RESPONSE TO WILLIAM VAN ROO

Similar documents
A Comprehensive Critical Study of Gadamer s Hermeneutics

Action Theory for Creativity and Process

Trinity College Faculty of Divinity in the Toronto School of Theology

RESPONSE AND REJOINDER


UNIT SPECIFICATION FOR EXCHANGE AND STUDY ABROAD

Philosophy Pathways Issue th December 2016

that would join theoretical philosophy (metaphysics) and practical philosophy (ethics)?

Action, Criticism & Theory for Music Education

Truth and Method in Unification Thought: A Preparatory Analysis

PH th Century Philosophy Ryerson University Department of Philosophy Mondays, 3-6pm Fall 2010

PAUL REDDING S CONTINENTAL IDEALISM (AND DELEUZE S CONTINUATION OF THE IDEALIST TRADITION) Sean Bowden

Ithaque : Revue de philosophie de l'université de Montréal

Nature's Perspectives

Art, Vision, and the Necessity of a Post-Analytic Phenomenology

Postmodernism. thus one must review the central tenants of Enlightenment philosophy

None DEREE COLLEGE SYLLABUS FOR: PH 4028 KANT AND GERMAN IDEALISM UK LEVEL 6 UK CREDITS: 15 US CREDITS: 3/0/3. (Updated SPRING 2016) PREREQUISITES:

What do our appreciation of tonal music and tea roses, our acquisition of the concepts

Kant s Critique of Judgment

A Comparison of the Aesthetic Approach of Hans- Georg Gadamer and Hans-Urs von Balthasar

Penultimate Draft- Final version forthcoming in Philosophical Psychology

Edward Winters. Aesthetics and Architecture. London: Continuum, 2007, 179 pp. ISBN

THE STRUCTURALIST MOVEMENT: AN OVERVIEW

HEGEL, ANALYTIC PHILOSOPHY AND THE RETURN OF METAPHYISCS Simon Lumsden


KINDS (NATURAL KINDS VS. HUMAN KINDS)

Owen Barfield. Romanticism Comes of Age and Speaker s Meaning. The Barfield Press, 2007.

Joona Taipale, Phenomenology and Embodiment: Husserl and the Constitution of Subjectivity

H-France Review Volume 15 (2015) Page 1

Philosophical Background to 19 th Century Modernism

Phenomenology Glossary

«Only the revival of Kant's transcendentalism can be an [possible] outlet for contemporary philosophy»

By Tetsushi Hirano. PHENOMENOLOGY at the University College of Dublin on June 21 st 2013)

1/9. The B-Deduction

Heideggerian Ontology: A Philosophic Base for Arts and Humanties Education

Kant Prolegomena to any Future Metaphysics, Preface, excerpts 1 Critique of Pure Reason, excerpts 2 PHIL101 Prof. Oakes updated: 9/19/13 12:13 PM

Necessity in Kant; Subjective and Objective

PH 8122: Topics in Philosophy: Phenomenology and the Problem of Passivity Fall 2013 Thursdays, 6-9 p.m, 440 JORG

Jacek Surzyn University of Silesia Kant s Political Philosophy

Conclusion. One way of characterizing the project Kant undertakes in the Critique of Pure Reason is by

REVIEW ARTICLE IDEAL EMBODIMENT: KANT S THEORY OF SENSIBILITY

The Existential Concept of Freedom for Maxine Greene: The Influence of Sartre and Merleau-Ponty on Greene s Educational Pedagogy

CRITICAL THEORY BEYOND NEGATIVITY

Architecture as the Psyche of a Culture

Mass Communication Theory

The Confluence of Aesthetics and Hermeneutics in Baumgarten, Meier, and Kant

observation and conceptual interpretation

Penultimate draft of a review which will appear in History and Philosophy of. $ ISBN: (hardback); ISBN:

The notion of discourse. CDA Lectures Week 3 Dr. Alfadil Altahir Alfadil

Imagination and Contingency: Overcoming the Problems of Kant s Transcendental Deduction

Major Philosophers II, 460, 3 credits; CRN 3068 Topic for the 2012 Winter Term: Philosophy, Hegel s Phenomenology of Spirit

PH 360 CROSS-CULTURAL PHILOSOPHY IES Abroad Vienna

aggression, hermeneutic motion, hermeneutics, incorporation, restitution, translation, trust

Interdepartmental Learning Outcomes

The Pure Concepts of the Understanding and Synthetic A Priori Cognition: the Problem of Metaphysics in the Critique of Pure Reason and a Solution

An Intense Defence of Gadamer s Significance for Aesthetics

EASTERN INTUITION AND WESTERN COGNITION: WHERE AND HOW DO THEY MEET?

PHIL 415 Continental Philosophy: Key Problems Spring 2013

6AANB th Century Continental Philosophy. Basic information. Module description. Assessment methods and deadlines. Syllabus Academic year 2016/17

THE RELATIONS BETWEEN ETHICS AND ECONOMICS: A COMPARATIVE ANALYSIS BETWEEN AYRES AND WEBER S PERSPECTIVES. By Nuria Toledano and Crispen Karanda

Summary. Key words: identity, temporality, epiphany, subjectivity, sensorial, narrative discourse, sublime, compensatory world, mythos

Principal version published in the University of Innsbruck Bulletin of 4 June 2012, Issue 31, No. 314

1/8. Axioms of Intuition

1. What is Phenomenology?

THE POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY OF G.W.F. HEGEL

Peircean concept of sign. How many concepts of normative sign are needed. How to clarify the meaning of the Peircean concept of sign?

Colloque Écritures: sur les traces de Jack Goody - Lyon, January 2008

BASIC ISSUES IN AESTHETIC

Discourse analysis is an umbrella term for a range of methodological approaches that

Tradition and the Individual Poem: An Inquiry into Anthologies (review)

Hans-Georg Gadamer, Truth and Method, 2d ed. transl. by Joel Weinsheimer and Donald G. Marshall (London : Sheed & Ward, 1989), pp [1960].

Intersubjectivity and Language

Kęstas Kirtiklis Vilnius University Not by Communication Alone: The Importance of Epistemology in the Field of Communication Theory.

9/7/2018. Or this? Or this? LITERARY THEORY PRACTICAL CRITICISM. TEXT-CENTRED CRITIC mediates between individual texts and their readers

Phenomenology and Non-Conceptual Content

Glen Carlson Electronic Media Art + Design, University of Denver

Recommended: Dermot Moran, Introduction to Phenomenology (New York and London: Routledge, 2000).

Categories and Schemata

The Shimer School Core Curriculum

1/8. The Third Paralogism and the Transcendental Unity of Apperception

CHAPTER 2 THEORETICAL FRAMEWORK

Dabney Townsend. Hume s Aesthetic Theory: Taste and Sentiment Timothy M. Costelloe Hume Studies Volume XXVIII, Number 1 (April, 2002)

The Human Intellect: Aristotle s Conception of Νοῦς in his De Anima. Caleb Cohoe

Making Modal Distinctions: Kant on the possible, the actual, and the intuitive understanding.

The Polish Peasant in Europe and America. W. I. Thomas and Florian Znaniecki

Università della Svizzera italiana. Faculty of Communication Sciences. Master of Arts in Philosophy 2017/18

206 Metaphysics. Chapter 21. Universals

Notes on Gadamer, The Relevance of the Beautiful

SOLIPSISM: A PERCEPTUAL STUDY

Logic and the Limits of Philosophy in Kant and Hegel

Verity Harte Plato on Parts and Wholes Clarendon Press, Oxford 2002

When we speak about the theories of understanding and. interpretation in European Continental philosophy we cannot ommit the

Terminology. - Semantics: Relation between signs and the things to which they refer; their denotata, or meaning

Philosophy Department Expanded Course Descriptions Fall, 2007

Embodied music cognition and mediation technology

Communication Studies Publication details, including instructions for authors and subscription information:

scholars have imagined and dealt with religious people s imaginings and dealings

ANALOGY, SCHEMATISM AND THE EXISTENCE OF GOD

SPGR Methods in Christian Spirituality Spring 2016 Session A

Aesthetics and Cognition in Kant s Critical Philosophy

Transcription:

RESPONSE TO WILLIAM VAN ROO I am sure that you are aware how difficult it is to respond to such a comprehensive vision concerning symbol as the one which Professor Van Roo has presented to us. Instead of outlining an all-encompassing, critical interpretation of his paper, which it will surely deserve in its final form as a book, I have decided to note two major areas of agreement, and then to make some methodological remarks concerning the definition of symbol and the place of symbol and sacrament in theological method. One of Van Roo's major arguments may seem a truism to some, but its substance has not always been taken seriously by philosophers and theologians. It asserts the fundamentally imageladen character of human existence. Human temporality is always spatial, essentially dependent upon images (even pictures) in its presencing. Indeed, although I prefer to name those spatial moments "linguistic" (both gestures and speech), Van Roo and I would clearly agree that each temporal moment is a presence of past actualizations and of further possibles (whether of "possible experience" in his formulation, or of a "yet-to-be-spokendiscourse" in my own). This is not uncontroversial since, as Van Roo insists, these spatial moments also inform scientific languages as well. So Mary Hesse can maintain that the "hard" sciences are integrally dependent upon image/model for continuing insight; and Paul Ricoeur can maintain that philosophy and theology require image as a basic internal component. 1 Such a position, of course, seems to require a re-definition of classical metaphysics, or at least its reinterpretation. In religious interpretation and theology, one must learn to redescribe what is frequently claimed to be the non-languageable/non-spatial religious experience of mysticism. As Van Roo states, dreams and mysticism only seem to escape the spatial character of temporality. Secondly, I agree with Van Roo's insistence that the anthropology outlined must be accounted for on all levels: biological, somato-psychological, social, cognitive-epistemological and ontological. This must be so, if one is to take seriously one's own argument about the spatiality of the temporal; but it must be taken 1 For Mary Hesse's recent comments, see The Structure of Scientific Inference (London: Macmillan, 1974), esp. pp. 197-222, and her earlier Models and Analogies in Science (Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 1970). For Ricoeur, see the introduction and conclusion of Symbolism of Evil (Boston: Beacon Press, 1969), pp. 3-18, 347ff. and his "Herméneutique des symboles et reflexion philosophique," (I and II), in Le Conflit des Interprétations, essais d'herméneutique (Paris: Seuil, 1969), pp. 283-329, or his "Philosophy and Religious Language," The Journal of Religion 54 (January, 1974), 71-85. 114

Response to William Van Roo 115 even more seriously by the theologian who claims that theological and religious languages speak not just about a solipsistic internal world of religion, but about the world that religious symbols, not just religious concepts, make comments upon, address themselves to, and claim to transform a public and social discourse. 2 Indeed, symbols are the place in which all these values (motor, psychosomatic, mind-brain, etc.) are articulated, or perhaps better formulated, the place in which such values appear. One must question whether even theologians are converted by or to concepts. The shift invoice in the previous sentence from the passive to the active is also important, since it indicates my first real problem with Van Roo's paper. I shall face that problem through some methodological remarks. In his paper, Professor Van Roo assumes that there is a center of symbol-making activity an identity in which and from which symbols emanate a subject who creates symbols. One marks the entry of the language of imagination and aesthetics. But in the definition which we are given of symbol ("an image which terminates a human operation and communicates the imaged reality"), I suspect that there are two operative notions of creativity and that they are not altogether integrated, perhaps betraying residual elements of their origins. The problem is not so much with the first portion of the definition ("an image which terminates a human operation") although some might have problems with the overtones of "extroversion" in such a phrase; but rather with the second part ("communicates the imaged reality"). For the perennial question is howl and what is being communicated? and to whom? The first set of descriptive phrases used in this connection derives from Suzanne Langer's largely neo-kantian frame of interpretation. There remains in her work a notion that there is some prior mental, conceptual, sometimes simply ideal ("commanding 2 For arguments that foundational theology proceeds in a realm of public warrants, see David Tracy, Blessed Rage for Order (New York: Seabury, 1975). I would argue, as will become clear later in the paper, that one must have a "comparative symbolics," taking seriously the introduction of all linguistic praxis into foundations. It precedes a conceptual systematics, and is fundamentally interdisciplinary, discerning the way in which symbol-systems have in fact interacted or do at present interact at various cultural or cross-cultural junctures. Such a fundamentally dialectical operation must occur in the theologian as well, thus addressing the question of the inclusion of the present religious praxis of the interpreter in the operative moments of the discipline. Just as "self-appropriation" occurs in philosophy as an integral moment, so too in theology, the "basic trust" of the theologian in his symbols must not be excluded in the exercise of theological method. However, such faith in the symbols of one's religious discourse is not an uncritical predisposition, but a dialectically mediated experience and thematization.

116 Response to William Van Roo 116 form") "within," which is then executed "without," outside the creator. 3 Values conceived internally are articulated in the visible the passive voice. The created object is an instrument of a concept or idea; the spatiality of the moment seems sometimes, though not always, secondary to an a-spatial temporality. On the other hand, if one sees symbol through the eyes of Merleau-Ponty, both figure and ground are simultaneous in perception, execution, and re-perception. 4 The one is only discovered in the other. In the figure, both figure and ground appear. The created object is not an instrument of the already constituting or constituted subject; the object is a moment of self-constitution and its presence. Only in the object perceived (the intentionality of world) can the subject achieve itself or appear an active voice. These can produce two quite different notions of creativity and subject-object relation and interpretation. It seems to me that the notion originating in Merleau-Ponty takes more seriously the spatiality of the temporal, a judgment which would need to be argued at length elsewhere. There seem to be two reasons for this splicing together of notions of symbol: the first is due to the fact that Langer's investigations of the creation of art-symbols are more extensive, and thus in some ways more useful for speaking about creativity and the voluntary relation between subject and object. The second is methodological and derives from the origin of Van Roo's project, stated in the opening lines of his paper. He wishes to establish an anthropology which frames and understands the Christian Sacrament. 5 And interestingly enough, the neo-kantian categories 3 Although Susanne Langer wishes to distinguish herself from both Kant and neo-kantian philosophy, and in a certain sense does just that by her emphasis on symbol, nonetheless the epistemological basis of her position remains largely Kantian in my opinion. See Susanne Langer, Feeling and Form: a Theory of Art (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1967), esp. pp. 26, 27, 372, 389. See also her Philosophy in a New Key: a Study in the Symbolism of Reason, Rite, and Art (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1969). For William Van Roo's descriptive exposition of Cassirer and Langer, see "Symbol according to Cassirer and Langer," Gregorianum 53 (1972), 487-530, 615-73. Van Roo criticizes Langer's theory of art symbol as "severely abstract" in an article entitled "Symbol in Art and Sacrament," in StudiaAnselmiana: Symbolisme et Théologie, Sacramentum 2 (Roma: Editrice Anselmiana, 1974), p. 167. Considering the fact that one of the major philosophers studying symbol is a woman, I should have preferred that the text of Van Roo's paper register attention to its exclusively male gender references, so that the experience of women might be more clearly included in the discussion of symbol. 4See especially, Maurice Merleau-Ponty, Signs, trans, by Richard C. McCleary (Evanston: Northwestern University Press, 1964), pp. 42, 54-5, 83; and his Visible and Invisible, trans, by Alphonso Lingis (Evanston: Northwestern University Press, 1968), pp. 35-49, 95-104. 6See the article cited in fn. 3 of this paper for a broader analogy traced by Van Roo. There are several other attempts to accomplish the same analogy, some

Response to William Van Roo 117 of Langer offer a clearer link than the phenomenological ones of Merleau-Ponty. Why is this so? I shall indicate only the barest outline of a response. One of Van Roo's primary emphases in his notion of symbol is its "inter-subjective" context. And in spite of Langer's avowal that the "work" is in the end autonomous of its "author," the description of creativity which she offers speaks of "schemata," "forms," concepts, ideas all of which reside in and define an epistemological subject. 6 For Christian sacraments, one needs a clearly defined subject. In the final analysis, sacraments are prayer and prayer is directed discourse not the language of commentary in the third person (he, she, it, they), but a first (I, we) and second (You) person language. It is not only a language directed to other members within the same social frame but it maintains that it is a language which addresses God. Indeed, it seems that all third person language (narrative, parable, etc.) was originally born within the language of directed discourse. 7 If one wishes to define symbol in this context, then, it is clear that all language about God was first of all, language directed to God. 8 Moreover, religious symbols claim that in their working, God directs himself to human beings. They claim a reciprocal dative of presence. This discussion in my opinion, places prayer and the sacraments at the very center of the arguments about the nature of foundational theology. 9 The question of intersubjectivity, therefore, which Professor Van Roo stresses as a component in the nature of symbol must be recognized both as a direct reflection upon Christian sacraments, undergoing the same criticism as the paper under consideration here. See, for example, J. A. Appleyard, "How does a Sacrament 'Cause by Signifying'?" Science et Esprit 23 (1971), 167-99 and J. R. Barth, "Symbol as Sacrament in Coleridge's Thought," Studies in Romanticism 11 (Fall, 1972), 320-31. 6 See Susanne Langer, Feeling and Form (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1967), p. 394., 7 There is, of course, some dissent from this position about the relation ot ritual and myth; see for example, G. S. Kirk, Myth Its Meaning and Functions in Ancient and Other Cultures (Berkeley: Cambridge University Press, 1974), pp. 8William James quotes Sabatier with approval: "It is prayer that distinguishes the religious phenomenon from such similar and neighboring phenomena as purely moral or aesthetic sentiment." And James continues: "The genuineness of religion is thus indissolubly bound up with the question whether the prayerful consciousness be or be not deceitful." Varieties of Religious Experience (New York: Collier, 1961), pp. 361-2. 9 It strikes this author that such an assertion is simply to take all torms ot religious language as data for reflection and explication. It also recognizes that gestures as well as speech (the praxis of the community, therefore) deserve inclusion at the foundational level of theology. They are not simply an application of doctrine or an instrument of some interior and a-spatial temporality.

118 Response to William Van Roo 118 and a correction of types of post-kantian aesthetics and/or hermeneutics which neglect or dismiss the question of the subjectmaker of symbols or the subject-participant in symbols. Thus, although I do not prefer the heavily neo-kantian formulations 10 of creativity which are Susanne Langer's, the use of her thought in this context raises an important hermeneutic and methodological issue. Can the examination of symbol or of sacrament do without a language which directly accounts for and thematizes subjectivity and inter-subjectivity? There are two historical notes to this discussion: (1) much of the submergence of the subject in criticism, literary, aesthetic and philosophical is a residue of philosophical issues precipitated by and seemingly unresolved in Kant's Critiques, and the question must be faced where it emerged in the "transcendental unity of apperception"; and (2) many of the issues which we now discuss were previously 11 treated in the early post-kantian context, frequently in explicitly theological contexts, for example, by Coleridge on imagination and perception in the English-language world, and by Schelling on the function of myth and poesy in religion in the German-language world. 12 Van Roo's paper therefore raises some substantive theological issues: (1) one must re-think the concrete and integral relation between images and concepts, symbols and theories in ontology and theological method; (2) one ought to face the fact that the language of symbol, if it is to be successful, must not hastily engraft 10For example, in the recently published lectures of 1973, Interpretation Theory: Discourse and the Surplus of Meaning (Fort Worth, Texas: Texas Christian University Press, 1976), Paul Ricoeur stresses the "event"-transience of the speaker-discourse relation (pp. 12-3). The Ego as determinative of meaning in utterance becomes the self as determined in discourse (pp. 89-95). The relation between the two is unclear. Although I am no more interested than Ricoeur in re-asserting a "psychologizing hermeneutic" (p. 23), I would argue that the theory of interpretation, denunciated in the text, a theory which does not account for this relationship, cannot be applied too well to the language of sacraments and prayer in religious discourse. The discussion of rhetoric in La Métaphore Vive (Paris: Seuil, 1975), pp. 13-86, 173-220, mines the same vein. The theory's usefulness in philosophy of aesthetics must also be questioned. "Immanuel Kant, Critique of Pure Reason, trans, by N. K. Smith (New York: St. Martin's Press, 1965), pp. 135-61(A/B), 155, 168ff., 109ff., 237, 369ff., 376-7. 12Much of Coleridge's speculation remains unpublished; for two excellent studies, see Thomas McFarland, Coleridge and the Pantheist Tradition (London: Clarendon Press, 1969) and Stephen Prickett, Romanticism and Religion. The Tradition of Coleridge and Wordsworth in the Victorian Church (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1976), and the more limited investigation of J. R. Barth, The Symbolic Imagination: Coleridge and the Romantic Tradition (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1977). On Schelling, see Xavier Tilliette, Schelling: Une Philosophie en devenir, 2 vols. (Paris: Librarie philosophique J. Vrin, 1970).

Response to William Van Roo 119 itself to branches of post-kantian or neo-kantian aesthetics without some further investigation; (3) one should re-include the spatiality of conversion, namely the sacraments, in the discussion of the nature of foundational theology, thus taking seriously the second person language of prayer as a primal religious language; and (4) if the process is truly dialectical, one will, in turn accomplish two things: (a) one will address the significant criticism of a Jacques Derrida, for example, on the very nature of language itself and the relation between speaker and sign: 13 and (b) one may be able to redefine the nature of aesthetics, without lapsing into the seemingly subjectivist failures of "romantic" hermeneutics. 14 After all, as Coleridge once maintained, "it is by Symbols alone that we can acquire intellectual knowledge of the Divine." 15 STEPHEN HAPPEL The Catholic University of America Washington, DC 1 3 See both his Speech and Phenomena and other Essays on Husserl's Theory of Signs, trans, by D. B. Allison (Evanston: Northwestern University Press, 1973) and "la mythologie blanche, la metaphore dans le texte philosophique," reprinted in Marges de la philosophic (Paris: Minuit, 1972), pp. 247-324. 1 4 See the critique and reconstruction of H.-G. Gadamer, Truth and Method (New York: Seabury, 1975), pp. 153-92, 345-447. 15Unpublished Huntingdon Library MS. HM 17299, fol. 85 (1825-26).