells us that there is something which is not large. Let s call this object d. Now by universal instantiation we have the following: (1) Cube(d) Dodec(d) (2) Cube(d) Large(d) By modus tollens on (2) above, we have that d is not a cube. But then by (1) above it must be the case that d is a dodecahedron. Since d was an arbitrary object in the domain of discourse, we can by existential instantiation obtain xdodec(x), which is our desired conclusion. 3

(b) (Ex 12.5) 1 y[cube(y) Dodec(y)] 2 x[cube(x) Large(x)] 3 x Large(x) 4 x[dodec(x) Small(x)] This argument is not valid. Suppose that there is a medium dodecahedron only. Then the premises are true (check this!) but the conclusion is false. (c) (Ex 12.8) 1 x[cube(x) (Tet(x) Small(x))] 2 x[large(x) BackOf(x,c)] 3 x[frontof(c,x) Cube(x)] Proof: By the second premise there is something which is large and behind c. Let s call this object e. By Existential Instantiation we get that e is large and that it is behind c. But since BackOf and FrontOf are inverses, we know that c is in front of e. Now by the first premise everything is either a cube or a small tetrahedron, so by Universal Instantiation, e is either a cube or a small tetrahedron. But we know that e is large so it must be cube. So c is in front of e and e is a cube. But now we use Existential Generalization in order to obtain our conclusion: that there is something that c is in front of and that is a cube. (d) (Ex 12.9) 1 x[(cube(x) Large(x)) (Tet(x) Small(x))] 2 x[tet(x) BackOf(x,c)] 3 x[small(x) BackOf(x,c)] Proof: We re going to reason about an arbitrary object it could be any one. For convenience, we ll call it j. We ll show by Conditional Proof that if j is small then it is behind c. But since j is arbitrary, this will be true of every object. Suppose j is small. By Universal Instantiation on the first premise we get that j is either a large cube or a small tetrahedron. Since it is small, we know it is a tetrahedron. By Universal Instantiation on the second premise we get that if j is a tetrahedron then it is behind c. So, by modus ponens, j is behind 4

c. So this shows that if j is small, then it is behind c. (In other words, we have proved Small(j) BackOf(j,c). But j was arbitrary, so by Universal Generalization, we get that any small object is behind c, which is the desired conclusion. 5