SoPhA 2018: contribution submission. Continuity, Mathematisation, and Conceptual Change Continuité, mathématisation et changement conceptuel!

Similar documents
Philosophy Historical and Philosophical Foundations of Set Theory Syllabus: Autumn:2005

Introduction to Special Issue: Dedekind and the Philosophy of Mathematics

UNIT SPECIFICATION FOR EXCHANGE AND STUDY ABROAD

Information-not-thing: further problems with and alternatives to the belief that information is physical

On Recanati s Mental Files

The Logic in Dedekind s Logicism

EUROPEAN JOURNAL OF PRAGMATISM AND AMERICAN PHILOSOPHY. The History of Reception of Charles S. Peirce in Greece 1

Università della Svizzera italiana. Faculty of Communication Sciences. Master of Arts in Philosophy 2017/18

Bas C. van Fraassen, Scientific Representation: Paradoxes of Perspective, Oxford University Press, 2008.

Action Theory for Creativity and Process

Ithaque : Revue de philosophie de l'université de Montréal

SUMMARY BOETHIUS AND THE PROBLEM OF UNIVERSALS

From Pythagoras to the Digital Computer: The Intellectual Roots of Symbolic Artificial Intelligence

TÉLÉCHARGER LIRE DOWNLOAD READ. Description

The Strengths and Weaknesses of Frege's Critique of Locke By Tony Walton

Análisis Filosófico ISSN: Sociedad Argentina de Análisis Filosófico Argentina

Published in: International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 29(2) (2015):

Verity Harte Plato on Parts and Wholes Clarendon Press, Oxford 2002

Intelligible Matter in Aristotle, Aquinas, and Lonergan. by Br. Dunstan Robidoux OSB

Necessity in Kant; Subjective and Objective

Scientific Philosophy

December 2018 Language and cultural workshops In-between session workshops à la carte December weeks All levels

Are There Two Theories of Goodness in the Republic? A Response to Santas. Rachel Singpurwalla

A Note on Analysis and Circular Definitions

Reply to Stalnaker. Timothy Williamson. In Models and Reality, Robert Stalnaker responds to the tensions discerned in Modal Logic

FROM TRANSLATION, NO ONE ESCAPES

The Shimer School Core Curriculum

Philosophy 405: Knowledge, Truth and Mathematics Spring Russell Marcus Hamilton College

Sidestepping the holes of holism

Aesthetics Mid-Term Exam Review Guide:

Logic and Philosophy of Science (LPS)

7AAN2056: Philosophy of Mathematics Syllabus Academic year 2016/17

Incommensurability and Partial Reference

Partial and Paraconsistent Approaches to Future Contingents in Tense Logic

Social Mechanisms and Scientific Realism: Discussion of Mechanistic Explanation in Social Contexts Daniel Little, University of Michigan-Dearborn

Phenomenology Glossary

WHITEHEAD'S PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE AND METAPHYSICS

Interdepartmental Learning Outcomes

observation and conceptual interpretation

Penultimate draft of a review which will appear in History and Philosophy of. $ ISBN: (hardback); ISBN:

du Châtelet s ontology: element, corpuscle, body

The Nature of Time. Humberto R. Maturana. November 27, 1995.

INTERVIEW: ONTOFORMAT Classical Paradigms and Theoretical Foundations in Contemporary Research in Formal and Material Ontology.

THE MATHEMATIZABLE PROPERTIES OF HUMAN BODIES IN RELATION TO MEILLASSOUX S DISCUSSION OF PRIMARY QUALITIES

Logical Foundations of Mathematics and Computational Complexity a gentle introduction

Building blocks of a legal system. Comments on Summers Preadvies for the Vereniging voor Wijsbegeerte van het Recht

Doctoral Thesis in Ancient Philosophy. The Problem of Categories: Plotinus as Synthesis of Plato and Aristotle

Introduction. Fiora Salis University of Lisbon

What do our appreciation of tonal music and tea roses, our acquisition of the concepts

6. The Cogito. Procedural Work and Assessment The Cartesian Background Merleau-Ponty: the tacit cogito

Kuhn s Notion of Scientific Progress. Christian Damböck Institute Vienna Circle University of Vienna

Practical Intuition and Rhetorical Example. Paul Schollmeier

Cover Page. The handle holds various files of this Leiden University dissertation.

INTRODUCTION TO AXIOMATIC SET THEORY

What is Character? David Braun. University of Rochester. In "Demonstratives", David Kaplan argues that indexicals and other expressions have a

Review of Krzysztof Brzechczyn, Idealization XIII: Modeling in History

In Parts of Animals I 1 (and elsewhere) Aristotle makes it clear that his goal in the study of nature is a

Sets, Symbols and Pictures: A Reflection on Euler Diagrams in Leonhard Euler s Tercentenary (2007)

In Search of Mechanisms, by Carl F. Craver and Lindley Darden, 2013, The University of Chicago Press.

Riccardo Chiaradonna, Gabriele Galluzzo (eds.), Universals in Ancient Philosophy, Edizioni della Normale, 2013, pp. 546, 29.75, ISBN

The Concept of Nature

Copy these 2 verbs into your book:

TEST BANK. Chapter 1 Historical Studies: Some Issues


A Theory of Structural Constraints on the Individual s Social Representing? A comment on Jaan Valsiner s (2003) Theory of Enablement

THE MATHEMATICS. Javier F. A. Guachalla H. The mathematics

SocioBrains THE INTEGRATED APPROACH TO THE STUDY OF ART

FLF5246 History of Ancient Philosophy (Aristotle s Psychology: Perception) 1 st semester, 2019 Prof. Evan Keeling 08 Créditos Duração: 12 semanas

The Semantic Significance of Frege s Puzzle

David Katan. Translating Cultures, An Introduction for Translators, Interpreters and Mediators. Manchester, St. Jerome Publishing, 1999, 271 p.

HPS 1653 / PHIL 1610 Introduction to the Philosophy of Science

On the Concepts of Logical Fallacy and Logical Error

1/6. The Anticipations of Perception

The Human Intellect: Aristotle s Conception of Νοῦς in his De Anima. Caleb Cohoe

Conclusion. One way of characterizing the project Kant undertakes in the Critique of Pure Reason is by

INTRODUCTION TO NONREPRESENTATION, THOMAS KUHN, AND LARRY LAUDAN

ABSOLUTE DIRECTORS ROCK, CINéMA ET CONTRE-CULTURE (CAMION NOIR) (FRENCH EDITION) BY FRANCK BUIONI

7AAN2026 Greek Philosophy I: Plato Syllabus Academic year 2015/16

THE SOCIAL RELEVANCE OF PHILOSOPHY

The Introduction of Universals

On The Search for a Perfect Language

Tamar Sovran Scientific work 1. The study of meaning My work focuses on the study of meaning and meaning relations. I am interested in the duality of

Writing Skills in French: Focus on Sustainability

Philosophy of Science: The Pragmatic Alternative April 2017 Center for Philosophy of Science University of Pittsburgh ABSTRACTS

Cultural History of Mathematics

Is Genetic Epistemology of Any Interest for Semiotics?

Mathematical Representation: playing a role

UNIT SPECIFICATION FOR EXCHANGE AND STUDY ABROAD

French 2323/4339 Fall 2015 French Cinema as Cultural Memory & Artistic Artifact Course Information Sheet and Syllabus

Kuhn Formalized. Christian Damböck Institute Vienna Circle University of Vienna

Special Issue on Ideas of Plato in the Philosophy of the 21st Century : An Introduction

CONTINGENCY AND TIME. Gal YEHEZKEL

Hypatia, Volume 21, Number 3, Summer 2006, pp (Review) DOI: /hyp For additional information about this article

Book Reviews Department of Philosophy and Religion Appalachian State University 401 Academy Street Boone, NC USA

Martin, Gottfried: Plato s doctrine of ideas [Platons Ideenlehre]. Berlin: Verlag Walter de Gruyter, 1973

Florence Baschet. Titre de l oeuvre : BogenLied. Date : Durée : mn. Commande : Commande l association Cumulus, festival Why Note

1 Objects and Logic. 1. Abstract objects

Incommensurability and the Bonfire of the Meta-Theories: Response to Mizrahi Lydia Patton, Virginia Tech

Mathematical Practice and Conceptual Metaphors: On cognitive studies of historical developments in mathematics

PHIL/HPS Philosophy of Science Fall 2014

Transcription:

Contribution format: symposium Title: SoPhA 2018: contribution submission Continuity, Mathematisation, and Conceptual Change Continuité, mathématisation et changement conceptuel Long anonymous abstract describing each contribution : The main goal of this symposium is to discuss different conceptions of continuity, from Aristotle to the first set-theoretical developments of the notion, both in physics and mathematics. The discussion aims to highlight some aspects of what we take to be the philosophical and scientific depth of the notion of continuity. In particular, the reflexion on continuity will give us the occasion to make two main philosophical points: on the one hand, the mathematisation of the notion of continuity, which made it possible to develop some central empirical concepts in the physics of motion, allows us to argue for the thesis that mathematical language can play a central role in the conceptual elaboration of empirical sciences. On the other hand, the existence of different mathematical notions of continuity offers us direct evidence of cases of incommensurability in mathematics. In this connection, we will discuss the possibility of taking into account the change of meaning of a given term (e.g. continuum ) in the semantic interpretation of our mathematical statements. The whole discussion will also point out two different lines on which the notion of continuity develops through the history of science: namely, a spatial model and a temporal one. The symposium s discussion will be conducted as follows: the first talk analyses Aristotle s notion of continuity as a property of both physical and geometrical objects that cannot be understood in set-theoretical terms. The second presentation takes into account the passage from the geometrisation to the mathematisation of motion, from Galileo to Varignon: in this connection, we will discuss how the mathematisation of the notion of continuity made it possible to develop some central empirical concepts in physics, by focusing on the role of mathematical language within a process of scientific change. Our third talk will analyse Descartes notion of continuity, highlighting how the theoretical force of the concept of continuity is determinant for the development of the Cartesian philosophical and geometric conception of space. The following presentation will deal with the development of a set-theoretical version of the notion of continuity, showing how Dedekind s and Cantor s constructions of the continuum in arithmetical terms can be seen as directly opposed to an Aristotelian, physical understanding of continuity: here the question will be how the change in the extension of of a given mathematical concept may be accepted, and which semantic account for mathematical terms - if any - may allow for that change to be taken into account.

Finally, the last talk will connect the analysis of the Aristotelian notion of continuity with the reflection of the set-theoretical ones discussed, by pointing out the opposition between a temporal and a spatial model of continuity. Building on Hausdorff s work, we will discuss the role played by this opposition in the set-theoretical genesis of topological spaces. The five presentations are interconnected and conceived in an interactive, dialogical way; moreover, a rich general discussion session will follow the talks. i) Aristotelian Continuity The notion of continuity is of fundamental importance for philosophy and mathematics: its long and complex history starts with Aristotle. While he does not invent the term to suneches, he is the one who moves it out of the ontological and cosmological context, and makes of it a technical notion to be used in physical and mathematical inquiry, notably in connection with Zeno s paradoxes of infinite divisibility. Aristotle s codification of continuity is extremely influent, and sets the terms of the inquiry at least until the Early Modern period. Throughout this long history, however, it has usually been assumed that Aristotle s continuity is nothing else than infinite divisibility i.e. what we nowadays call density. Because of this, nowadays Aristotle s account of continuity is often treated as at most an historical curiosity, not really relevant to the contemporary debate regarding the modern, post- Dedekindian notion. This is, I believe, a mistake. A thorough reading of Aristotle s texts (notably the Physics), reveals that the Aristotelian account of continuity is much more sophisticated and interesting than it could seem at first sight, and that it cannot be reduced to the mere infinite divisibility. Aristotle defines the term to suneches (the continuous) twice in the Physics: while it is the definition in terms of infinite divisibility (Ph. VI) that survived through the Middle Ages and the Early Modern period, I believe that the other, more complex formulation (Ph. V.3) is the most important one. This obscure definition does not refer directly to the property of continuity, but defines what it means, for an object, to be continuous to another one: understanding this relation provides the means to have an intuitive grasp on the property of continuity, which is never explicitly defined by Aristotle, but only alluded to. Starting from the definition of the relation given in Ph. V.3, however, it is possible to reconstruct the missing definition of the property of continuity: I will present it, and then analyse its characteristics, that go beyond the mere infinite divisibility. In such a way, it is possible to recover and understand the full powerfulness of Aristotle s account, and to evaluate properly its relation to the contemporary theory of continuity. This means not only to cast light on the similarities and the invariants, but also to properly appreciate its peculiarities and the differences from the contemporary account. Notably, (i) Aristotle s continuity is primarily a physical notion, and only secondarily a mathematical one; (ii) continuity is a property of objects (be them physical or geometrical), and there is nothing like the

abstract object that we now call the continuum ; (iii) what is continuous cannot be composed of or reduced to points: Aristotle s understanding of continuity is not set-theoretical. References J. Barnes (ed.), The Complete Works of Aristotle. The Revised Oxford Translation, Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1984. D. Bostock, Space, Time, Matter, and Form. Essays on Aristotle s Physics, Oxford: OUP, 2006. N. Kretzmann (ed.), Infinity and Continuity in Ancient and Medieval Thought, Londra: Cornell University Press, 1982. A. G. J. Newstead, Aristotle and Modern Mathematical Theories of Continuum, in D. Sfendoni- Mentzou (ed.), Aristotle and Contemporary Science, New York: Lang, 2001; vol. 2, pp. 113-129. M. Panza, «Una stessa cosa». Come intendere la definizione della continuità di Aristotele, Fisica pratiche, 715-728. V.3, 227a10-12, in D. Generali (a cura di), Le radici della razionalità critica: saperi, teleologie. Studi offerti a Fabio Minazzi, vol. II, Milano: Mimesis, 2015, pp. W. D. Ross, Aristotle s Physics. A Revised Text with Introduction and Commentary, Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1936, 1955 2. Richard Sorabji, Time, Creation and the Continuum: Theories in Antiquity and Early Middle Ages, London: Duckworth, 1983. M. J. White, The Continuous and The Discrete, Oxford: OUP, 1992. ii) On the Role of Mathematical Structures in Conceptual Change There is a common idea that mathematical structures are formal languages, and as such, they are supposed to have some kind of representational flexibility and conceptual neutrality, this is, they can be applied to different domains of phenomena and they can express pre-established content without affecting it. In a similar vein, it is widely accepted that mathematics played a central role in the conceptual development of empirical sciences. But this role is far from being fully understood, and it is not clear how it could be explained if we accept the thesis of the conceptual neutrality of mathematical language. I will argue that there is plenty historical evidence against this last thesis, notably, coming from mathematical physics. As various philosophers and historians of science have shown, there are cases in which the very content of empirical concepts of scientific theories is deeply affected by the mathematical structure involved in the theory (see Toulmin 1953, Guisti 1994, Panza 2002, Blay 1992 or Roux 2010). I will analyse of one of these cases in order to argue against the conceptual neutrality of mathematical languages. I will explain the passage from the geometrisation to the mathematisation of motion from Galileo to Varignon, trying to show how the mathematisation of the notion of continuity made it possible to develop some central (empirical) concepts from the physics of motion, notably that of instantaneous velocity.

The main point of this analysis is to show how the use of geometrical methods of representation in physics posited serious constraints to conceptual development and conceptual use to physicists, and how some of these problems were solved when geometry was partially substituted by analytical methods of representation thanks to the development of infinitesimal calculus. References: M. Blay, La Naissance de la mécanique analytique. Presses Universitaires de France, 1992. E. Giusti, Il Filosofo Geometra. Matematica e Filosofia Naturale in Galileo. Nuncius, 9 ( 2 ), 485 498, 1994. M. Panza, Mathematisation of the Science of Motion and the Birth of Analytical Mechanics: A Historiographical Note. In P. Cerrai, P. Freguglia & C. Pellegrini (eds.), The Application of Mathematics to the Sciences of Nature (pp. 253 271). Springer US, 2002. Palmerino, The Geometrization of Motion: Galileo s Triangle of Speed and its Various Transformations. Early Science and Medicine, 15(4-5), 410 447, 2010. S. Roux, Forms of Mathematization (14th-17th Centuries). Early Science and M e d i c i n e, 15(4-5), 319 337, 2010. S. Toulmi, An Introduction to Philosophy of Science. Hutchinson University Press, 1953. iii)continuity in Cartesian Thought: Some Considerations About the Identification Between Extension and Matter in Cartesian Science. In general terms, the notion of continuity is used by Descartes in different parts of his work under different types of analysis, but obeying our own interests, we identify "continuity" with two principles in particular: 1) the identification of the body as a continuous extension and 2) continuity as a geometric property. On the one hand, we have "continuity" as an explanatory condition for physical phenomena and their magnitudes and, on the other hand, we have "continuity" as the property of the geometric space. If matter, according to Descartes, is identified with the property of extension, then matter is space; therefore, it is possible to show how the relationship between physics and geometry is dependent on the demonstration of continuity as a common property. The purpose of this argument is to denote the role of "continuity" in the explanatory process of Cartesian physics (through its theory of matter) and "continuity" in its conception of geometric space that allows us to create the bridge towards a geometric compression of physics. The purpose of our presentation is to emphasize a case where the theoretical force of the concept of "continuity" is determinant for the development of a certain philosophical and geometric conception of space, i.e. continuity as a property in the construction of geometrical forms and as a fundamental property of the composition of the physical world, based on the Cartesian mechanistic analysis of extension and matter. In other words, we will defend the idea that continuity is a theoretical key element for the ontology and metaphysics of Descartes, which has a direct and decisive impact on his conception of geometry and on his views about the composition of the material world and its interrelations.

References : R.Descartes, D. E. Smith, & M. L. Latham, The geometry of René Descartes. New York, N Y : Cosimo Classics, 2007. R.Descartes, Méditations métaphysiques: [avec] objections et réponses suivies de quatre l e t t r e s. Paris: Flammarion, 1992. R. Descartes, & S. Gaukroger, Descartes: The World and Other Writings. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998. D. Rabouin, Mathesis universalis: L'ideěe de "mathématique universelle" d'aristote aě Descartes. Paris: Presses Univ. de France, 2009. S. Maronne, M. Panza, & Université Paris Diderot - Paris 7. La théorie des courbes et des équations dans la géométrie cartésienne: 1637-1661. Lille: Atelier national de Reproduction des Thèses, 2008. M. Panza, Rethinking geometrical exactness. Historia Mathematica, 38, 2011. iv) Continuity and Conceptual Change: Which Semantics for Mathematical Terms? The attention of the philosophical community has frequently been drawn to the fact that cases of conceptual change occur in mathematics (see Gillies 1992). This phenomenon is at work every time that, in the history of the discipline, incompatible descriptions of (what we take to be) the same object arise. However, the possibility of conceptual change (together with the overall attention to the mathematical practice) is often neglected when it comes to formalize the semantics of mathematical theories. We will show how the analysis of the notion(s) of continuity offers us direct evidence of the existence of incommensurability in mathematics. Our main focus will be on Dedekind s definitions of continuity and the real numbers (Dedekind 1872), and on Cantor s analysis of the continuum in terms of infinite point sets (Cantor 1895-97). These constructions of the continuum in arithmetical terms will be seen as directly opposed to an Aristotelian, physical understanding of continuity. The philosophical challenge posed by our case study lies in the question of how we may accept the possibility of the change of meaning of a given mathematical term (e.g. continuum ), or the possibility of a change in the extension of the corresponding concept. In this connection, we will look to the semantics of mathematical terms, and to the ways in which these terms are taken to refer to objects. The problem of constructing a reference theory for mathematical terms that may be adequate to take into account the phenomenon of conceptual change will be approached starting from the assumption that the only epistemic access to mathematical objects that we have is a linguistic access (Azzouni 1997, Shapiro 2011). Buzaglo (2002) s and Hannes Leitgeb (forthcoming) s proposals on these issues will be considered. References : J. Azzouni, Thick Epistemic Access: Distinguishing the Mathematical from the Empirical, Journal of Philosophy 94, 1997, pp. 472-484.

M. Buzaglo, The Logic of Concept Expansion, CUP, Cambridge 2002. G. Cantor, Contributions to the Founding of the Theory of Transfinite Numbers, 1895-97, reprinted in P. Jourdain (Ed.), Contributions to the Founding of the Theory of Transfinite New York, 1915. R. Dedekind, Continuity and Irrational Numbers, 1872, reprinted in W.W. Beman (Ed.), Essays on the Theory of Numbers, Dover, New York 1963. D. Gillies, (Ed.), Revolutions in Mathematics, Clarendon Press, Oxford 1992. H. Leitgeb, The Stability of Beliefs, OUP, forthcoming. S. Shapiro, Epistemology of Mathematics: What Are the Questions? What Count as Answers?, The Philosophical Quarterly 61(242), 2011, pp. 130-150. v) La continuité, entre modèle spatial et temporel Numbers, Dover, Cet exposé s articulera à la fois à celui relatif au continu aristotélicien et à celui développant les perspectives dedekindiennes et cantoriennes. Notre objectif sera de mettre à jour une tension qui parcourt, dès Aristote, les conceptions de la continuité et partage celles-ci en deux modèles distincts : un modèle temporel et un modèle spatial. Cette démarcation entre ces deux lignes de force, et les tentatives de synthèse auxquelles elle a pu donner lieu, scande l évolution de la notion et innerve également les premiers développements ensemblistes (pour lesquels la question du continu, comme problème de cardinalité mais aussi comme problème d une analyse fine de la composition du continu linéaire, est particulièrement prégnante). Nous verrons notamment, avec la prise en compte du cas de Hausdorff et de son exploration axiomatique et relationnelle des concepts de temps et d espace, que cette tension a joué un rôle non négligeable dans la genèse ensembliste des espaces topologiques. Après un retour sur les outils terminologiques élaborés par Aristote et sur son analyse de l infini au livre III de la Physique, nous problématiserons la conception temporelle de la continuité qui se dégage de ces réflexions et l opposerons à un modèle spatial (qui contrevient à la perspective du Stagirite). Nous montrerons ensuite que les premiers développements ensemblistes posent un nouveau cadre d élaboration conceptuelle pour cette problématique classique cadre qui a joué un rôle moteur dans le développement du vocabulaire et des approches topologiques (les espaces topologiques fournissant précisément un biais d étude privilégié pour les applications continues). Indications bibliographiques: Aristote, Physique, Paris : Vrin, 1999. R. Dedekind, Was sind und was sollen die Zahlen?, Braunschweig, Vieweg, 1888. Trad. Les nombres. Que sont-ils et à quoi servent-ils? Publié avec Continuité et nombres irrationnels. Trad. J. Milner & H. Sinaceur. Paris, 1978. G. Cantor, Gesammelte Abhandlungen mathematischen und philosophischen Inhalts, E. Zermelo (éd.), Berlin, Springer, 1932 (rééd., Hildesheim, G. Olms, 1966). F. Hausdorff, Gesammelte Werke, Band IA [Allgemeine Mengenlehre] & Band VII [Philosophisches Werk], Berlin, Springer, 2004 (Band VII) et 2013 (Band IA).