Kalevi Kull 1. [...] and since knowledge is habit [...]. (1906, CP 4.531) 4

Similar documents
44 Iconicity in Peircean situated cognitive Semiotics

Priscila Lena Farias* and João Queiroz On Peirce s diagrammatic models for ten classes of signs

Monday August 25. Göran Sonesson: Phenomenological semiotics.

Terminology. - Semantics: Relation between signs and the things to which they refer; their denotata, or meaning

Peircean concept of sign. How many concepts of normative sign are needed. How to clarify the meaning of the Peircean concept of sign?

Biosemiotics: To Know, What Life Knows. Kalevi Kull 1. Whether biology has studied what organisms know?

Is Genetic Epistemology of Any Interest for Semiotics?

Community of Inquiry and Inquiry- based learning

C. S. Peirce s formal science of signs provides an analytic framework

Journal of Nonlocality Round Table Series Colloquium #4

Keywords: semiotic; pragmatism; space; embodiment; habit, social practice.

Specialization, semiosis, semiotics: the 33rd annual meeting of the Semiotic Society of America

5 ETCS One Week PhD- course in

SYNTHESE LIBRARY VOLUME 329 STUDIES IN EPISTEMOLOGY, LOGIC, METHODOLOGY, AND PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE

Anne Freadman, The Machinery of Talk: Charles Peirce and the Sign Hypothesis (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 2004), pp. xxxviii, 310.

TARTU SEMIOTICS LIBRARY 11

Author Query Form. Iconic semiosis and representational efficiency in the London Underground Diagram

Action, Criticism & Theory for Music Education

The Polish Peasant in Europe and America. W. I. Thomas and Florian Znaniecki

ENVIRONMENTAL EXPERIENCE: Beyond Aesthetic Subjectivism and Objectivism

SYSTEM-PURPOSE METHOD: THEORETICAL AND PRACTICAL ASPECTS Ramil Dursunov PhD in Law University of Fribourg, Faculty of Law ABSTRACT INTRODUCTION

Diagrams, Iconicity, and Abductive Discovery

CHAPTER I INTRODUCTION

Intersemiotic translation: The Peircean basis

Action, Criticism & Theory for Music Education

Pragmatism, Semiotic mind and Cognitivism

Semiotic modelling of biological processes: semiotic systems João Queiroz a,b,c & Charbel El-Hani a,b

LIMITATIONS ON APPLYING PEIRCEAN SEMEIOTIC

Symposium on Semiotics and Mathematics with the Special Theme 'Peirce, the Mathematician', June 11 13

Space, Time, and Interpretation

Daniella Aguiar and Joao Queiroz Semiosis and intersemiotic translation

Bent Sørensen and Torkild Leo Thellefsen

Entropy ISSN by MDPI

Semiotics of Terminology: A Semiotic Knowledge Profile

THREE ABDUCTIVE SOLUTIONS TO THE MENO PARADOX WITH INSTINCT, INFERENCE, AND DISTRIBUTED COGNITION. SAMI PAAVOLA and KAI HAKKARAINEN

INTERPRETING HUMAN S PLACE IN NATURE LILL SARV Università degli Studi di Bari

Embodied Experience and the Semiosis of Abductive Reasoning. Donna E. West State University of New York at Cortland

Information in Biosemiotics: Introduction to the Special Issue

Kant, Peirce, Dewey: on the Supremacy of Practice over Theory

Pragmatism and Idealism

KANT S TRANSCENDENTAL LOGIC

Introduction SABINE FLACH, DANIEL MARGULIES, AND JAN SÖFFNER

Thinking of or Thinking Through Diagrams? The Case of Conceptual Graphs.

Current Issues in Pictorial Semiotics

Prephilosophical Notions of Thinking

Emotionally Charged Aesthetic Experience. Määttänen, Pentti. Springer 2015

Leverhulme Research Project Grant Narrating Complexity: Communication, Culture, Conceptualization and Cognition

days of Saussure. For the most, it seems, Saussure has rightly sunk into

Lecture (0) Introduction

What do our appreciation of tonal music and tea roses, our acquisition of the concepts

Habit, Semeiotic Naturalism, and Unity among the Sciences Aaron Wilson

Logic and Philosophy of Science (LPS)

Ithaque : Revue de philosophie de l'université de Montréal

The Teaching Method of Creative Education

observation and conceptual interpretation

TERMS & CONCEPTS. The Critical Analytic Vocabulary of the English Language A GLOSSARY OF CRITICAL THINKING

Seven remarks on artistic research. Per Zetterfalk Moving Image Production, Högskolan Dalarna, Falun, Sweden

By Rahel Jaeggi Suhrkamp, 2014, pbk 20, ISBN , 451pp. by Hans Arentshorst

The role of productive imagination in creating artworks and discovering scientific hypotheses

Moving Pictures of Thought II: Graphs, Games, and Pragmaticism s Proofs

Postprint.

SocioBrains THE INTEGRATED APPROACH TO THE STUDY OF ART

TEST BANK. Chapter 1 Historical Studies: Some Issues

Natika Newton, Foundations of Understanding. (John Benjamins, 1996). 210 pages, $34.95.

Ideology the Metalanguage of Culture

Truth and Method in Unification Thought: A Preparatory Analysis

In Pursuit of Objectivity. Chiara Ambrosio Department of Science and Technology Studies University College London

Mind, Thinking and Creativity

Bertolotti, Tommaso. Science-Like Gossip, or Gossip-Like Science? Social Epistemology Review and Reply Collective 6, no. 7 (2017):

Edusemiotics To Date, an Introduction of

Semiosis as an Emergent Process

From Pythagoras to the Digital Computer: The Intellectual Roots of Symbolic Artificial Intelligence

International conference on William James and Pragmatism

Conclusion. One way of characterizing the project Kant undertakes in the Critique of Pure Reason is by

Book Review. John Dewey s Philosophy of Spirit, with the 1897 Lecture on Hegel. Jeff Jackson. 130 Education and Culture 29 (1) (2013):

On The Search for a Perfect Language

1/8. The Third Paralogism and the Transcendental Unity of Apperception

Dabney Townsend. Hume s Aesthetic Theory: Taste and Sentiment Timothy M. Costelloe Hume Studies Volume XXVIII, Number 1 (April, 2002)

TARTU SUMMER SCHOOL OF SEMIOTICS 2011 SEMIOTIC MODELLING

1. What is Phenomenology?

Reply to Stalnaker. Timothy Williamson. In Models and Reality, Robert Stalnaker responds to the tensions discerned in Modal Logic

The Object Oriented Paradigm

EUROPEAN JOURNAL OF PRAGMATISM AND AMERICAN PHILOSOPHY. The History of Reception of Charles S. Peirce in Greece 1

The Cybersemiotic Model of Communication: An Evolutionary View on the Threshold between Semiosis and Informational Exchange 1

What Is Wrong with Dewey s Theory of Knowing

10/24/2016 RESEARCH METHODOLOGY Lecture 4: Research Paradigms Paradigm is E- mail Mobile

Mixed Methods: In Search of a Paradigm

Phenomenology Glossary

Dicisigns and Habits. Implicit propositions and habit-taking in Peirce's pragmatism. Frederik Stjernfelt

On Recanati s Mental Files

Review of Krzysztof Brzechczyn, Idealization XIII: Modeling in History

Neglected Aspects of Peirce s Writings: Contributions to Ethics and Humanism

A Study of the Bergsonian Notion of <Sensibility>

Interdepartmental Learning Outcomes

SYMBOLIZATION AND DIALOGUE OF CULTURES: SEQUEL OF CULTURAL AND HISTORICAL TRADITION

Chapter 2: The Early Greek Philosophers MULTIPLE CHOICE

C. S. Peirce s Evolutionary Sign: an Analysis of Depth and Complexity within Peircean Sign Types and Peircean Evolution Theory.

CONRAD AND IMPRESSIONISM JOHN G. PETERS

A new aspect of sign and its implications for the Theory of Communication

Capstone Design Project Sample

Transcription:

Sign Systems Habits Studies semioses 44(4), 2016, habits 623 629 Habits semioses habits Kalevi Kull 1 Review of Consensus on Peirce s Concept of Habit: Before and Beyond Consciousness. (Studies in Applied Philosophy, Epistemology and Rational Ethics 31.) Donna E. West and Myrdene Anderson (eds.). Cham: Springer, 2016, 434 pp. The most plastic of all things is the human mind, and next after that comes the organic world, the world of protoplasm. Now the generalizing tendency is the great law of mind, the law of association, the law of habit taking. We also find in all active protoplasm a tendency to take habits. Hence I was led to the hypothesis that the laws of the universe have been formed under a universal tendency of all things toward generalization and habit-taking. (1898, CP 7.515) 2 It may fairly be urged that since the phenomena of habit may thus result from a purely mechanical arrangement, it is unnecessary to suppose that habit-taking is a primordial principle of the universe. (1892, CP 6.262) 3 [...] and since knowledge is habit [...]. (1906, CP 4.531) 4 This brief essay is a reflection on and appreciation of the thorough work collected and edited by Donna E. West and Myrdene Anderson entitled Consensus on Peirce s Concept of Habit: Before and Beyond Consciousness (2016) on the phenomenon and concept of habit through the interpretation of the legacy of Charles S. Peirce. Semiotics is not yet completed. Semiotics whose role is to serve with fundamental theories and methods of all sciences that study knowing and meaning-making in all their forms (including the primitive forms of semiosis ever since life emerged) has a long history; however, as an institutionalized field it is only a half a century old. Habits of this science are not yet taught in many schools, and they are not ready either. 1 Author s address: Department of Semiotics, University of Tartu, Jakobi 2, Tartu 51014, Estonia; e-mail: kalevi.kull@ut.ee. 2 See also Santaella 2016 and Sonesson 2016 in the volume of West and Anderson, as well as Kull 2014, who all comment on this passage. 3 See also comments in Houser 2010: lxxxix. 4 See comments in Kilpinen 2015: 167 168. http://dx.doi.org/10.12697/sss.2016.44.4.07

624 Kalevi Kull Semiotics experiences its youthfulness. Accordingly, our part is pleasure and pain, ours an era of fascinating insights and discoveries in semiotics as well as changes in views, or hard work and tiresome discussions. No concept is protected against reinterpretation. Habit is a fundamental concept for semiotics; at least the development of semiotics demonstrates it is becoming one. It already was one in the thought of Peirce, 5 and for that reason an inquiry into his work is a significant part of semiotics. The development of the concept of habit has much to teach to us. 6 For instance, it was important in the discussions of evolution and development in Peirce s times. Speaking of the Law of Habit, Joseph John Murphy, in Habit and Intelligence, says that all vital actions whatever tend to repeat themselves, and consequently to become habitual ; he also speaks about three main types of habits: formative, motor, and mental habits, mentioning that the law of mental habit is usually called the law of association of ideas (Murphy 1869: 48). As Conwy Lloyd Morgan states in Habit and Instinct, habit [...] involves individual acquisition (Morgan 1896: 17). Or, as Samuel Butler observes in Life and Habit, unconscious knowledge and unconscious volition are never acquired otherwise than as a result of experience, familiarity, or habit (Butler 1878: 18). James Mark Baldwin (1906: 452) adds, concerning an organism s development, [F]irst, it develops by getting habits formed; and second, it develops by getting new adaptations which involve the breaking up or modification of habits these latter being called accommodations. In Peirce s system, habit takes a most fundamental place. All these scholars were important as regards the formation of the understanding of evolution on the basis of organic selection, or the Baldwinian mechanism, that today is known as a part of the Post-Darwinian, or epigenetic account of organic evolution. 7 And this is not all. When the social aspect of habit is brought into a focus, a line of development of this concept appears which leads from Peirce s habit via Erwin Panofsky to Pierre Bourdieu s habitus (see Viola 2012). 8 Yet another dimension of habit is related to moral decisions and ethics (see, e.g., Colapietro 2011). How is diversification possible in the world? This was one of the central problems Peirce attempted to solve. However, it appears to have been a little too early for a scientifically well-argued answer to be formulated. Anyhow, modelling of habit is a 5 Cf. Pietarinen (2015: 378): It turns out that at least experience and habit, two cornerstones of Peirce s thought, do not fall under the umbrella of signs. Every sign has its representative quality, its meaning. Meaning, in turn, is a habit, and it is derived from experience. 6 E.g, the use of the concept of habit already by David Hume, or in later psychology (Roeckelein 1998: 224 225). 7 Also called Extended Synthesis, or semiotic theory of evolution; on this, see Kull 2016. 8 In this respect, see also Nöth 2016 and Sonesson 2016 in the volume of West and Anderson.

Habits semioses habits 625 constituent of the problem of diversification. Theoretical semiotics has a long way to go, and this is kept in mind in the formulations that follow. The semiotic concept of habit Habits are regularities that are products of semiosis. Any habit is a regularity produced by semiosis. The process involved in habit-change is learning. Learning modifies habits and establishes new ones. Habits presuppose learning. Thus habits carry on one s experience. Semiotics is a fundamental field of (study of) knowing and habits are necessary for any knowing. Even more as Peirce said, knowledge is habit (CP 4.531). Jaakko Hintikka (2007: 17) added, Surely the first order of business of any genuine theory of knowledge the most important task both theoretically and practically is how new [knowledge can be] acquired, not merely how previously obtained information can be evaluated. As Erkki Kilpinen (2015: 160) has said, habits are vehicles of cognition. With a reference to John Dewey, Kilpinen (2015: 160) also states that intentionality without habituality is empty, habituality without intentionality is blind. 9 What exactly is the relationship between semiosis and habit? Or rather, in the plural semioses and habits (since sign is never single). Do habits include semioses or does semiosis always precede habit? The formula habits semioses habits can be used as a simple representation of the dynamic relationship. Semiosis occurs due to certain incompatibility in the interaction of habits, thus it requires habits. As a result of semioses, habits will change, or new habits appear. It is reasonable to hypothesize that semiosis takes place only in a phenomenal present (in specious present, as William James used the term). 10 Or rather semiosis creates the phenomenal present, the now. (We can even say that semiosis is the phenomenal now.) This is because interpretation assumes a possibility for choice (between options), while choice truly cannot happen in a sequentionality, it presumes presence and the present. In this aspect, semiosis is a choice between habits. Habits themselves are sequential behaviours. Habits are inferences carried out by life far before logic becomes conscious or formal. Not only is habit repeated (almost automatic) behaviour; habit may also be repeated semiosis. 9 Cf. Dewey (1922: 67): Thought which does not exist within ordinary habits of action lacks means of execution. Cf. also comments in Glăveanu 2014 about habitual creativity. 10 More on this in Kull 2015.

626 Kalevi Kull The regularity of habits is based on scaffoldings (Hoffmeyer 2014). The scaffoldings, however, are modified by habits themselves. Habit is always a construing. Thus, it is a basis for creativity (Glăveanu 2014). Almost paradoxically, the force of habit works as vis vitalis. Consensus on Peirce s concept of habit? Donna West and Myrdene Anderson have compiled and edited a book that can be described as a collective monograph on, and also a companion to, the Peircean approach to the phenomenon of habit. As far as I know, this book constitutes the first treatment of Peirce s unique concept of habit. The editors of this volume are professional semioticians whose impact on contemporary semiotics has been remarkable (e.g., Anderson et al. 1984; 2003; Adams, Anderson 1994; Anderson, Merrell 1991; Anderson 2004, 2016a; West 2014). They have done marvellous work in carefully uniting the efforts of 27 semioticians from 12 countries: USA (7), Italy (3), Brazil (3), Finland (3), Germany (2), UK (2), Estonia (2), Sweden (1), Denmark (1), Norway (1), Mexico (1), Uruguay (1). The book includes 23 chapters: the Preamble by Anderson, the Epilogue by West, and 6+7+8 articles, divided into three parts. An appendix includes a brief glossary of some of Peirce s terms. The list of authors is impressive. Part I (Background: Eco-logical Systems) includes the contributions of Dinda L. Gorlée, Winfried Nöth, John Coletta, Stanley N. Salthe, John Pickering, Pedro Atã and João Queiroz. Part II (Habit as Action Schema) consist of chapters by Juuso-Ville Gustafsson and Ahti-Veikko Pietarinen, Atocha Aliseda, Lucia Santaella, Mats Bergman, Erkki Kilpinen, Donna E. West, and Frederik Stjernfelt. Part III (Mental Complexions of Habit) contains writings by Ahti- Veikko Pietarinen and Francesco Bellucci, Göran Sonesson, Vincent Colapietro, Sara Cannizzaro and Myrdene Anderson, Fernando Andacht, Lorenzo Magnani, Selene Arfini and Tommaso Bertolotti, Nathan Houser, Elize Bisanz and Scott Cunningham. From its title, Consensus on Peirce s Concept of Habit, one may assume that the volume assuredly states the consolidation and settledness of Peirce s approach in semiotics. Indeed, one can say that the last decade has shown the possibility of arriving at a productive agreement in the interpretation of the core of Peirce s theory (in this respect I would particularly like to emphasize the work of Ahti-Veikko Pietarinen, Francesco Bellucci, Nathan Houser, Vincent Colapietro). This impression should be still kept apart from an association with a final consensus that is obviously impossible in case of Peirce. The book is rich in fresh ideas and fine formulations. For illustration, a few hints in the form of quotations.

Habits semioses habits 627 Myrdene Anderson (2016b: 8): Understanding self as a manifestation of a bundle of habits, implicates self-control as a player. It happens that contemporary research in the social and behavioural sciences seems to back into the study of selfcontrol, though seldom via Peirce s insights. [...] Probably no single angle of habit will turn out to be so significant to the contemporary world as self-control. Indeed, the topic of self-control is discussed in the papers by Gorlée, Nöth, Gustafsson and Pietarinen, Santaella, Bergman, Kilpinen, West, Stjernfelt. Pietarinen and Bellucci, Colapietro, Cannizzaro and Anderson, in this volume about habit. Dinda Gorlée (2016: 31): Habits show clear signs of improvement during each year of Peirce s early work. [...] The original word habit comes from Aristotle s right and wrong behavior, but transfigured by Peirce into the term of acquired (learned) habits as inferior sign to Thirdness. An exact synopsis. Ahti-Veikko Pietarinen and Francesco Bellucci (2016: 265): The logical representative interpretant is a principle not itself a premise, a rule not itself subject to rules, a habit not itself a sign. A habit may not be a sign. It is important to keep the concept of habit separated from the concept of physical law. Habit is a locally acquired regularity, a rule of behaviour with its exceptions. By definition, a physical law is, in contrast, universal, without exceptions, not acquired. The excellent volume by Donna West and Myrdene Anderson about the concept of habit is a part of the collective work on the conceptual apparatus of semiotics that semiotic science systematically has to engage in and accomplish. References Adams, Walter, R.; Anderson, Myrdene (eds.) 1994. Refiguring debris becoming unbecoming, unbecoming becoming. Special issue of The American Journal of Semiotics 11(1/2): 63 289. Anderson, Myrdene (ed.) 2004. Cultural Shaping of Violence: Victimization, Escalation, Response. West Lafayette: Purdue University Press. 2016a. My half-century saturated in semiotics: A spiralling confessional. Sign Systems Studies 44(1/2): 267 288. 2016b. Preamble Peircean habit explored: Before, during, after; and beneath, behind, beyond. In: West, Anderson 2016: 1 10. Anderson, Myrdene; Deely, John; Krampen, Martin; Ransdell, Joseph; Sebeok, Thomas A.; Uexküll, Thure von 1984. A semiotic perspective on the sciences: Steps toward a new paradigm. Semiotica 44: 7 47. Anderson, Myrdene; Merrell, Floyd (eds.) 1991. On Semiotic Modeling. (Approaches to Semiotics 97.) Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter. Anderson, Myrdene; Sáenz-Ludlow, Adalira; Zellweger, Shea; Cifarelli, Victor V. (eds.) 2003. Educational Perspectives on Mathematics as Semiosis: From Thinking to Interpreting to Knowing. Ottawa: Legas Publishing.

628 Kalevi Kull Baldwin, James Mark 1906. The Mental Development of the Child and the Race. (3rd ed.) New York: Macmillan & Co. Butler, Samuel 1878. Life and Habit. London: Trübner & Co. Colapietro, Vincent 2011. Customary reflection and innovative habits. The Journal of Speculative Philosophy 25(2): 161 173. Dewey, John 1922. Human Nature and Conduct: An Introduction to Social Psychology. New York: Henry Holt and Company. Glăveanu, Vlad Petre 2014. Thinking through Creativity and Culture: Toward an Integrated Model. New Brunswick: Transactions Publishers. Gorlée, Dinda 2016. On habit: Peirce s story and history. In West, Anderson 2016: 13 34. Hintikka, Jaakko 2007. Socratic Epistemology: Explorations of Knowledge-Seeking by Questioning. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Hoffmeyer, Jesper 2014. The semiome: From genetic to semiotic scaffolding. Semiotica 198: 11 31. Houser, Nathan 2010. Introduction. In: Peirce, Charles Sanders, Writings of Charles S. Peirce: A Chronological Edition. Volume 8: 1890 1892. Bloomington: Indiana University Press, xxv xcvii. Kilpinen, Erkki 2015. Habit, action, and knowledge, from the pragmatist perspective. In: Zackariasson, Ulf (ed.), Action, Belief and Inquiry: Pragmatist Perspectives on Science, Society and Religion. (Nordic Studies in Pragmatism 3.) Helsinki: Nordic Pragmatism Network, 157 173. Kull, Kalevi 2014. Physical laws are not habits, while rules of life are. In: Thellefsen, Torkild; Sørensen, Bent (eds.), Charles Sanders Peirce in His Own Words: 100 Years of Semiotics, Communication and Cognition. (Semiotics, Communication and Cognition 14.) Boston: De Gruyter Mouton, 87 94. 2015. Evolution, choice, and scaffolding: Semiosis is changing its own building. Biosemiotics 8(2): 223 234. 2016. What kind of evolutionary biology suits cultural research? Sign Systems Studies 44(4): 634 647. Morgan, Conwy Lloyd 1896. Habit and Instinct. London: Edward Arnold. Murphy, Joseph John 1869. Habit and Intelligence, in their Connexion with the Laws of Matter and Force: A Series of Scientific Essays. Vol. 2. London: Macmillan and Co. Nöth, Winfried 2016. Habits, habit change, and the habit of habit change according to Peirce. In: West, Anderson 2016: 35 64. Pietarinen, Ahti-Veikko 2015. Signs systematically studied: Invitation to Peirce s theory. Sign Systems Studies 43(4): 372 398. Pietarinen, Ahti-Veikko; Bellucci, Francesco 2016. Habits of reasoning: On the grammar and critics of logical habits. In: West, Anderson 2016: 265 282. Roeckelein, Jon E. 1998. Dictionary of Theories, Laws, and Concepts in Psychology. Westport: Greenwood Press. Santaella, Lucia 2016. The originality and relevance of Peirce s concept of habit. In: West, Anderson 2016: 153 170. Sonesson, Göran 2016. Thirdness as the observer observed: From habit to law by way of habitus. In: West, Anderson 2016: 283 296.

Habits semioses habits 629 Viola, Tullio 2012. Peirce and iconology: Habitus, embodiment, and the analogy between philosophy and architecture. European Journal of Pragmatism and American Philosophy 4(1): 6 31. West, Donna E. 2014. Deictic Imaginings: Semiosis at Work and at Play. Heidelberg: Springer. West, Donna E., Anderson, Myrdene (eds.) 2016. Consensus on Peirce s Concept of Habit: Before and Beyond Consciousness. (Studies in Applied Philosophy, Epistemology and Rational Ethics 31.) Cham: Springer.