The Pragmatic Turn, by Richard J. Bernstein. Cambridge: Polity, 2010,, The Pragmatic Turn, Polity, Cambridge Malden 2010, xi pp.

Similar documents
By Rahel Jaeggi Suhrkamp, 2014, pbk 20, ISBN , 451pp. by Hans Arentshorst

PAUL REDDING S CONTINENTAL IDEALISM (AND DELEUZE S CONTINUATION OF THE IDEALIST TRADITION) Sean Bowden

UNIT SPECIFICATION FOR EXCHANGE AND STUDY ABROAD

Brandom s Reconstructive Rationality. Some Pragmatist Themes

The Strengths and Weaknesses of Frege's Critique of Locke By Tony Walton

WILLIAM JAMES STUDIES VOLUME 14 NUMBER 1 SPRING 2018 PP

Undercutting the Realism-Irrealism Debate: John Dewey and the Neo-Pragmatists

REVIEW ARTICLE IDEAL EMBODIMENT: KANT S THEORY OF SENSIBILITY

Rorty, Dewey, and Incommensurability

TROUBLING QUALITATIVE INQUIRY: ACCOUNTS AS DATA, AND AS PRODUCTS

TERMS & CONCEPTS. The Critical Analytic Vocabulary of the English Language A GLOSSARY OF CRITICAL THINKING

Mitchell ABOULAFIA, Transcendence. On selfdetermination

Anne Freadman, The Machinery of Talk: Charles Peirce and the Sign Hypothesis (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 2004), pp. xxxviii, 310.

Situated actions. Plans are represetitntiom of nction. Plans are representations of action

Sidestepping the holes of holism

Kant, Peirce, Dewey: on the Supremacy of Practice over Theory

Bas C. van Fraassen, Scientific Representation: Paradoxes of Perspective, Oxford University Press, 2008.

Philosophy of Science: The Pragmatic Alternative April 2017 Center for Philosophy of Science University of Pittsburgh ABSTRACTS

observation and conceptual interpretation

What counts as a convincing scientific argument? Are the standards for such evaluation

SUMMARY BOETHIUS AND THE PROBLEM OF UNIVERSALS

UNIT SPECIFICATION FOR EXCHANGE AND STUDY ABROAD

The topic of this Majors Seminar is Relativism how to formulate it, and how to evaluate arguments for and against it.

Philosophical Background to 19 th Century Modernism

Kęstas Kirtiklis Vilnius University Not by Communication Alone: The Importance of Epistemology in the Field of Communication Theory.

Conceptual Change, Relativism, and Rationality

WHAT S LEFT OF HUMAN NATURE? A POST-ESSENTIALIST, PLURALIST AND INTERACTIVE ACCOUNT OF A CONTESTED CONCEPT. Maria Kronfeldner

Peircean concept of sign. How many concepts of normative sign are needed. How to clarify the meaning of the Peircean concept of sign?

Philip Kitcher and Gillian Barker, Philosophy of Science: A New Introduction, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2014, pp. 192

Manuel Bremer University Lecturer, Philosophy Department, University of Düsseldorf, Germany

PHILOSOPHY OF SOCIAL SCIENCE INTS 4522 Spring Jack Donnelly and Martin Rhodes -

PRAGMATIST METAETHICS

Critical Thinking 4.2 First steps in analysis Overcoming the natural attitude Acknowledging the limitations of perception

Media as practice. a brief exchange. Nick Couldry and Mark Hobart. Published as Chapter 3. Theorising Media and Practice

Necessity in Kant; Subjective and Objective

A Comprehensive Critical Study of Gadamer s Hermeneutics

Creative Actualization: A Meliorist Theory of Values

Action, Criticism & Theory for Music Education

Are There Two Theories of Goodness in the Republic? A Response to Santas. Rachel Singpurwalla

An Intense Defence of Gadamer s Significance for Aesthetics

Uskali Mäki Putnam s Realisms: A View from the Social Sciences

BOOK REVIEW: JOHN DEWEY BETWEEN PRAGMATISM RECONSTRUCTING DEMOCRACY, RECONTEXTUALIZING DEWEY: PRAGMATISM AND INTERACTIVE CONSTRUCTIVISM

CONRAD AND IMPRESSIONISM JOHN G. PETERS

Pragmatism and Idealism

Interpretive and Critical Research Traditions

What do our appreciation of tonal music and tea roses, our acquisition of the concepts

PRAGMATIZING CRITICAL THEORY S PROVINCE

A Handbook for Action Research in Health and Social Care

James SCOTT JOHNSTON, John Dewey s Earlier Logical Theory

Mixed Methods: In Search of a Paradigm

Mixing Metaphors. Mark G. Lee and John A. Barnden

Harris Wiseman, The Myth of the Moral Brain: The Limits of Moral Enhancement (Cambridge, MA and London: The MIT Press, 2016), 340 pp.

The Self as an Object of Criticism: Richard Rorty s Denial of the Objectivity of Truth. Do Kien Trung, Kobe University, Japan

IS SCIENCE PROGRESSIVE?

Book Review - Christian Gero Stallberg, Urheberrecht und moralische Rechtfertigung (2006)

Book Review. John Dewey s Philosophy of Spirit, with the 1897 Lecture on Hegel. Jeff Jackson. 130 Education and Culture 29 (1) (2013):

HEGEL S CONCEPT OF ACTION

Penultimate draft of a review which will appear in History and Philosophy of. $ ISBN: (hardback); ISBN:

Is Genetic Epistemology of Any Interest for Semiotics?

CRITICAL CONTEXTUAL EMPIRICISM AND ITS IMPLICATIONS

Kant s Critique of Judgment

Herbert Marcuse s Review of John Dewey s Logic: The Theory of Inquiry 1

Care of the self: An Interview with Alexander Nehamas

What Is Wrong with Dewey s Theory of Knowing

Truth and Method in Unification Thought: A Preparatory Analysis

Pragmatism and Experience in Contemporary Debates

Culture, Space and Time A Comparative Theory of Culture. Take-Aways

Ithaque : Revue de philosophie de l'université de Montréal

Having the World in View: Essays on Kant, Hegel, and Sellars

Università della Svizzera italiana. Faculty of Communication Sciences. Master of Arts in Philosophy 2017/18

The Polish Peasant in Europe and America. W. I. Thomas and Florian Znaniecki

Kent Academic Repository

Confines of Democracy

Ed. Carroll Moulton. Vol. 1. New York: Charles Scribner's Sons, p COPYRIGHT 1998 Charles Scribner's Sons, COPYRIGHT 2007 Gale

AESTHETICS. Key Terms

that would join theoretical philosophy (metaphysics) and practical philosophy (ethics)?

foucault s archaeology science and transformation David Webb

On Recanati s Mental Files

HEGEL, ANALYTIC PHILOSOPHY AND THE RETURN OF METAPHYISCS Simon Lumsden

INTRODUCTION TO NONREPRESENTATION, THOMAS KUHN, AND LARRY LAUDAN

Twentieth Excursus: Reference Magnets and the Grounds of Intentionality

Edward Winters. Aesthetics and Architecture. London: Continuum, 2007, 179 pp. ISBN

What Can Experimental Philosophy Do? David Chalmers

Integration, Ambivalence, and Mental Conflict

TRAGIC THOUGHTS AT THE END OF PHILOSOPHY

Practical Intuition and Rhetorical Example. Paul Schollmeier

Anchoring scientific abstractions ontological and linguistic determination following socio-instrumental pragmatism

None DEREE COLLEGE SYLLABUS FOR: PH 4028 KANT AND GERMAN IDEALISM UK LEVEL 6 UK CREDITS: 15 US CREDITS: 3/0/3. (Updated SPRING 2016) PREREQUISITES:

History Admissions Assessment Specimen Paper Section 1: explained answers

Metaphors we live by. Structural metaphors. Orientational metaphors. A personal summary

Architecture is epistemologically

1) Three summaries (2-3 pages; pick three out of the following four): due: 9/9 5% due: 9/16 5% due: 9/23 5% due: 9/30 5%

The Public and Its Problems

Normative Logic and Psychology: Peirce on Dewey Christopher Hookway

206 Metaphysics. Chapter 21. Universals

The Senses at first let in particular Ideas. (Essay Concerning Human Understanding I.II.15)

Review of Krzysztof Brzechczyn, Idealization XIII: Modeling in History

By Tetsushi Hirano. PHENOMENOLOGY at the University College of Dublin on June 21 st 2013)

Theory or Theories? Based on: R.T. Craig (1999), Communication Theory as a field, Communication Theory, n. 2, May,

Arnold I. Davidson, Frédéric Gros (eds.), Foucault, Wittgenstein: de possibles rencontres (Éditions Kimé, 2011), ISBN:

Transcription:

1 Anton Leist The Pragmatic Turn, by Richard J. Bernstein. Cambridge: Polity, 2010,, The Pragmatic Turn, Polity, Cambridge Malden 2010, xi + 263 pp. ISBN 978 0 7456 4907 8 hb 55.00; ISBN 978 0 7456 4908 5 pb 17.99 Will be published in: European Journal of Philosophy If one is asked what pragmatism is about, no short or precise answer comes readily to hand. The term pragmatism, arising from the Greek pragma, meaning action, signals an effort to bring intellectual things down to questions of practical interest but this surely is too wide a circumscription. Fundamentalist political movements are typically doing just this: setting academic goals regarding what to produce intellectually, out of a given interest. This is not what pragmatists are in sympathy with. Rather, what they have in mind is both a critique of socially decontextualized thought (paradigmatically traditional philosophy) and a programme of social democratic culture. These are difficult and somehow overambitious perhaps even conflicting aims. Their attack on pure thought demands from pragmatists a wide ranging campaign not only against traditional philosophy, but also against its more recent analytic manifestations: already an enormous task. But to go one step further: how do pragmatism s therapeutic quest and its partisanship for a left wing liberal policy work together? Are philosophical self criticism and democratic policy not simply too far apart? Both breadth and complexity may be the reasons why no book length treatment of pragmatist claims (or those pronounced as such) in systematic form is available today. If it is too difficult to grasp the basic ideas of pragmatism in a principled way, the most obvious alternative will be an historic exposition of pragmatist thinkers, both past and present. This is exactly how Richard Bernstein s outline of the pragmatic turn is arranged. The book collects three chapters on Peirce, James and Dewey to demonstrate early pragmatism, and three chapters on Putnam, Habermas and Rorty for late or new pragmatism. Sandwiched between these are three further chapters on Hegel and pragmatism, objectivity and truth and the linguistic turn. These more systematically

2 announced chapters, though, are again largely dealt with by reference to the authors already mentioned. The book builds on a number of already published articles, and frequently shifts the presentation from one thinker to the other, with, it seems, no reason other than a chronological one. But one of the strengths of the book is its provision of links between the early and the new pragmatists, and its challenging defence of the early pragmatists against some of the new. If one accepts the historic approach to pragmatism, are there serious gaps in Bernstein s selection? In my opinion, the omission of Davidson is the most serious. A chapter on him would have been more important than chapters on Habermas or even Rorty, notwithstanding the popularity of the latter. To which extent readers may miss Wittgenstein or Heidegger, Nietzsche or Rawls, depends on a more fine grained and systematic understanding of what pragmatists are about. By mentioning Rawls I cannot help but state that this is one general lacuna in the present understanding of pragmatism. In Bernstein s book, not untypically, there is hardly anything on moral philosophy. Bernstein presents Putnam s attack on the fourth dogma of empiricism (p. 156), the factvalue dichotomy (Ch. 7), and he gives a sympathetic treatment of Habermas discourse ethics (Ch. 8). But both topics are not an adequate substitute for reflecting on what a pragmatist ethics would look like; nor whether pragmatists, especially Dewey, still have something to offer to present day moral philosophy. Most of the pragmatists had, and have, quite different views on ethics: Peirce might have had a Kantian view, James was a Millian, Dewey had eclectic, pluralist views, while the new pragmatists Putnam, Habermas and Rorty side in different ways with open and free discourse, without overly engaging in its systematic defence. In my opinion Rawls, even if not a self pronounced pragmatist, today comes closest to what a pragmatist ethics should look like; and he, strangely enough, is not really acknowledged by the new pragmatists as a fellow thinker. In my view, the dubious state of a pragmatist ethics points to a lacuna in the positive, normative part of pragmatism s project. This lacuna is a serious one, because it also affects the constructive meaning of pragmatism with regards to theoretical philosophy. It points to a missing synchrony between its radical philosophy critical attitude and its liberal political claims. Why this is a problem can be more clearly seen if we have a look at the anti

3 philosophical argument typically offered by pragmatists. And this part of the pragmatist agenda is well documented in Bernstein s book. Insofar as there is a thread running through the book, it is the attack on traditional epistemology which unifies all pragmatists. As Bernstein emphasises at the outset, with a citation from Menand (p. 10), the early pragmatists share a critique of the realist vision incorporated in much of typical epistemology and metaphysics. The motive for this is not itself philosophical in some lofty sense; rather, it builds on a naturalist view of what generally impels inquiry, taking into account biological, psychological and social forces. Ideas for the pragmatists are social creations, but they are also evolutionary products (Dewey) and emotional constructs (James). The early pragmatists are naturalists, but naturalists of a specific sort. They want less to scientifically supplement than to transform epistemology into a philosophico naturalist discipline, and this is what gives their programme its exclusive, even if up until now hotly contested, relevance. Bernstein s treatment of the early pragmatist begins well, with Peirce s earliest articles invoking the logic of scientific procedure against the overexcited, absolute sceptical questioning of Descartes (p. 18). The early pragmatists attack distinctions such as mind/body, corrigible/incorrigible, universal/local, necessary/contingent if handled in a dichotomous and not merely distinctive manner. In a sense the dismissal of dichotomies can be summarized as a dismissal of different versions of something absolute as against something humanly relative, and this shows why the opposition to the traditional, realist epistemology lay at the beginning of the pragmatist movement. Since Plato s introduction of ideal forms set the agenda for Western philosophy, the separation of man s cognitive and emotional nature, thoughts and emotions, or human powers that do or do not reach beyond humans, was very much on the mind of philosophers. Bernstein is most explicit on this in his depiction of Peirce, for him (as opposed to Rorty), the most original and important of the pragmatists. The way he commemorates Peirce is oriented by a sort of via media strategy offered at several turns of the argument, addressing the calamities that await those striving as boldly as the pragmatists do for a standpoint which is both naturalist and philosophical. Searching for a balanced solution

4 between extremes may be taken as the intellectual signature of this book, perhaps in harmony with Bernstein s usual way of dealing with conceptual contradictions. i But one objection to the pragmatist, given its thorough opposition to epistemology, is obvious: how to steer clear of a naively uncritical acceptance of everyday thinking, including everyday scientific thinking, if the reflective potential of epistemology is rejected as illusionary? What, according to Bernstein, is Peirce s via media through this conflict? A two tiered answer is given in the first and sixth chapters of the book. The first, more direct answer refers to Peirce s critical commonsensism (p. 34), which develops a fallibilist and social notion of knowledge by distinguishing between indubitable and incorrigible truths. Peirce points out that, if backed up by the right amount of societal consensus, we can reach a point of certainty but we are not incorrigibly right. Genuine knowledge need not be absolutely indubitable, only well embedded in a social community. Such knowledge is intended to be critical because of its fallibilist status: something that Popper later demonstrated to be important for science and society in a much more elaborate manner. In the second stage of his argument, Bernstein presents Peirce as guarding himself against an idealistic, purely coherentist understanding of knowledge by drawing on a once more critically reclaimed concept of experience. As Bernstein rightly documents, this is also the stage where early and new pragmatists part company, as the linguistic turn motivates the new pragmatists of whom the most outspoken is Rorty to shun all talk of experience in favour of talk of sentences and language use. The terminal point of this movement is incorporated in Davidson s notorious dictum that nothing can count as a reason for holding a belief except another belief (p. 46), which has been carried to even more appalling anti realistic consequences by Rorty. Bernstein recoils from Rorty s claim that there are only conversational constraints to knowledge (pp. 134, 207). Not only does he see a form of linguistic idealism in such a pure coherence position, he also chides it as giving up in terms of normative politics. For a pragmatist, then, two dangers stand out. On the one hand there is the concept of experience being in danger of falling back into the myth of the given, on the other there is a loss of critical norms, if authority is reduced to

5 the conversational powers that be. Bernstein s pragmatism attempts to steer clear both of Descartes and the empiricists on the one hand, and of Rorty and Davidson on the other. Perhaps due to the book s textbook format, one does not find developed arguments as to whether there is, in fact, a way through these handicaps. The book devotes itself extensively to exposition and deals with such a large portion of philosophical history, that it runs out of space for detailed argument. But often it points to where an argument should be found, and hints at how it might be elaborated. Bernstein suggest that rehabilitating the phenomenon of experience is a way of avoiding linguistic idealism, and that Peirce s system of Firstness, Secondness and Thirdness even more than James and Dewey s conceptions of experience is most helpful as part of this aim (Ch.6). The linguistic turn is charged for having discarded all theories of experience and having put language and meaning in its place. With dramatic flair Bernstein criticises Rorty s pragmatism as a pragmatism without experience (p. 128). It is true that the notion of experience has lost its foundational role in epistemic disputes since the linguistic turn, but to cast this as a problem is more rhetoric than argument. Experience as a compound may have been lost, but perception, practice and knowledge all elements of experience are still well taken care of. At any rate, what is missing in Bernstein s complaint is a more thorough analysis, beyond the citation of typical statements from Peirce (and further from James and Dewey), as to why Peirce s triadic view on signs and experience is something unfortunately lost by talking instead of language and concepts. Bernstein, fixated as he is on Rorty s lamented idealism, never touches upon what advancement was really brought about by the linguistic turn versus the psychological talk about experience. Peirce still set himself the task somehow to construct meaningful signs and their function for experience with the help of more elementary pieces, those pooled together with the terms Firstness (the immediate in experience) and Secondness (responses to the immediate), thereby clumsily wrestling with a newly invented pseudopsychological terminology. The triadic relation and its terms are surely an improved version of the older subject object distinction, but they are still a version of it, whereas it

6 would be better to avoid such oppositions altogether. Bernstein s via media solution, in regard to Peirce, is to call his triadic scheme one of distinguishable, but not separable (p. 130) elements. In the end, however, it remains unclear what it is that makes the nonseparable unity: is it something in the world, something subjective, a habit, or something else? Perhaps the comprising entity is meant to be experience, but then it remains unclear what experience is, besides being a something which comprises. Mead s idea of social communication, which Bernstein suggests is the solution for all problems remaining in the classical pragmatists concept of experience (p. 151), is surely not an easyway out. What Mead supplies is a still more primitive psychological method, behaviourism, which leads to a dubious epistemological understanding of meaning. One who has followed through the linguistic turn would instead suggest giving up on attempts to find out how Firstness, Secondness and Thirdness might be sensibly put together, and instead begin reflecting from a position within language use, from sentences and communicative understanding instead of signs. If she wished, she could try to make sense of what Peirce, James or Dewey had been up to from within this use, which is taken for granted. But she would depart from the idea of constructing language and experience from somewhere deep below, as the early pragmatists (still partially) did. ii Would she therefore fall into the trap of linguistic idealism or, something deplored by Bernstein, fail in managing to lose contact with the everyday life world of human beings (p. 152)? It is the everyday world of linguistic understanding, including acting on the basis of such understanding, with which she begins. The linguistic philosopher may come to the rescue of sorting out what is good and bad in early pragmatism, instead of being helped by an outdated psychological epistemology. The one central positive message in this book, therefore, seems to misfire. Whatever is problematic in new pragmatism, and especially in Rorty, cannot be repaired by reading the classical pragmatists more thoroughly. The linguistic turn put their psychology based agenda to rest for good. Does the book highlight the political part of pragmatism, its defence of a social or liberal democratic position? (This is something that excludes, of course, Peirce, and to a lesser extent James but Dewey, Putnam, Habermas and Rorty each voice a liberal democratic position.) Liberal (i.e. social) democracy as present in these thinkers is represented by

7 principles of universality, equality and freedom. Bernstein includes a chapter on Dewey and democracy (Ch. 3) and reports comperable thoughts by Putnam and Habermas. The chapter on Dewey leaves one in a similar state to when one reads many texts by Dewey himself. The impression that Dewey is up to something genuine conflicts with the observation that he is not able to verbalize it. The same occurs with Bernstein s depiction, which in part adopts the Polonius like quality familiar from Dewey texts. Bernstein s method is, again, the via media approach. Dewey is a liberal but not an individualist, he favours community but is not a communitarian, he accepts conflicts but also considers consensus, he is in favour of rational persuasion but also of embodied intelligence. Dewey wants politics to accomplish nothing less than encompass the full range of human experience (p. 86). One (problematic) reading of Dewey s argument for democracy arises from his belief that humans can grasp their values and interests only within, and with the help of, social contexts, optimally under a democratic regime. (Another staunch defender of this thesis again was Dewey s friend Mead.) This belief can be taken causally or normatively, and obviously, with regards to the latter, it is potentially illiberal. There is room for argument, however, if democracy, as suggested by Putnam (p. 163f.), is meant to be a precondition for inquiry, both of individuals inquiry into their idea of a life, and of scientific inquiry. Now, though, the original belief vacillates between a strong but risky and a weak but trivial thesis. Dewey (and Putnam) in part suggest that humans build up their identity only politically, and moreover in a democratic way. This would be an extremely normative statement, falsified by the dubious personal character of many professional politicians (but perhaps they follow the wrong politics?). If, on the other hand, liberal freedom is meant to be a precondition for unimpeded socialisation and private decisions, this is common lore of large parts of liberalism. Dewey, Putnam and Bernstein stand of course, some distance away from the private/public distinction at the basis of this kind of liberalism, and are therefore not on this side of the alternative. Unfortunately, Bernstein remains silent on the issue of finding a way out of this impasse, and also on whether Dewey would be helpful.

8 Favouring the private/public distinction concerning liberal politics is a consequent move by Rorty, in the light of his radical critique of epistemology. Along with this goes a rather minimal liberalism of fear, which has always seemed at odds with his fondness for Dewey. The importance of the anti epistemical side to pragmatism for its liberal side is clearly visible in Rorty, even if largely only negative. In not following Rorty with regards to this solution, Bernstein manifests himself as a good Deweyan, but less so as a rationally transparent pragmatist. Anton Leist Research Centre for Ethics University of Zurich Switzerland leist@access.uzh.edu NOTES i Via media-solutions are offered on pp. 49, 51, 58, 84, 129, 226 fn.12. ii For further advantages of this move see Davidson 2002. REFERENCES Davidson, D. (2002), The Myth of the Subjective, reprinted in D. Davidson, Subjective, Intersubjective, Objective. Oxford: Oxford University Press.