Sight and Sensibility: Evaluating Pictures Mind, Vol April 2008 Mind Association 2008

Similar documents
Categories and Schemata

1/8. The Third Paralogism and the Transcendental Unity of Apperception

Faceted classification as the basis of all information retrieval. A view from the twenty-first century

observation and conceptual interpretation

The Ethical Criticism of Art: A New Mapping of the Territory

McDowell, Demonstrative Concepts, and Nonconceptual Representational Content Wayne Wright

Current Issues in Pictorial Semiotics

Humanities Learning Outcomes

In his essay "Of the Standard of Taste," Hume describes an apparent conflict between two

Emotions from the Perspective of Analytic Aesthetics

Ithaque : Revue de philosophie de l'université de Montréal

Brandom s Reconstructive Rationality. Some Pragmatist Themes

Conclusion. One way of characterizing the project Kant undertakes in the Critique of Pure Reason is by

Review of Carolyn Korsmeyer, Savoring Disgust: The foul and the fair. in aesthetics (Oxford University Press pp (PBK).

1/9. The B-Deduction

TERMS & CONCEPTS. The Critical Analytic Vocabulary of the English Language A GLOSSARY OF CRITICAL THINKING

Dawn M. Phillips The real challenge for an aesthetics of photography

1/10. The A-Deduction

REVIEW ARTICLE IDEAL EMBODIMENT: KANT S THEORY OF SENSIBILITY

PROGRAMME SPECIFICATION FOR M.ST. IN FILM AESTHETICS. 1. Awarding institution/body University of Oxford. 2. Teaching institution University of Oxford

What is the Object of Thinking Differently?

For reference: RUBRIC for STUDENT ESSAYS in Philosophy

Peircean concept of sign. How many concepts of normative sign are needed. How to clarify the meaning of the Peircean concept of sign?

Resemblance Nominalism: A Solution to the Problem of Universals. GONZALO RODRIGUEZ-PEREYRA. Oxford: Clarendon Press, Pp. xii, 238.

Philosophy of Science: The Pragmatic Alternative April 2017 Center for Philosophy of Science University of Pittsburgh ABSTRACTS

Comments on Bence Nanay, Perceptual Content and the Content of Mental Imagery

Felt Evaluations: A Theory of Pleasure and Pain. Bennett Helm (2002) Slides by Jeremiah Tillman

Art and Morality. Sebastian Nye LECTURE 2. Autonomism and Ethicism

Why Pleasure Gains Fifth Rank: Against the Anti-Hedonist Interpretation of the Philebus 1

BOOK REVIEW. William W. Davis

Spectrum inversion as a challenge to intentionalism

Rational Agency and Normative Concepts by Geoffrey Sayre-McCord UNC/Chapel Hill [for discussion at the Research Triangle Ethics Circle] Introduction

Aristotle on the Human Good

Bas C. van Fraassen, Scientific Representation: Paradoxes of Perspective, Oxford University Press, 2008.

Image and Imagination

History Admissions Assessment Specimen Paper Section 1: explained answers

What do our appreciation of tonal music and tea roses, our acquisition of the concepts

6 Bodily Sensations as an Obstacle for Representationism

Dabney Townsend. Hume s Aesthetic Theory: Taste and Sentiment Timothy M. Costelloe Hume Studies Volume XXVIII, Number 1 (April, 2002)

What Can Experimental Philosophy Do? David Chalmers

THESIS MIND AND WORLD IN KANT S THEORY OF SENSATION. Submitted by. Jessica Murski. Department of Philosophy

Intentional approach in film production

SNP Best-set Typesetter Ltd. Article No.: 583 Delivery Date: 31 October 2005 Page Extent: 4 pp

Naïve realism without disjunctivism about experience

Any attempt to revitalize the relationship between rhetoric and ethics is challenged

VISUAL ARTS. Overview. Choice of topic

Aesthetics in Art Education. Antonio Fernetti. East Carolina University

CHAPTER TWO. A brief explanation of the Berger and Luckmann s theory that will be used in this thesis.

Spatial Formations. Installation Art between Image and Stage.

Practical Intuition and Rhetorical Example. Paul Schollmeier

MAURICE MANDELBAUM HISTORY, MAN, & REASON A STUDY IN NINETEENTH-CENTURY THOUGHT THE JOHNS HOPKINS PRESS: BALTIMORE AND LONDON

VISUAL ARTS. The range and suitability of the work submitted:

An autonomist view on the ethical criticism of architecture

A Comprehensive Critical Study of Gadamer s Hermeneutics

UNIT SPECIFICATION FOR EXCHANGE AND STUDY ABROAD

Integration, Ambivalence, and Mental Conflict

Communication Studies Publication details, including instructions for authors and subscription information:

Reading One: Three Couples by Ivy C. Dally

The Nature of Time. Humberto R. Maturana. November 27, 1995.

In Defense of the Contingently Nonconcrete

Mark Scheme (Results) January GCE English Literature Unit 3 (6ET03)

The identity theory of truth and the realm of reference: where Dodd goes wrong

1/10. Berkeley on Abstraction

Interdepartmental Learning Outcomes

Review of David Woodruff Smith and Amie L. Thomasson, eds., Phenomenology and the Philosophy of Mind, 2005, Oxford University Press.

In basic science the percentage of authoritative references decreases as bibliographies become shorter

Kant IV The Analogies The Schematism updated: 2/2/12. Reading: 78-88, In General

Kuhn Formalized. Christian Damböck Institute Vienna Circle University of Vienna

Reviewed by Charles Forceville. University of Amsterdam, Dept. of Media and Culture

CHAPTER IV RETROSPECT

Julie K. Ward. Ancient Philosophy 31 (2011) Mathesis Publications

Articulating Medieval Logic, by Terence Parsons. Oxford: Oxford University Press,

Visual Argumentation in Commercials: the Tulip Test 1

PHIL 480: Seminar in the History of Philosophy Building Moral Character: Neo-Confucianism and Moral Psychology

In The Meaning of Ought, Matthew Chrisman draws on tools from formal semantics,

Thesis-Defense Paper Project Phi 335 Epistemology Jared Bates, Winter 2014

6AANA034 Aesthetics Syllabus Academic year 2016/17. Module description. Assessment methods and deadlines

The topic of this Majors Seminar is Relativism how to formulate it, and how to evaluate arguments for and against it.

Reply to Romero and Soria

A Meta-Theoretical Basis for Design Theory. Dr. Terence Love We-B Centre School of Management Information Systems Edith Cowan University

Philip Kitcher and Gillian Barker, Philosophy of Science: A New Introduction, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2014, pp. 192

Lejaren Hiller. The book written by James Bohn is an extensive study on the life and work of

1/9. Descartes on Simple Ideas (2)

Kuhn s Notion of Scientific Progress. Christian Damböck Institute Vienna Circle University of Vienna

Film-Philosophy

Copyright is owned by the Author of the thesis. Permission is given for a copy to be downloaded by an individual for the purpose of research and

PHI 3240: Philosophy of Art

Natika Newton, Foundations of Understanding. (John Benjamins, 1996). 210 pages, $34.95.

Social Mechanisms and Scientific Realism: Discussion of Mechanistic Explanation in Social Contexts Daniel Little, University of Michigan-Dearborn

What counts as a convincing scientific argument? Are the standards for such evaluation

Exam Revision Paper 1. Advanced English 2018

If Paris is Burning, Who has the Right to Say So?

Zhu Xi's Reading of the Analects: Canon, Commentary, and the Classical Tradition (review)

Student Performance Q&A:

What is Character? David Braun. University of Rochester. In "Demonstratives", David Kaplan argues that indexicals and other expressions have a

A Study of the Bergsonian Notion of <Sensibility>

Action, Criticism & Theory for Music Education

126 BEN JONSON JOURNAL

Western School of Technology and Environmental Science First Quarter Reading Assignment ENGLISH 10 GT

KABARAK UNIVERSITY GUIDELINES TO PREPARING RESEARCH PROPOSAL, THESIS/PROJECT POST GRADUATE STUDENT GUIDE

Transcription:

490 Book Reviews between syntactic identity and semantic identity is broken (this is so despite identity in bare bones content to the extent that bare bones content is only part of the representational system s semantics). In such a case an appeal to the observer s recognitionally keyed concepts cannot explain the difference in the fleshed out content of the two pictures, to the extent that the same concepts apply to both. Obviously there are dimensions of information (some even external to the picture) that ground the contrasting ascriptions of fleshed out content; but what these dimensions of information are and how they are embedded in the system of pictorial representation (controlling to a great extent the system s semantics) is something that a complete account of pictorial representation needs to explain. Having said that, it was the primary aim of On Images to provide a plausible and coherent definition of pictorial representation, a definition that would, further, shed some light on the way in which pictures assume their content (rather than to provide an exhaustive analysis of the process of content ascription) and in this aim the author, I believe, succeeds. To this extent On Images covers significant theoretical ground in the explanation of pictorial representation, which makes this, without a doubt, one of the most valuable and important contributions to the topic. Philosophy Arthur Lewis Building University of Manchester Oxford Road Manchester M13 9PL UK doi:10.1093/mind/fzn064 katerina bantinaki Sight and Sensibility: Evaluating Pictures, by Dominic McIver Lopes. Oxford: Oxford University Press 2005. Pp. x + 210. H/b 30.00. Dominic Lopes s Sight and Sensibility contributes, with originality and sharp argumentation, to a growing interest, within contemporary aesthetics, for questions of value, but with respect to a domain the aesthetic value of pictures that has so far received less attention. Lopes claims two major goals for his book: first, to explain what it is for pictures to elicit experiences of the scenes they depict (p. 11); second, to defend aesthetic interactionism about pictures, a view about how aesthetic and non-aesthetic evaluations of pictures interact (p. 4). The book focuses, not on pictorial art but, more generally, on the evaluation of pictures as pictures, that is, as essentially mimetic. Indeed, throughout Sight and Sensibility, the question of the aesthetic evaluation of pictures and that of the interaction between such an evaluation and evaluations of other sorts are addressed in light of the specific visual experiences that pictures elicit in their viewers.

Book Reviews 491 The first two chapters are dedicated to the puzzle of mimesis, for representational and for expressive properties respectively. What makes the experience of looking at a picture of some scene worth having, while looking at the same scene face to face would not be an equally worthy experience? The answer emerges gradually throughout the book and amounts, ultimately, to spelling out the complexities of what, from Richard Wollheim onwards, has been known as seeing-in (in brief, the experience of seeing in a picture what it depicts, combined with a visual awareness of the picture s surface). In some of the most intriguing pages of this book, Lopes analyses the visual experience of looking at a picture with understanding. After distinguishing the visual awareness of a picture s surface from the visual awareness of a picture s design, he spells out the different ways in which seeing-in combines, in different pictures or parts of a picture, with the other dimensions of pictorial seeing, and especially with design seeing. The result is a helpful taxonomy of types of pictures that is often recalled throughout the text. The solution to the puzzle, then, needs full acknowledgment of seeing-in as a multi-faceted phenomenon (p. 129), one never to be conflated with seeing face to face; and hence of the fact that looking at a picture always differs in important ways from merely looking at the scene the picture depicts. The theoretical analysis is well supplemented by the use of examples. (Indeed, one of the many virtues of this book is that, rather than throwing at the reader a plethora of obscure examples, it concentrates on a few ones, which are revisited from chapter to chapter, enhancing the clarity and unity of the theoretical presentation.) In chapter two, for instance, the discussion of the puzzle of expressive mimesis (where does the value of seeing, say, frustration, in a painting come from, if looking at a scene of frustration face to face would typically not be valuable in the same way?) is conducted mostly by analyzing a drawing by Honoré Daumier, Fatherly Discipline, which depicts a man in the act of punishing his son. After defending a contour theory of pictorial expression (inspired by the contour theories proposed by Peter Kivy and Stephen Davies for musical expression), Lopes makes suggestions on how, in a picture like Daumier s, the picture s expressiveness results not just from the depicted figures and scene but also from the picture s design, as well as from the combination of this with the depicted elements. The discussion of the puzzle of mimesis is also an opportunity for Lopes to investigate how looking at a picture is also always similar to looking at the depicted scene face to face. The two forms of seeing, he contends, share the application of the same visual concept, one that endows the viewer with the capacity to identify the object. Like face to face seeing, seeing an object in a picture depends upon and expresses knowledge of the object s appearance (p. 46). Naturally, the difficult case for a thesis of this sort is the picture of an unfamiliar object, for which no visual concept is available to the viewer. Surprisingly, Lopes dismisses the problem in a few paragraphs. The visual concept of the depicted object, he contends, need not be had beforehand but may be Mind, Vol. 117. 466. April 2008 Mind Association 2008

492 Book Reviews acquired as a result of seeing [the object] in the picture (p. 47). Yet mere appeal to the fact that we can learn of the appearance of an object by looking at a picture of it is no explanation of such a fact. In general, the capacity of seeing an object (in a picture or face to face) may depend on something else, and something less, than the capacity of identifying the object. Perception of an object (in a picture or face to face) may be concept-dependent in a, so to speak, thinner way than assumed by Lopes: not always requiring a visual concept of the object seen, but rather some more generic conceptual apparatus, one compatible with alternative categorizations ( it could be this, it could be that ) and yet one sufficient to grant phenomenological continuity to the experience of seeing the object through the alternative categorizations. Chapter three begins the transition to the question of the interaction between aesthetic value and other types of evaluations, by defining aesthetic value and providing a way to determine when values of other sorts may have aesthetic implications. Lopes defends experience internalism (vs. externalism ), the view that the experience elicited by an object of aesthetic evaluation is part of the evaluation, indeed may sometimes be an evaluation. Specifically, Lopes formulates what he calls the internalist conjecture : of an evaluation (R) of a picture (P), attributing to it a feature (F) deemed to be a merit or demerit, the evaluation is aesthetic if and only if, were R accurate, (1) being F would be a (de)merit in P, all else being equal; (2) a suitable observer s experience, E, of P as F is partly constitutive of (1); and (3) R is an experience with the same content as E or R is a representation [of (de)merit] warranted by E (p. 107). Lopes admits that such a definition is somewhat broad and that more finegrained distinctions are needed to separate properly aesthetic evaluations from purely hedonic ones (such as the evaluation of something as painful). Yet, he thinks that the definition successfully discriminates between undisputed cases of aesthetic evaluation and undisputed cases of non-aesthetic evaluation (p. 110). Doubts arise, however, on whether the internalist conjecture is not too inclusive in some other, more damaging ways. Take a fisherman s evaluation of a fishing rod (an experience or a representation of one) as, say, light (assuming that lightness is a merit in certain kinds of fishing rods). According to the conjecture, the fisherman s evaluation would count as aesthetic in all those instances in which experiencing the rod s lightness is part of what makes the rod s lightness a merit in the rod. By contrast, this would seem an undisputed instance of a non-aesthetic evaluation. Examples involving vision could be found, too: the lenses of a pair of spectacles may be clear, the clearness being a merit in the lenses, and the experiencing of their clearness being in part constitutive of the fact that it is a merit in them. The internalist conjecture provides Lopes with a non-aesthetic aesthetic conversion mechanism (p. 119) that allows him, in chapters four and five, to declare some cognitive evaluations and some moral evaluations, respectively, to be aesthetic as well. The overall strategy is ingenious. Roughly, it consists in spelling out the structure of certain species of cognitive and moral evaluations,

Book Reviews 493 to then show how such a structure matches that of an aesthetic evaluation as per the internalist conjecture. Of course, Lopes continues, not every evaluation is like this. Not just any cognitive merit, for instance, can be converted into an aesthetic merit. A picture may be truthful, but truthfulness converts into an aesthetic merit only when its being a merit partly depends on the response of a suitable observer who sees the picture as truthful. In particular, Lopes claims that the cognitive value of pictures that may count aesthetically is that of fostering and reinforcing some intellectual virtue. One of such virtues is fine observation (some pictures promote delicacy of discrimination, accuracy in seeing, adaptability of seeing, and conceptual revision they help us, that is, to see things in increasingly fine-grained ways, accurately, and under new and even surprising categories). By contrast, other pictures inhibit and weaken fine observation. Amongst the pictures fostering fine observation, some have a cognitive merit of a different, higher kind, although only for some viewers: they do not just foster fine observation, they are experienced as doing so. They have, then, step-up cognitive merit (vs. mere ground-level cognitive merit ). Since being experienced as promoting fine observation is in part what makes the picture s promoting fine observation a merit in it, such a cognitive merit qualifies, as per the internalist conjecture, as not just cognitive but aesthetic as well. The argument is subtle but, perhaps because of the aforementioned excessive inclusiveness of the internalist conjecture, it seems to grant odd consequences. Take a visual puzzle of the sort that can be found in entertainment magazines (e.g. find the error in this picture ): a well-made visual puzzle of this kind fosters fine observation and its doing so is a cognitive merit of the puzzle; furthermore, part of the fact that the picture is cognitively meritorious is that a suitable observer (a visual puzzles lover) would see it as fostering fine observation. According to Lopes, so it seems, this would be an instance of stepup cognitive merit, hence one that has an aesthetic implication. Yet, such pictures are not better or worse aesthetically because of the degree to which they foster fine observation and are experienced as doing so they simply are better or worse visual puzzles. Indeed, an analogous reasoning applies to all sorts of things that have cognitive merit partly because they are experienced as giving cognitively valuable contributions: crossword puzzles, for example, which are cognitively valuable in part because they enrich a person s vocabulary and in part because they are experienced as doing so. In spite of these difficulties, Lopes s discussion of visual examples is quite convincing and it leaves future investigators with the challenge of showing how cognitive merits of pictures can be aesthetically relevant as well. The argument, in chapter five, regarding moral evaluations is analogous to the one regarding cognitive evaluations, but applied to the moral merit of boosting moral sensibility. Incidentally, at one place, Lopes confuses the reader, as he appears to define step-up moral merit in a way that is different from that developed so far and from that needed for the internalist conjucture to apply: a moral merit is a step-up moral merit if part of the boost to moral Mind, Vol. 117. 466. April 2008 Mind Association 2008

494 Book Reviews sensibility comes from a suitable observer s experience of the boost as a merit (p. 181, emphasis added). This is different from defining step-up merit as such that its being a merit partly depends on being experienced by a suitable observer as the feature it is. The discussion is conducted by means of two relatively extended analyses, of illustrations of Dante s Inferno and of Edgar Degas s paintings of female nudes. The former is especially original in showing how some images may succeed ethically, by enhancing the viewer s moral sensibility, in ways that are distinctively pictorial. The latter is a convincing and balanced defense of a moralist critique of the male gaze embodied in some pictures, and yet short of accepting the thesis that all pictorial seeing is a manifestation of the male gaze. Since Lopes s interest is in the aesthetic value of pictures, not on their value as art, the relationship between Sight and Sensibility and the contemporary debates on the relevance to art criticism of cognitive and moral value considerations is doomed to be complex. Yet, in general, there is no doubt that this book brings us closer to the truth regarding an interesting entanglement of questions regarding pictures, their experience, and their values. Department of Philosophy Lafayette College Easton, PA 18042 USA giovannelli@lafayette.edu doi:10.1093/mind/fzn065 alessandro giovannelli The Measure of Mind: Propositional Attitudes and Their Attribution, by Robert J. Matthews. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2007. Pp. x + 248. H/b 30.00. This fascinating book is about propositional attitudes. In it, Robert Matthews pursues, with great rigour and tenacity, the question of how we should understand our practice of attributing propositional attitudes and, in particular, the specific question of how subjects must be built (given the best available accounts of the building materials) if they are to serve as proper targets for that practice. Many philosophers have been struck by the thought that putative assignments of propositions to subjects attitudes are somehow akin to assignments of numbers to their weights. One of Matthews s central aims is to develop that thought into a serious hypothesis. He seeks to use work on the theory of measurement proper as the basis for a (broadly) measurement theoretic (MT) account of our practice of attitude attribution and to provide reasons for thinking that the latter account is adequate to the practice. In so doing, he hopes to present a hypothesis able to challenge (what he thinks of as) the hegemony of (what he refers to as) the Received View (RV, his majusculation).